October 11, 2022 | Author: Anonymous | Category: N/A
Download Why It Is Better Never To Come Into Existence - David Benatar...
North
merican Philosophical Philosophical Publications
Why It Is Better Never to Come into Existence Author(s): David Benatar Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 34, No. 3 (Jul., 1997), pp. 345-355 Published by: University of Illinois Press on behalf of the North American Philosophical Publications Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20009904 Accessed: 03-07-2018 21:11 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms
University of Illinois Press, North American Philosophical Publications are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly
This content downloaded from 129.1.11.117 on Tue, 03 Jul 2018 21:11:26 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Philosophical Quarterly Volume 34, Number 3, July 1997
WHY IT ISINTO BETTER NEVER TO COME EXISTENCE David Benatar I
years of frailty. We all face death.1 We infrequently contemplate the harms that
A here is a common assumption in the await any new-born child: pain, disappoint? literature about future possible people that, ment, anxiety, grief and death. For any all things being equal, one does no wrong given child we cannot predict what form by bringing into existence people whose these harms will take or how severe they lives will be good on balance. This as? will be, but we can be sure that at least sumption rests on another, namely that some of them will occur. (Only the prema? being brought into existence (with decent turely deceased are spared some but not life prospects) is a benefit (even though the last.) None of this befalls the non? not being born is not a harm). All this is existent. Only existers suffer harm. assumed without argument. I wish to ar? Of course I have not told the whole story.
gue that the underlying assumption is Not only bad things but also good things
erroneous. Being brought into existence is happen only to those who exist. Pleasures, not a benefit but always a harm. Many joys, and satisfaction can be had only by
people will find this deeply unsettling claim to be counter-intuitive and will wish existers. Thus, thepleasures cheerfulof will say, we must weigh up the life against to dismiss it. For this reason, I propose the evils. As long as the former outweigh not only to defend the claim, but also to the latter, the life li fe is worth living. Coming suggest why people might be resistant to it. into being with such a life is, on this view,
II
a benefit. How ever, this conclusion does not fol?
As a matter of empirical fact, bad things low. This is because there is a crucial happen to all of us. No life is without hard? difference between harms and benefits ship. It is easy to think of the millions who which m akes the advantages of existence
-existence2 nce2 hollow but the disad? live a life of poverty or of those who live over non -existe much of their lives with some disability. vantages real. Consider pains and pleasures Some of us are lucky enough to be spared as exemplars of h arms an d benefits. It iiss these fates, but most of us who do none? uncontroversial to say that:
theless suffer ill-health at some stage 1) the presence of pain is bad during our lives. Often the suffering is ex? and that
cruciating, even if it is only in our final days. Some are condemned by nature to 2) the presence of pleasure is good.
3 4 5
This content downloaded from 129.1.11.117 on Tue, 03 Jul 2018 21:11:26 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
346 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
However, such a symmetrical evaluation However, even of those who do think does not apply to the absence of pain and that we have positive duties only a few pleasure, for: also think that amongst these is a duty 3) the absence of pain is good, even if that good is not enjoyed by anyone,
whereas 4) the absence of pleasure is not bad un less there is somebody somebody for w hom this ab? sence is a deprivation.
M y view about tthe he asymmetry between 3) and 4) is widely widely shared. A num ber of reasons can be advanced to support this. First, this view is the best explanation for the commonly held view that while there is a duty to avoid bringing suffering people
into existence, there is no duty to bring happy people into being. In other word s, the reason why w e think that there is a duty not to bring suffering people into existence existence is that the presence of this suffering w ould
to bring happy peop le into existence. For this reason, my ex planation is preferable to the alternative.
A second suppor supportt for my cla claim im about the
asymm etry between 3) and 4) is tthat, hat,
wher eas it seems strange to give as a rea? son for having a child that the child one has will thereby be benefited, sometimes we do avoid bringing a child into exist?
ence b ecause of the potential child's child's interests. If If having children w ere done for
the purpose of thereby benefiting those
children, then there would be greater moral
reason for at least many people to have
m ore children. In contrast to this, our con?
cern for the welfare of p otential chil children dren
who would suffer is taken to be a sound
ing). In contrast to this, we think that there
basis for deciding not to h ave the child. If absent pleasures were bad irrespective of whether they w ere bad for anybody, then having children for their own sakes would not seem odd. A nd if it were not the case
is no duty to bring happ y people into ex?
that absent pains are good even where they
istence because, while their pleasure would
are not good for anybody , then we could
be bad (for the sufferers) and the absence of the suffering is good (even though there
is nobody to enjoy the absence of suffer?
be good, its absence would not be b ad
(given that there would be nobody who would be dep rived of it). It might b e objected that there is an al?
ternative explanation for the view about our
procreational duties, one that does not ap?
peal to my claim claim about the asym metry
between 3) and 4). It might be suggested
that the reason why w e have a duty to avoid
bringing suffering people into being, but not a duty to bring hap py people into ex? istence, is that we have negative duties to
not say that it would be good to avoid bringing suffering children into existence.
Finally, support for my claim can be
drawn from a related asymm asymm etry, this time time
in our retrospective judgments. Bringing people into existence as w ell as faili failing ng to bring people into existence can be regr et? ted. However, only bringing people into existence can be regretted for the sake of the person whose existence was contingent on our decision. One migh t grieve about not having had children, but not because
avoid harm, but no corresponding positive duties to bring about happiness. Judgm ents about our p rocreational duties are thus like judgmen ts about all ot other her duties. Now for those who deny that w e have any positive duties, this would indeed be an alternative
explanation to the one I have provided.
the children which one could have had have
been deprived of existence. Remorse about not having children is remorse for ourselves,
sorrow about having missed child-bearing and child-rearing experiences. However, we do regret having brou ght into existence a child with an unhapp y life, and we regret
This content downloaded from 129.1.11.117 on Tue, 03 Jul 2018 21:11:26 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
WHY IS IT BETTER NEVER TO COME INTO EXISTENCE / 347 it for the child's sake, even if also for our
and one (B) in w hich X nev er exists. This, already ady m entioned entioned,, own sakes. The reason why we do not la? along with the views alre ment our failure to bring somebody into can be represented diagramaticall diagramatically: y:
existence is because absent pleasures are not bad. I realize that the judgm judgm ents that underlie this asymmetry are not universally shared.
For exam ple, positive util utilitaria itarians ns ? w ho
are interested not only in minim izing izing pain
but also in maxim izing pleasure ? would tend to lamen t the absence of additional possible pleasure pleasure even if there were no? body deprived of that pleas pleasure. ure. On their view there is a duty to bring people into existence if that would increase utility. Usually this would be manifest as a duty to bring happy people into existence. How? ever, under certain circumstances the duty
could be to bring a suffering person in to being if that w ould lead to a net increase of happiness, by ben efiting others. This is not to say that all positive utilitarians must reject the view about the asymmetry of 3) and 4). Positive utilitarians who are sympathetic to the asymm etry could draw
a distinction between (i) promoting the
happiness of people (that exist, or will ex?
ist independently of one's choices) and
(ii)) increasing happiness by m aking (ii
people. They could then, consistent with positive utiliarianism, judge only (i) to be a requirement of m orality. This is tthe he pref? erable version of positive utilitarianism. If
one took (ii) also to be a requirement of
Scenario A
Scenario B
(X exists)
(X never exists)
3 3))
1 Presence of Pain
Absence of Pain
(Bad)