Proofs From The Book
October 9, 2022 | Author: Anonymous | Category: N/A
Short Description
Download Proofs From The Book...
Description
Martin Aigner Giinter M. Ziegler
Proofs from THE BOOK Third Edition With 250 Figures Including Illustrations by Karl H. Hofmann
Springer
Preface
Paul Erd˝os
VIII
Table of Contents
Cornbinatorics
137
22 . Pigeon-hole and double counting . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .139 23 . Thre 63Lamousg
..........................
Six proofs of the infinity of primes
5
8
Bertrand's postulate
Leg ndre's The number
theorem
10
Bertrand's
12
Bertrand's postu40.036
Binomial coefficients are (almost) never powers
There is an epilogue to Bertrand's postulate which leads to a beautiful result on binomial coefficients.
Binomial coeflicients are (almost)never powers So for each i the number of multiples of pi among n, . . . , n-k+1, and hence among the aj9s,is bounded by 1sJ
15
<
16
Binomial coefficientsare (almost)never uowers Now since mi
<
18
Representing numbers as sums of two squares 0
x
Representing numbers as sums of two squares
20 Proof. We study the set
This set is 208sinite.This Indeed,oof.
24
Every finite division ring
EveryJinite
26
Every finite division ring is afield we find
k
By assumption, all ao, . . .
29
Some irrational numbers
and this is approximately (-I)"+'
E. More precisely: for 29
30
Some irrational numbers where for r
> 0 thTm(where )Tj01.6207 0 Td(denominator )Tj/T1_0 1 Tf0.
31
Some irrational numbers
F ( x ) may also be written as an infinite sum F(x)
=
s2" f ( x ) - sZn-' f l ( x )
since the higher derivatives
+s
~ f U ~( x )7- . . .~,
n)
32
Some irrational numbers
integral of a function that is positive (except on the boundary). However, < 1, then from part (ii) of the lemma we if we choose n so large that obtain
a contradiction. Here comes our final irrationality result.
Theorem 3. For every odd integer n 2 3, the number 1
Some irrational numbers
is rational (with integers k , 4 > 0). Then
33
Three times 7r2/6
36 This evaluation
Three times n 2 16
37
This proof extracted the value of Euler's series from an integral via a rather simple coordinate transformation. An ingenious proof of this type - with an entirely non-trivial coordinate transformation - was later discovered by Beukers, Calabi and Kolk. The point of departure for that proof is to split $ int4(p18(the )11(even )-4(terms )3(and )6(the )]TJ0.03951 Tc 11.7473 0 Td(odd )Tj0.0132 Tc 1.8695 the sum
38
Three times .ir2 16 Beautiful
Form = l , 2 , 3 this yields cot2 =
5 ; =2 cot2 ;+ cot2 cot2 $ + cot2 + cot2
=5
-
Three times 7r2 16
Three times r216
40
This is very easy with the technique of "comparing with an integral" that we have reviewed already in the appendix to Chapter 2 (page 10). It yields
for an upper bound and
for a lower bound on the "remaining summands"
if you are willing to do a slightly more
-
or even
Three times n2/6
4
42
Three times n216
References [I] K . BALL& T. RIVOAL:
Hilbert 's third problem:
Hilbert's third problem: decomposinn polyhedra
48
Proof. The
Lines in the plane and decompositions of graphs
Perhaps the best-known problem on configurations of lines was raised by Sylvester in 1893 in a column of mathematical problems. QUESTION8 FOR SOLUTION.
11851. (Professor SYLFEBTEH.)-Provethat it is not poaaible to
a m n g c any finite number of real point8 EO that a right line. through every two of them shall pas8 through third, unless they
54
Lines in the plane, and decompositions of graphs
and x' are contained in precisely one set
55
56
A graph G with 7 vertices and 11 edges. It has one loop, one double edge and one triple edge.
The complete graphs K , on n vertices and (); edges
The
Lines in the plane, and decompositions o f graphs
Lines in the plane, and decompositions o f graphs
57
u'
The paths
The slope problem
Try for yourself -
Chapter 10
The slope uroblem
61
62
The slope problem
is crossing of order d
A touching move
An ordinary move
Three applications of Euler's formula
Chapter 11
.4 graph isplonar if it can be drawn in th515956n7llane
gW2
66
Three applications of Euler's formula Euler's formula thus produces a strong numerical conclusion from a geometric-topological the
The five platonic solids
Here the degree is written next to each vertex. Counting the vertices of given 1, degree yields n2 = 3, n s = 0, n4 n s = 2.
The number of sides is written into each region. Counting the faces with a given 3, number of sides yields fl = 1, f2
andf,=0otherwis.
1,f9=1,
f4=
Three a~nlicationso f Euler's formula
Let us deduce from this - together with Euler's formula- quickly that the complete graph K g and the complete bipartite graph K3,3are not planar. 5 For a hypothetical plane drawing of K5 we calculate
67
Sylveste475
70
Three applications of Euler's formula
Lattice bases A basis
72
Cauchy's rigidity theorem Now we mark by
+ the angles of Q for which the corresponding angle
73
Cauchv's ripidin theorem
>
Now let n 4. If for any i E ( 2 , . . . , n corresponding vertex can be cut off by c
-
1) we have ai = a : , then the u t
Touching simplices
Chapter 13
How many d-dimensional simplices can be positioned in Rdso that they touch pairwise, that is, so that thatpaim(so )TjETEMC BT/T1_1 1 Tf0.0128 Tc 9.75 0 0 10.25 281.27969 476
t1
Touching simplices
Proof. For d = 2 the family of four triangles that we had considered does have such a transversal line. Now consider any d-dimensional configuration of touching simplices that has a transversal line k'. Any nearby parallel line e' is a transversal line as well. and
Touching simplices In contrast to this exponential lower bound, tight upper bounds are harder to get. A naive inductive argument (considering all the facet hyperplanes in
77
78
The first row of the C-matrix represents the shaded triangle, while the second row corresponds to an empty intersection of
Touchina simulices
80 Every large point set has
Every large point set has an obtuse angle
This correspondence is illustrated by the sketch in the margin. Furthermore, from
81
83
Evew laree voint set has an obtuse anale We have sete aboe
thata
n
l
l
84 84
Borsuk's conjecture
Karol Borsuk's paper "Three theorems on the n-dimensional euclidean sphere" from on
Borsuk's conjecture
87
(3) From R, we obtain the set of points in R(;) whose coordinates are the subdiagonal entries of the corresponding matrices:
S
:= { ( z x ~ ) ~ , ~
Borsuk's coniecture
Claim 4. There is
89
90
Borsuk's conjecture To obtain a general bound for large d, we use monotonicity and unimodality of the binomial coefficients and the estimates n! > e(:)" and n! < en(:)" (see the appendix to Chapter 2) and derive
95
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
How do we obtain this sequence, and hence the Calkin-Wilf listing of the positive fractions? Consider the infinite binary tree in the margin. We immediately note its recursive rule: is on top of the tree, and every node 4 has two sons: the left son is 3
& and the right son is y. 1 -
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
96 To
Sets, jitnctions, and the continuum hypothesis
So how does one get from one rational to the next? To answer this, we first
97
98
Sets. functions. and the continuum hv~othesis
Let us move on to the real numbers R. Are they still countable? No,44(98(th
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis Next we find that any two intervals (of finite length > 0) have equal size by considering the central projection as in the figure. Even more is true: Every interval (of length
99
100
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
Now we are faced with a basic problem. We would certainly like to have that the usual laws concerning inequalities also hold for cardinal numbers. n, But is this true for infinite cardinals? In particular, is it true that m n 5 m imply m = n? This
<
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
(Case 2), it may stop in an element of A l that does not lie
101
102
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
As a corollary to N o 5 m for any infinite cardinal m, we can immediately prove "Hilbert's hotel" for any infinite cardinal number m, that is, we have With this we have also proved a result
1M
U
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis Very shortly afterwards Erdos showed that, surprisingly, the answer depends on the continuum hypothesis.
Theorem 5. Ifc > N1, then evVery
103
104
"A legend talks about St. Augustin who, walking along the seashore and contemplating injinitj, saw a child trying to empty the
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
Sets, ,functions, and the continuum hypothesis
-
p :N subset U
P ( A f ) is a bijection of N
C N of all
bl onto P ( M ) . Consider the
105
106
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis number a. Indeed, if the infinite well-ordered set M has ordinal 6 ber
set element
Sets, functions, and the continuum hypothesis
What we finally need is a considerable strenghthesning
107
In praise of inequalities
Analysis abounds with inequalities, as witnessed for example by the famous book "Inequalities" by Hardy, Littlewood and
110
In praise of ine~ualities
For n = 2, we have ala2 5 (%jQ)2
(a1 - ~
2
)
~
In praise of inequalities
where the left-hand side equals
while the right-hand side is
6
We conclude integrals in ( I )
-
1
2 0, which is A 2 G. In the case of equality, all
111
In praise of inequalities
Second proof. The following proof of Theorem 3, using the inequality of the arithmetic and the geometric mean, is a
115
118
A theorem of Po'lya on polynomials
120 which means that It
122
A theorem of Pdlya on polynomials Equating the real parts in (4) and ( 5 ) we obtain by
125
On a lemma of Littlewood and Offord
and an easy calculation shows that the first sum adds the k and the second sum the largest k binomial coefficients
+ 1 largest
126
On a lemma ofLittlewood and
128
Cotangent and the Herglotz
Addition theorems: sin(x t y) = sin cos(x y) = cos
+
sn(x+)= X ); =
+
y
+ cos -
sin
- sinx
= 2sin$cosI
5.
y y
Cotangent and the
130
Cotangent and the Herglotz trick
So to finish our story let us see how Euler
Cotangent and the Herglotz trick
From
we obtain by comparing coefficients for z n :
We may compute the Bernoulli numbers recursively
131
Buffon's needle problem
Buffon's needle problem
135
The circle can be approximated by polygons. Just imagine that together with the circular needle C we are dropping an inscribed polygon as well a46 25(a6 22(circumscribed )-62ed )-118(polyg/T1_0 1 Tf0.0667 Tc 11.211.75 0 01211149.5195 556.32019 Tm(Pn
Pigeon-hole and double counting
Some mathematical principles, such as the two in the title of this chapter, are so obvious that you might think they would only produce equally obvious results. To convince you that "It ain't necessarily so" we illustrate them with examples that were by Paul
Chapter 22
142
Pigeon-hole and double counting
For the proof we set N = { 0 , 1 , . . . , n} and R = { 0 , 1 , . . . , n sider the map f : N +
-
1). Con-
Pigeon-hole and double counting
144
Pigeon-hole and double counting ois n o this section the following beautiful application to an extremal problem on graphs. Here is the problem: length G = (V,E ) has n vertices and contains no cycle of Suppose 4 (denoted by C4), that
Pigeon-hole and double counting
Theorem. Ifthe graph G on n vertices contains no 4-cycles, then
For n = 5 this gives JEl 5 6, and the
145
146
Pigeon-hole and double counting
i
Pigeon-hole and double counting
From linear algebra we know that the trace equals the sum of the e5values. And here comes the trick: While
147
148
Pigeon-hole and double counting
We discuss Sperner's lemma, and Brouwer's theorem as a consequence, for the first interesting case, that of dimension n = 2. The reader
152
Threefamous theorems onJinite sets Tw
Three famous theorems on finite sets
As we mentioned, Hall's theorem was the beginning of the now vast field of matching theory [6]. Of the many variants and ramifications let us state one particularly appealing result which the reader is invited to prove for himself: Suppose the sets A l . . . . , A,
155
158
Shufflingcards
than which is smaller than for n = 23 (this is the paradox"!), less 9 percent for n = 42, and exactly 0 for n > 365 (the "pigeon-hole principle," see Chapter 22). The formula is easy to see - if we take the persons in some fixed order: If in
where at the end we sum a geometric series (see page 28).
Shuffling cards
Indeed, if Ai denotes the event that the ball i is not drawn in the first m drawings, then rob [v,>
159
160
Shufling cards
Two
Shufflingcards
Let T be the number 3161
161
162
Shufflingcards
and we have seen that Prob[Ti - T,-1 for
= j] =
Prob[V,-i+l
-
Vn-i
= j]
163
Shuffling cards
>
+
0 and k := [nlog n cnl . Then after peiforming k top-in-at-random shuffles on a deck qf n cards, the variation distance,from the uniform distribution satisjies
Theorem 1. Let c
One can also verify that the variation distance d ( k ) stays large if we do significantly fewer than n log n top-in-at-random shuffles. The reason is that a smaller number of shuffles will not suffice to destroy the relative ordering on the lowest few cards in the deck. Of course, top-in-at-random shuffles are extremely ineffective - with the
164
Shuflinn cards Bell Labs "Mathematics of Communication" department at the time), has several virtues: 0 it is elegant, simple, and ca3ms natural, 0 it models quite well the way an amateur would perform riffle shuffles, a and we have a chance to analyze it. Here are three descriptions - all of them describe the
Lattice paths
168
Lattice paths and determinants and the weight of the path system 'P,
Lattice paths and determinants
Proof. A typical summand of det(A1) is sign a r n ~ , ( ~. .j . rn,,(,), which can be written as
Summing over a
169
170
Lattice paths and determinants
Theorem. If P is an ( r x
171
Lattice paths and determinants
Now look at the figure to the right, where A, is placed at the point (0, - a i ) and B, at ( b j , - b j ) . The number of paths from Ai to B, in this onlygrid steps thatto the use ( b 3 + (b, " ' p b ~north )) = and other east In is, by what we just proved, words, the matrix of binomials Af is precisely the path frommatrix A to B in thegraph directed for which lattice all edges have weight A
(z;).
172
Lattice paths and determinants
References [ I ] I. M. GESSEL&
Cayley's formula for the number of trees
Chapter 26
One of the most beautiful formulas in enumerative combinatorics concerns the number of labeled trees. Consider the set N = {1,2, . . . ,n). How many different trees can we form on this vertex set? Let us denote this number by Enumeration "by hand" yields TI = 1, = 1, = 3, T4 = 16, with the trees shown in the following table:
T,.
T2
T3
174
T2 1 1 L
The four trees of
Cavlev's formula for the number o f trees
Cayley's
176
Cayley's formula for the number of trees
1 Third proof (Recursion). Another classical method in enumerative combinatorics is to establish a recurrence relation and to solve it by induction. The following idea is essentially due to Riordan and RCnyi. To find the proper recursion, we consider a
Cayley'sformula for the number of trees
177
178
Cavlev's formula for the number o f trees
Completing Latin squares
Comnletinp Latin sauares 4
181
184
Completing Latin squares
In our example the "exchange case" happens for k = 5: the element x5 = 3 does already occur in the last column, so that entry has to be moved back to column k = 5. But the exchange element xk = 6 is not new either, it is exchanged by x:
186
The
The Dinitz ~ r o b l e m
188
The Dinitz uroblem
Now we come to an important concept, "stable matchings," with a downto-earth interpretation. A matching M
190
The Dinitz problem
of a new graph, joining two such vertices if and only if as edges in K,,, they have a common endvertex, then we clearly obtain the square graph S,. Let us say that
Construction of a line graph
Identities versus bijections
+
+
+
Chapter 29
+
Consider the infinite product ( I x ) ( 1 x 2 )( 1 x 3 )(1 x 4 ) . . . and expand it in the usual way into a series Enroanxn by grouping together those products that yield the same power xn. By inspection we find for the first terms
So we have e. g. a6
=
4, a7
=
5,
Identities versus bijections
Problem. Let P,(n) and Pd(n)be the partitions of n into odd and into
193
196
Identities versus bijections
References [I] G. E. ANDREWS: The Theory of
Five-coloring plane graphs
Plane graphs and their colorings have been the subject of intensive research since the beginnings of graph theory because of their connection to the fourcolor problem.
Chapter 30
200
Five-coloring plane graphs From part (A) of the proposition on page 67 we know that G has a vertex v of degree at most 5. Delete 11 and all edges incident
202
Five-coloring plane graphs is still plane and 3-colorable. We assign { 5 , 6 , 7 , 8 ) to the top vertex and {9,10, 11,
204
A museum with n = 12 walls
A triangulation of the museum
The interior dihedral angles po-0.039 Tnc 8.875 0.026 Tc - 170674368rd
How to guard a museum
How to guard a museum
convex vertex A. In fact, there must be at least three of them: In essence this is an application of the pigeonhole principle! Or you may consider the convex hull of the polygon, and note that all its vertices are convex also for the original polygon. Now look at the two neighboring vertices B and C of A.If the segment BC lies entirely in then this is our diagonal. If
205
206
"Museum guards" (A 3-dimensional art-gallery problem)
How to guard a museum
208
Turdn's graph theorem
Let us turn to the general case. The first two proofs due to Turin and to ErdBs, respecttivly.
induction and are
First proof. We -6e induction on n. One easily computes tha5 0 0 9.8123 Tc
Turan's graph theorem
all vertices adjacent to u,, and define s, similarly for uj, where we may
209
Tura'n's
214
Communicating without errors
set Vl x V2 =
Cornmunicatin~without errors
cliques of size 1, the edges are the cliques of size 2, the triangles are cliques of size 3, and so on. Let C be the set of cliques in G. Consider an arbitrary probability distribution
215
216
The
Communicating without errors
Communicatin~without errors Let us see how LovAsz proceeded
217
Communicating without errors
Of friends and politicians
It is not known who first raised the following problem or who gave it its
Suppose in a group of people we have the situation that any pair of persons have precisely one common friend. Then there is always a
Chapter 34
224
Of
O f friends and voliticians Now if the square root
225
Probability makes countinn (sometimes) easy
Theorem 2, 2. For all numbers: R(k:k)
>
229
the following lower bound holdsfor the Ramsey
2
2s.
. .
. * ______.....,_______ L _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _
H 2) Proof. = 2. o We mhave (2) we R (know 2 3
3)
Probability makes counting (sometimes) easy
23 1
Probability makes counting (sometimes) easy
232
Since the right-hand side goes to 0 with n going to infinity, we infer that ):
>
p(X
234
Probability makes counting (sometimes) easy By linearity of expectation we thus find
Set
which is
: p = Here comes the punch line:
View more...
Comments