Descripción: Plato's Theory of Desire Author(s): Charles H. Kahn Reviewed work(s): Source: The Review of Metaphysics...
Plato's Theory of Desire Author(s): Charles H. Kahn Reviewed work(s): Source: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Sep., 1987), pp. 77-103 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20128559 . Accessed: 24/01/2012 08:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics.
http://www.jstor.org
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE CHARLES
aim here
1YJ.Y middle
sense
is to make
dialogues.
account
of Plato's
I need
To do that
of desire
or reconcile
to unify
H. KAHN
in the are
what
at first sight two quite different accounts: the doctrine of eros in the in the Repub Symposium and the tripartite theory of motivation It may
lic.1
be
that
the
two
theories
are
after
all
irreconcilable,
that Plato simply changed his mind on the nature of human desire after
and
the Symposium
writing
before
the Republic.
composing
But that conclusion can be justified only if attempts two
end
theories This
temporary articulate
of the some
provoke other hand, pate
Plato,
a full-scale the concept
view
some
psychology,
subject critical
Plato of
the
The
attempt
a historical
interest.
to formulate
his
in failure.
is primarily
must
be made
first.
but
one with
some
project,
in the Republic,
theory of desire
to reconcile the con
is the first philosopher
of the psyche, in a systematic
the first
to
Furthermore, view today's
to
and hence way.
remote is sufficiently on our own reflection
from
On
assumptions. is perhaps the only major philosopher of twentieth-century central discoveries
depth
that is, of Freud and his school; I shall end with
Plato and Freud. between comparisons to begin Plato's structive by presenting the contemporary of action. theory
But view
it will within
the
to antici
some
be more the
context
in of
I at supposed, or intentional
It is commonly a voluntary plain
that to ex by philosophers, we must a action both identify
least
1 I ignore whatever For present there may be differences purposes of the Phaedrus between and I and that of the Republic, the psychology to deal with the complications in later works introduced make no attempt I briefly discuss of and Timaeus. the treatment such as the Philebus such as the Gorgias and Lysis. desire in earlier dialogues Review Metaphysics
of Metaphysics
41
(September
1987):
77-103.
Copyright
?
1987
by
the Review
of
CHARLES H. KAHN
78 on the part
a belief
and
desire
the agent's
of the agent:
in question will
certain goal and his belief that the action A
this
belief
goal. to act; agent
it is assumed, alone, must be an appropriate
there
ought
to be the
Hobbes,
who
spies,
to range
"the
abroad
common
embedded, reasons
action:
although
Aristotle
explicitly
avoids
simply of action
a deliverance has
it seems For
to Aristotle. a two-factor
give the Humean
assumption As Aristotle puts
good to us, rather the starting-point
pattern by Hobbes For Aristotle ultimately the slave, ing action. nant form
criti
is that, he for action, explanation is funda that motivation
that makes
all
difference
it, "we desire
something we because
it seeming good is rational thought
than
(no?sis)"
of this explanatory
the difference.4
his then, despite in charge of our actions;
double-factor it remains
reason
theory, the master
and
even
it needs the cooperation of desire though can play this role because Reason boul?sis, in human is of desire rational. beings, fully
less, Aristotle's
traditional
The
It is the reversal
(Metaphysics A.7.1072a29).
theory
assumption
may
rightly
be regarded
that human
action
as the
is not
in initiat the
domi
Neverthe
source
of the
is to be explained
2 Leviathan 1.8. the comments of John Cooper, Compare of Human Motivation," Theory History of Philosophy Quarterly 3-21.
of
been
The is just a desire-belief pair.3 one old. With differ very significant
does
non-rational.
it.
desire
is not
and
a reason
in question is, in fact, can back it be traced
mentally because
desired."2
thing
recent
for
of
ence,
to the
only echoing as scouts and
theory It is but it is still widely discussions, accepted. treatment in Donald for example, Davidson's influential
in some
theory
desires
is and
to the fact that this notion of desire
a philosophical theory sense. The belief-desire
embodies
was
Hume
case.
in every
desire
to the
thoughts and find the way
the
claim that reason
And are
to call attention
I want
cized
of the passions.
slave said
lead to
not motivate
could
is the view that lies behind Hume's
This
for a
desire
by
"Plato's 1 (1984):
3
on Ac See D. Davidson, and Causes," in Essays "Actions, Reasons tions and Events (Oxford, 1980), 3-19 (although Davidson speaks not of but more generally desires of "pro-attitudes"). to the For a challenge Humean view see T. Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism 1970), (Oxford, 29-30.
4 or Leviathan 1.6: "But whatsoever is the object of any mans Appetite that is it, which he for his part calleth Good" (Hobbes's Leviathan, Desire; ed. C. B. Macpherson [Penguin Books, 1968], 120).
79
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE to two distinct
reference or,
in a later if we
to take note of the originality
Plato, seem
are
because
an accurate
to have
It is hard
theory.
factors: contrasting reason and will.
terminology,
It is essential regard
and
this
to be the merest
to avoid view
view
imposing become
has
common
reason
and desire,
in this
of Aristotle
of Plato's
so familiar
different
quite
a double-factor to us
upon theory that it may
sense.
And there may be passages Plato in the dialogues where himself flirts with such a view.5 But most mature in and the is his fullest psychological theory, Republic, In the Republic not a double-factor at all. is no con there theory can in with and that be contrasted this sense reason, cept of desire of desire. The fun does not have Aristotle's concept simply can be illustrated the two views at the between damental difference
Plato
of terminology, is also particularly level
where clear.
the historical Aristotle
connection
to be good), and pride), genus eral;
which and
the
of the soul in the Republic.
of
species
for what
is judged
with connected feelings or desire for pleasure). is orexis, desire species
(self-assertive thymos and epithymia (appetite three embraces these
principle corresponding psychic of desire). Now the names alone make faculty are directly of desire Aristotle's three species
partition
three
recognizes
desire: boul?sis (rational desire for the good?or
them
between
anger The in gen
is to orektikon clear based
that upon
(the two out of the
(See the diagram below.)
tri
But
term. term and no generic The genus comparable never occurs no in his orexis and that is accident. writings; (desire) he may Aristotle the word, have deliber did not invent Although to fit the needs of his theory.6 at its meaning Plato, ately stretched Plato
least
has
no
in the Republic,
has
no place
for a generic
concept
of desire,
as
like Gorgias 51 have in mind passages and Meno 468a-b, 509d-510a, Socrates claims that everyone desires what is good and 77b-78b, where hence implies that doing evil is to be explained in cognition by a mistake out to me (by Alexander rather than volition. It has been pointed Ne to construe be tempted the contrast that one might the between hamas) as a distinction in the Phaedrus and the two horses charioteer be myth tween reason and desire; but I think that would be a misconstrual. The not reason alone but rational desire: he relies upon charioteer represents the horses for his locomotion but not for his motivation. His desire to is precisely the desire for knowledge behold the Forms and the good that (I will argue) is constitutive of reason in the Republic. 6 The only earlier use of orexis is in three fragments of Democritus at two of which least appear (DK B.72, 219, 284), genuine (no.s 219 and seems to use orexis and epithymia Democritus 284). interchangeably.
CHARLES H. KAHN
80 Plato
Freud
Aristotle
(psyche)
(psyche) Reason
1.
Desire
2. ?
Nutrition
(orexis) 1. boul?sis
1. logistikon (rational) 2. thymoeides
ego
Sensation
2.
thymos
("spirited", anger)
3. epithymia
3. id (libido)
3. epithymia
("appetite")
opposed to some other psychic faculty. The tripartition of the Re public is not the division of a faculty of desire but a division of the itself. psyche the soul can reason
From also
all
three
Plato divides
When out
as
some
from
divides desire
reason,
the psyche
into three parts, he the
and
sense-perception,
into three parts, he divides
like.
it with
remainder. This
Platonic to us
miliar Perhaps
that
that
concept it may
is why
even
noted that the tripartition not generally of theory rationality Aristotle of love.
have
that what
Plato's, good,
of view, Plato's of point tripartition as a partition But of desire. then as a distinct but principle particular
When Aristotle
form of desire. distinguishes
be described not
appears
another
will
belong
drawn and
of reason
as a form a kind
seem
to be
those
commentators
of the Republic the
necessary
category who have
is a tripartition consequences of philosophy
for his
conception in mapping his remarks, or the rational he calls boul?sis, in Plato's
logistikon,
"in
the
is so unfa
of desire of
mistake. correctly
of desire7 for Plato's as a form
onto tripartition desire for what is
rational,
calculating
part of the soul" (De Anima 3.9.432b5), but this is an understate ment. For Plato the rational desire for what is good just is the part of the soul. reason itself. for Plato, rational
Aristotle's
rational
I begin with a sketch of this extraordinary the Republic, in the context of the tripartite 7 Notably Press, 1977), Motivation,"
principle
of desire
is,
theory of reason in conception of the
T. H. Irwin, Plato's Moral (Oxford at the Clarendon Theory "Plato's Theory of Compare Cooper, p. 192 n. 20, p. 195. \*. 5-6.
81
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE a brief
After
psyche.
I turn
desire,
of eros.
on the subject of dialogues a account Plato gives unified
earlier
to the Symposium,
And
where
I end by considering can be made
of love
theory
at
look
how this unified
the question with
compatible
the
tripartite
psychol
ogy of the Republic.
II the theory of the Republic: My description
To begin with reason be
as a form
there
as
regarded
of desire
implies and will
controversial
an
of
that may
interpretation defense. require
For
what
Plato says at Republic 9.580d7 is that for the three parts of the soul there
are
has.
I think,
to each part, and similarly "one proper pleasures, to each part). and three rules" there are three desires (one proper seem more to construe It might to reason natural the desire proper or property reason not as reason which itself, but as an attribute three
and its desire
such
distinction
cannot be a distinction
between
but
property
that
however, between
only Plato regularly
principle.
any
two
reason
between
the thing and its
of a single psychic aspects on the one this principle
essential
characterizes
hand as the capacity to calculate and to think things through (to logistikon) and as "that by which we learn" (580dl0), but also, on the other
hand,
as
is "always wholly
which
so that
stand,"
things
the
the philomathes,
which
to knowing
directed
it is called
part
"lover
of
to
loves
and
learn,
the truth of how
learning
(philo-mathes)
and lover of wisdom (philo-sophon)" (581b9, in book 9). It was the of to philomathes (intellectual curiosity and notion precisely by love of learning)
that
Plato
first
ciple in book 4 (435e7), where
us to the
introduced
the mention
rational
prin
of this love is immedi
we to the part learn" by a reference "by which Thus the two descriptions, "lover of learning" and "that we we calculate"), are used both learn" in (or "by which
followed
ately
(436a9). by which
book 4 and in book 9 as alternative What
part.8 8
Plato
means,
I think,
designations is that
nothing
for the rational could
cause
us
(or
to the four passages cited see book 4.439d5 (hoi logizetai), "Lover of learn and 586e4 (to philosophon). (h?i manthanomen) a course is of of the philosophic standard ing" (philomathes) description both in the Republic temperament, (5.475c2,6.485d3,490a9, etc.) and in the Phaedo Socrates (67b4, 82cl, d9, etc.); in the Phaedrus, applies the term to 9.583a2
In addition
CHARLES H. KAHN
82
us want to learn. So although the soul) to learn if it did not make we may and between the capacity distinguish conceptually verbally to know, to know and the desire between just as we may distinguish the
theoretical
ity to calculate In each Plato.
to know capacity and deliberate,
the
truth
these
are
and not
the practical capac real distinctions for
reason and desire?we practice, a single two aspects of what is, for Plato, in is so fundamental of theory and practice and
case?theory
are
only distinguishing This unity principle. that he never makes Aristotle's distinction between Plato's thought in exercised wisdom and the theoretical contemplation, sophia, in action wisdom exercised and delibera the practical phron?sis, tion.
This
of
unity
that
presupposition edge of value,
of what
has as and practice theory of truth must the knowledge is worth
pursuing,
so that
a consequence or also be a knowl the desire
to know
the truth will ultimately be a desire to know and to possess the good. As Plato tells us inRepublic 6, the good is "that which every soul
And
(505dll).
for
and
pursues
the
sake
of which
since the Form
of the Good
all reality, rational desire knowledge a the know to and obtain be desire good. not soul is (or essentially comprises) only like Aristotle's for the good, also a desire and
come
clearer The
three
it performs
all
must
for Plato
So the rational a desire
its actions"
is the source of all ultimately part of the
for knowledge This will
boul?sis.
our sketch of the tripartition. complete are 4 by a distinction in book introduced parts
but be
as we
tween: (1) the philomathes,
be
the love of learning and the principle by
16 [1971]: As Richard has noted Robinson (Phronesis (230d3). the parts of the soul both as instruments by which 46-47), Plato describes we do things and also as agents in their own right. the instru However, or faculty, view of the parts must be seen as an expository device mental, to introduce since it is our actions them at the level of the explanandum, The agent-view of the parts ("lover of learning", that are to be explained. "lover of honor," etc.), on the other hand, represents them as theoretical Plato's of human character entities with explanatory power. explanation in terms of the interaction of these parts. and conduct is given exclusively There is no room for a person or self over and above the three parts on the over in book 9 to the person "handing level of the explanans. References a pictur the throne of his soul" to one or another of the parts constitute not to be taken literally feature of Plato's esque but eliminable exposition, as part of the explanatory It remains model. to be seen how far an to the model. of the three parts is essential conception anthropomorphic see of anthropomorphism Julia Annas, discussion For an interesting here, An Introduction toPlato's Press, 1981), 'Republic' (Oxford at the Clarendon himself
142-46.
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE
83
which we learn, (2) the thymoeides, the principle "by which we get principle (to philokhr?maton) or angry," and (3) the money-loving we desire the pleasures with concerned food and "by which are distin Thus the parts and the like" (435e-436a).
the part begetting
to so many from the beginning different by reference guished types or impulse.9 or appetitive The third of drives, desires part (to
will
epithym?tikon) into biologically
be elaborately and
necessary are
desires
non-necessary
and then the desires, into lawful and crimi
non-necessary
further
in books 8-9, first
subdivided subdivided
are latent in everyone, which These criminal desires, impulses. as Plato in a famous in dreams, describes themselves anticipa the rational ele tion of the Freudian "then, when Oedipal insight: . . ment wild the and and is from freed part. beastly sleeps, [wakes] nal
show
reason.
It does not hesitate to try to have inter or with in imagination, anyone else, man, god or beast; it is ready for any deed of murder, and will abstain from no transi, after Shorey). kind of food" (9.571c-d Plato's of the picture all
shame
course
with
and
a mother
thus
epithym?tikon
rather
corresponds
of the id. Struck by this parallel correlating
reason
with
the Freudian
tried to find the superego moeides),10 nation,
which
he describes and
nicely
to Freud's
depiction
and by the obvious possibility
in Plato's
ego,
some
principle
have
interpreters
of anger
as "always wholly impelled and hence called 'ambitious'
of
(to thy to domi
prestige, (philoni to win") and philotimon 'lov "loving literally, "loving victory," " terms As these honor' Plato's indicate, ing principle (9.581a-b). is self-assertive to competition and directed outwards with others, victory,
kon,
not
internalized
and
closer
affinities
with
first.
In view
of this
9
like the superego.11 self-punishing the love of power and with the desire essentially
social
character,
the
It has
thymoeides
to be is
See 436b2: The question is whether it is with a different in principle each case "or with the whole soul that we engage in these activities, when we are impelled to do so (hotan horm?s?men)." 10 A. J. P. Kenny, in Plato's Republic," "Mental Health in The Anat 1-27. omy of the Soul (Oxford: Blackwell, 1973), 11 In the Leontius does seem to act the part of the story the thymoeides in reproaching the eyes for their compulsion to gaze at the superego, cannot be its essential But self-reproach corpses (439e-440a). function, since in the parallel (at 441b) from Odyssey 20.17 it is Odysseus' example reason that upbraids his thymoeides (for urging punishment immediately, without regard to the larger plan of action).
CHARLES H. KAHN
84 more
perhaps
like Aggression we will focus here
But
cept.
Plato's
reason
"good
on the
other
any
rational
begins in book 4: they
in the psyche.
represents
ians will
like
reason
of
picture of the guardians
wisdom
than
at
the
part. social
be essentially their practical: or "goodness in deliberation."
of the whole
virtue
responding
They
must
city, and their wisdom
will
the welfare
concerning
judgment
of the
the
deliber
be good cor
The
be the excellence
to rule, what concerning
deserves
part psychic naturally "calculates (analogisamenon)
with
as a whole.
city
for the individual will
which
level
in the state what represent the knowledge of the guard excellence will be euboulia,
Now
counsel"
ate on behalf
con
Freudian
of the
the
which
logistikon or worse" is better
(441cl); which "has a care for the whole soul" (441e5) and "deliber ates on behalf of the whole soul and body" (442b6). Wisdom con in this
sists
part's
the whole
ruling
on "the knowledge
of what
of
for
the
parts
(442c5-8). as
has
and
function
it must advantageous, what is The best. pursue
to know and obtain what controversial
At
good.
three; whole
at
that
part
I shall
is not only essentially the
the
level
Hence
three"
reason for
wisdom
city, the goal
the whole at
of rational
love
This is the in the
desire for the
at what
aims
aims
also
reason
that
here:
desire but essentially
is advan
composed the welfare
desire,
of all of
the
of reason
as
the good of the individual alone (as it is sometimes
to be, on egoistic of Plato) readings but in the every case, nity alone, good as Good such. said
This
must
it takes to be) good.
individual, of the soul and the
to learn"
defend
of the
part level of
community.
such, is neither
reason
to all
of what is good knowledge nature be able to know and
"loves
is (orwhat
thesis
for each
tageous
based
for each
(to sympheron) is common
which
the practical by its very
and
Republic
is advantageous
the whole
orders
giving
But if the rational part, both in city and in individual,
its specific
second
and
person
identification, with for desire
or at the
least
good
can
ment which Plato uses to establish
this be
nor the
the good of the commu or the in general good
necessary confirmed
the distinction
of
convergence, from
the
between
argu
reason
as an example a thirsty man Plato who proposes appetite. on from a himself the basis of resistance that prevents drinking comes "from reasoning" thirst pulls him on to drink, (ek logismou): but this pull is "over-powered" force drag (kratein) by a rational and
ging him back (439b3-d8).
Plato has just emphasized
that thirst
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE here must
be construed
85 as desire
simply
for
drink
not
and
as desire
This passage has sometimes been for good drink (437d-439a). thought to imply that the appetite (epithymia) in question is a no cognitive with of its object;12 grasp craving," but, as its object thirst must and hence drinkable recognize
"blind course,
So a minimum
desirable. elemental
A more
appetite.
for other
characteristic
which moeides, been wronged.
complex such as the
drives,
appetitive
of a sexual object. are
of cognition
even is implied form of cognition
And quite definite of
the angry
gets
when
component emphasizes
that
as such
of
as
the most
is required or the pursuit
of a moral
judgments
intermediate
So a cognitive in all three parts thirst
love of money
for
of
the
sort
the
part soul, thy it thinks it (i.e., the person) has element of some kind is an essential
of the
soul.13
is a desire
The for drink
reason
why Plato as such, and not
a desire for hot drink or good drink, is not because he wants
to deny
a cognitive to appetite to insist upon element but because he wants to all considerations the appetite's other than getting indifference reason it wants. what In order to establish the distinction between
and appetite Plato must here define, for the first time, the notion of a desire that is essentially independent of any judgment concerning or advantageous beneficial, as synonymous). In earlier dialogues, as desire for something construed desire
what
is good,
ficial.14
Opinions will
these three terms (taking Plato had systematically to be good or bene judged
differ as to how far this "intellectualist"
of the historical the position the represents Socrates, a more or a naive I of delib younger, Plato, psychology (as believe) on Plato's erate to make the part, designed simplification plausible in the contained Socratic On of any insights paradoxes. reading must this earlier Plato with it break in order to view, decisively
view
of desire
reason
distinguish flicting
and
in the
factors
as separate con and potentially appetite as a desire It is precisely soul. for what is
judged to be good and beneficial appetite
and
the
that reason
is set apart
from
thymoeides.15
12 J. to Plato's Introduction 'Republic' 139. 13 Annas, This has been argued at length by Jon Moline, "Plato on the Com of the Psyche", Archiv f?r Geschichte der Philosophie, 60 (1978): plexity 1-26.
14 77c-78b. Meno See Section III, below. 15Gorgias 468b-c, 499e; 195: reason of consists So, rightly, Irwin, Plato's Moral Theory, "rational desires for the over-all good." Plato's Similarly, Cooper, Theory
CHARLES H. KAHN
86 We
must
that
as at by Plato two nonrational
represented sense. The
ing their objects; to attain soning reason.
with
in mind
bear
if all
what
intelligent,
of
the
soul
are
in the Humean
con seizing or analogue
very
But
to succeed this
(How
three
is distinctive
love of knowledge,
theoretical
parts rational
or appetite of spirit possibility since it obviously takes some form
The
below.)
three
of recogniz only capable use must some rea also of make means-end they their goal, at least in the intra-psychic competition
as much, trol implies of intelligence for these parts reason for their own ends. seen
all
least minimally parts are not
in enslaving to use reason, is to be understood will be
are parts of reason
represented are its twin
as minimally goals:
(a) the
and (b) the practical pursuit of what
concern it is primarily the second, more is good. And that practical reason on in the to Plato must the arguments rely upon distinguish For it is not any theoretical basis of psychic conflict. conclusion about the nature of the beverage but only the practical decision that
to drink which can explain why the thirsty man
itwould be harmful resists
to quench his the connection
the
impulse In order to see
and the fuller psychology three the
of reason
1. In the weakest has
no
action
guiding desire will
understand
of the
rule
to play in fixing the towards and desire as
count are
consequences
argument
in book
4
help to distinguish
Plato
to be speaking
of
in the notion
role
this
between
of books 8-9 it will
we might soul.
at which
levels rule
thirst.
judged as counts
ends these
rational
deliberation
to be pursued but only in ends. On this view, any
it is lucidly "all advantageous
rational
if
of reason,
pursued,
when
its
considered."
things is independently advantageous speci reason con in the hedonistic of the Protagoras: calculus not the ends. we may trols only the means, in fact while Now as a a case is not this rational this will that Plato life, regard as one in which reason describe "rules" he may (archei); though
However, fied, as
what
21 n. 18. But Cooper distinguishes about the of Motivation, "judgements the good" from "desires for good that follow upon them," thus introducing Aristotelian of rational and rational desire. bifurcation judgement (On p. 6 he thus speaks of reason having desires.) I do not think this does justice to the radically Platonic of reason as constituted different conception by desire.
87
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE reason
in any particular to decision "prevails" (kratei) from acting.16 2. A stronger notion of the rule of reason that the ends of requires not the be For action determined. means) rationally (and only this means that if reason will rules, the goal to be pursued Plato, that
say
act
or refrain
by a specific of which version
of human the mini welfare, conception is given of virtue in the by the account
be defined mum
and in the early books of the Republic
Socratic dialogues the
introduction
aims
at a good
ment 3.
of philosophy life,
in book
The rule 5). of the harmonious
in terms
specified
(before
of reason develop
of bodily health and psychic excellence.
In the
strongest
to be
and
pursued
rules
action
guiding
not
the ends only by fixing towards these but by ends,
the goal of human life through its own philosophical
constituting
in (2) the
Whereas
activity.
reason
notion,
of reason
function
is strictly
prac
tical, here it is both practical and theoretical: it is as knowledge of reality and the Forms (including the Form of the Good) that reason
both
specifies
three
These
stronger
action. ference
of
the
Plato's
between
of
rule
content
reason
of reason,
between account
of the good
are
as the goal
virtue
virtue
in books 5-6.
an
is not
innovation here: both Diotima's view stronger the doctrine of the Phaedo these later books anticipate
including
access
composed
as a defense Plato
to
4
is replaced by references
and speech of the Re
is explicitly Since the Republic Forms.) as a defense of justice and only secondarily of does not emphasize the distinction between (2)
our noticing
in books
the
philosopher to "the rule
it that the just man of book
of
reason"
tween (2) and (3). But the contrast between 16 At
(But the
the
and (3): it is almost without Plato's
the dif in Repub
the best human life with the life of philosophy,
public by identifying
philosophy,
of rational
(2) and (3) coincides with of pre-philosophic
lic 4 and the account of philosophic
life.
distinguished by to progres corresponding
of the good
characterizations
The distinction
the
provides
accounts
richer
progressively sively
levels
and
8-9. seem
Hence
of many as be ambiguous
the purely instrumen
that it be reason 439c7 it is essential that prevails (kratein), role for though, as we shall see, Plato hints at a more than instrumental reason here. in the In the case of the repression desires of spendthrift but of some appetities oligarchic soul, he speaks not of reason prevailing others dominating kratousas, (epithymias epithymion [554dl0]).
CHARLES H. KAHN
88
tal role of reason
in (1) and its teleological
role in (2) and (3) is
reason marked: this is the difference between sharply as master of the passions. Thus the Pha do deprecates of virtue based upon a balancing of pleasures conception in contrast
to
the
life
of genuine
virtue
as slave the
and
slavish
and
pains, wisdom
determinedly
(68d-69c). The Gorgias had argued earlier that no version of (1) can be fully coherent unless it coincides with (2), and hence that the only rational life is one that accepts the Socratic notion of the good.17 A similar argument is implicit in the account of the deviant lives of Republic 8-9, where the rule of reason is identified with the life of the just man (here equated with the philosopher). If reason is able to rule in the soul, itwill specify the life of virtue (the life of philosophy) as the good to be aimed at. If it does not succeed in so, that
doing
is because
it has
appetite that itmis-identifies part
can
that
form
any
the domination
so "overpowered"
been
the good.
even
of the good,
conception of the
by
spirit
or
Since it is only the rational
other
has
an
erroneous
the
conception, consequence parts reason a mistake of causing to make in its recognition of the ends to be pursued. it means That is what to be enslaved.18 for reason
Reason
can rule only if it is enlightened in a virtuous
to say only
in (3)?only
could
of reason
in book
not
And
need
not
his present the before 4, even the weaker
appearance view
much
skillfully
to philosophers. only so as not under-described, less
can be fully
that
full-strength
of the tripartite support psychology. to apply is designed to human beings men,
in regard its object, that is
its rule
if it is fully enlightened,
philosophy. Plato
does
soul.
for After
realized?as
is, only in the life of
of the rule conception of philosophy. But he his initial in argument all,
generally, Hence
the tripartite model not only to virtuous Plato's
to presuppose
example the notion
is of
reason ruling in the soul that will be specified in the following definition of the virtues.19 All he requires is a single instance in 17 See my "Drama and Dialectic in Plato's Gorgias," in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, ed. Julia Annas, 113-18. 1, (1983), 18 Here I am agreeing with Cooper (Plato's Theory ofMotivation, p. 19 n. 9 and p. 20 n. 18), against lives as Irwin, who speaks of the deviant a "rational following plan," being "controlled by (the) rational part," or from "a rational resulting choice, made by the rational part" (Plato's Moral I see no textual support for this interpretation. 19Theory, 227-34). The application seems quite general, of Plato's since the argument is not explicitly limited to the case where reason sets the ends of example
89
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE someone
which
of long-term established
calculation tion
from
refrains
of this result. is capable over intense ment prevail answer Plato's here, a contains, primitive tially
geous. soul what duct
urge
some
thirst? is that reason I submit, just is, or essen non for the good, an irreducible, desire to and advanta be it takes what good
to pursue it means
to claim
that
our action that determines is advantageous a is Plato's what On for rational desire led by good. the the good and wanting is no gap between there knowing we be desire that statement something (Even Aristotle's
view good. cause
it seems
distinct
episodes
book
4, wanting to perform its
morphic
what
good
to us might
been
rejected
by Plato
as
of in terms of the psychology Now means the soul of each part wanting just In the anthropo in a harmonious way.
or events.) the good function
language with which
parts,
have
that the judgment and the desire are
since it suggests
misleading,
one
of
the good is "what every is acts": the it always and for the sake of which good pursues our con Whenever we all want in so far as we are rational a judg can we it that is either is under rational say control,
concerning or that we are
will
a consequence
even
But the weakest concep an argument how it must explain can a faculty and of cognition judg
How
is what
That
ment
these
as
advantage. by such
of reason
derivative
drinking
reason's
desire
as commands
be expressed and with another
its own
Plato
concerning to them
describes
the interaction
of
of the soul the other parts with to perform in harmony to rule desire So reason's
judgment. and its judgment thing, over and above to rule is just the expression its desire is beneficial: for what desire is beneficial.20 or the spelling-out for what of its desire that the other reason in ruling, succeeds Whether is, whether in the soul
is not
some
third
use of reason in what Plato calls include the instrumental action but might Plato cunningly "slavish virtue" However, calculus). (as in the hedonic in the described rule of reason (which is gradually the virtuous insinuates that the desire to drink in his pages, 440a-441e) by suggesting following or disease" "affect (path?mata) is due to excessive (439d2), thus example If at is aimed health welfare. and calculation rational the that implying we would the role of reason were thought of here as merely instrumental, to establish in fact not get the division of psychic parts that Plato wants 7-8 n. 9). Motivation reasons Plato's Theory of by Cooper, (for 20 developed with Cooper to be a disagreement Here there seems (p. 6) who In the end, however, to reason "an innate taste for ruling." ascribes desire for good (p. 8). this from the more fundamental Cooper too derives
CHARLES H. KAHN
90
to obey (peithesthai)
parts will be persuaded
reason's
is
judgment
matter.
another
In order for appetite to listen to reason, and anger be hence the for the scheme need of they trained; properly education in books 2-3. too must Reason be pre-philosophical must
properly trained in order to give the right commands; hence the need for philosophy, and for the theory of knowledge and higher education in books 5-7.21 By the end of book 6 we know that the the
of
part
learning
soul will
until it reaches the highest
not
be
to rule
prepared
adequately
form of learning (tomegiston math?ma),
the only knowledge that can satisfy its desire, of namely cognition the Good "which in soul all its actions." The every pursues itself, we find in earlier which such as the Gorgias and principle dialogues the Meno,
was
and which
cited
in book
desire
of reason.
that
the
realize
that
and as the essential desire beings for Plato all knowledge culminates
of the Good, since it is the Good that makes
as well
knowable see
we
Once
in knowledge
of all human
as making
love of
them that
learning
real
identical with
shared
but which,
by all mankind,
because
doctrine
knowledge, real things these
is easy
do not and
difficult
still
and
to state see
clearly less do we
knowable.
problems.22
the
we (6.508e-509b), rational part of
to Plato,
according but
all things
the love of the good that
realized only by lovers of that Form which we
true
and
characterizes
the soul is ultimately
This
desires
"everyone
in book 6 in a double form: as
good things" (438a3), thus reappears the universal
4, that
can
be
is
fully
is truly the Good. hard
extremely the Good
to understand
can be an object how for see why or how the Good makes other I have no solution to propose to here
But
even without
an
explication
of the
21 The theory of the virtues in book 4 is not self-contained, as we can see if we ask what activity of reason constitutes wisdom to book according 4. If reason rules, it aims at the welfare of each part and of the whole as well. But what is the welfare of the rational And what is it for part? reason to do "its own proper work"? for an occasional mention of Except there is no hint of an adequate knowledge (428b6ff., 428cll-d8, 442c6), answer until we reach books 5-7. We can give no non-circular account of what Plato means to by the rule of reason until we can give some content the autonomous as love of (non-instrumental) activity of reason, conceived and pursuit of the good. And here the notion of what is good knowledge must be specified by more than civic concord and psychic harmony, since these both presuppose the notion of the rule of reason. 22 see G. Santas, For discussion of the Good "The Form in Plato's in Essays in Greek Philosophy, vol. 2, ed. J. P. Anton and A. Republic", Preus P. White, Plato (Albany: SUNY, 1983), 232-63. Compare Nicholas on Knowledge and Reality Hackett, (Indianapolis: 1976), 100-03.
91
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE supreme
we
of the Good,
principle
can
see how
the
factor
psychic
defined by the love of knowledge
and truth can coincide with
rational
welfare
common and
for
desire to all
the
human
the practical As has been
good?for beings. of our
sides
For
these
the
or happiness?which are just the theoretical
is
essential
rationality. of the soul have a cognitive seen, all three parts of desire. But only at the level and all three are also forms aspect of reason do the cognitive and desiderative elements fully coincide,
so that their highest Plato
though
always the erotic
correlation, is essentially sium
fulfillment must avoids
be achieved
mechanical
to the dialectical
equivalent
and
repetition of Beauty
to the Form
ascent
together.
Al
one-to-one
in the Sympo to the vision
ascent
of the Good inRepublic 6-7. Without begging the question whether the Form of Beautiful is to be taken as strictly identical for Plato with
the Form
precisely
the
of Good, role
same
of philosophical
can
that
recognize dialogue,
the
as terminus
two Forms
play for the scheme
enlightenment.
In the Symposium of eros presented
tion
we
in each
this whole
scheme
as a universal
desire
by the no A cursory
is structured for the good.
glance at the earlier dialogues inwhich this theme is developed will help us appreciate the rather different ways in which this desire is articulated in the Symposium and Republic.
Ill
Phaedo
the earliest with any system is, I believe, dialogue of desire. And it is the only dialogue the before a contrast to recognize and Republic between rational desire
aiming
at the good
atic
The Gorgias discussion
(expressed
desires aimed at pleasure desires
for
pleasure,
by the verb
boulesthai)
and
sensuous
(expressed by the term epithymia)P
praised
by Callicles
as
constituting
the
The life
23 Aristotle's distinction between boul?sis terminological (rational is inherited from the Gorgias, probably by desire) and epithymia (appetite) in the Academy. The Charmides also men way of semi-technical usage a terminological distinction between epithymia tions, in passing, aiming at and boul?sis aiming at some good (167e, where eras is said to be pleasure The author of the Gorgias and Char directed towards something kalon). not suffering from any "Socratic" mides was obviously illusion that all desire is desire for the good. the description of erotic (And compare emotion at Charmides 155d.)
CHARLES H. KAHN
92 of a naturally
goal
man,
superior
or "spirited"
anger
One where
correspond
are
appetites
"appe
include the
as well.24
drives even
passage
to the
roughly
though they probably would
titive" part of the Republic,
speaks prophetically found" But (493a-bl).
of "the there
part of the soul is no correspond
ing attempt to define a rational part of the soul. The psychological The possibility of a theory of the Gorgias is at best incipient. conflict
between
desires
is not
choice
between
the
rational
envisaged, satisfaction
505a-b, 507e2). that what implies
what
he
of our own
desire.25
all men
Meno:
A
desire
a person
we may
he wants:
thinks
closely
good
do hear
and
bad
wants
really be mistaken paradox no one wants
of a
desires
of argument is not always
as to the
related
things;
we
a famous
In addition,
cf. 491dll,
(500a; the Gorgias
although of good
true
object is argued for in the what is bad (Meno
77cl, 78b4). The Meno to be
wants one
unhappy"
of Socrates'
want
serves
also premiss love in the Symposium. "dear structs dear
in what
paradox
(78a4-5).26 arguments
protreptic
to be happy"
Symposium
this
supports
(282a2). as
As we
the
starting come We
the
Similarly takes
as
claim
that
"no
in the Euthydemus, its premiss: "We
shall see in a moment, for
point even closer
one
all
this
the Platonic
of theory to the doctrine of the
the Lysis has to say about something
that is
In a famous
con
for its own sake." (philon) the regress, and then breaks for the sake
with
of Z, etc.,"
Socrates
"X is dear suddenly
passage
which
for the sake introduces
of Y, Y is the notion
of the primary or truly dear thing "for the sake of which all other things are dear" (219c-220b). This alone is truly called dear; other things are dear only for the sake of this primary object, of which
24 in the Gorgias. There is no trace of the thymoeides Presumably Plato had not yet thought of it as a distinct type of desire; but in any case it in the Gorgias. A third there would have been no reason to introduce class of impulses would have spoiled the neat dualism by which Calliclean are opposed to Socratic boulesthai. appetites 25 Here again we have a paradox that Plato echoes in Gorgias 468b-c. do what it wants ruled soul will by no means the Republic: the tyrannically an 468e5 cf. and d5-7. 9.577el-2; Gorgias (ha 26 boul?th?i) Rep. is of course questionable. The logic of these arguments For an to which in view makes them too them defend my tame, see G. attempt and Henley: Socrates Kegan Paul, Santas, (London, Boston Routledge as protreptic must be understood I think these arguments 1979), 187-89. rather than deductive.
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE are
they
as
it were
the
93
deceitful
"images"
(eid?la,
The
219d3).
"original" is left open in the Lysis, identity of this mysterious though an interpretation in terms of the good is hinted at (222c4, d5; cf. 221e3-4). and primarily
For
a fuller
dear
we
account now
turn
of what
Plato
as
regards
truly
to the Symposium.
IV
to the priestess which Socrates attributes great speech into two parts. falls The first and longer section Diotima presents or lesser mysteries of love based upon the universal the preliminary The
for happiness.
desire
The
concluding
of Diotima's
portion
speech,
designed for full initiates, describes the philosophic ascent to the Beautiful itself outside of time and place. It will be necessary to between get clear on the relation to reconcile before we attempt
the
exoteric
this
and
esoteric
with
theory
the
doctrines ac
tripartite
count of desire in the Republic. The initial account of love is prefaced by a general definition of desire (epithymia) as wanting (boulesthai) to get what one lacks or keep what one has (200b-e). Although bodily appetities other than sex
are
not mentioned,
them as well; money,
fame,
the
is broad
analysis
it is explicitly
extended
and
in addition
learning,
enough
to apply
to love of children, to erotic
desires
to
sports, proper
(205d, 208c ff.). Eros is first specified as desire for what is beauti ful, which includes or is identical to what is good (201c; cf. 204el, But
the possession of good things is happiness, nor admits this desire neither needs happiness;
206al). desire ther desire
explanation (205a). as for happiness
things
forever
and
Diotima
eros, as hence
then is, as
that the
pursuit
reinterprets the desire of
and all men of any the
universal
to possess
immortality
fur
good
by procre
ation in beauty, beauty either of body or of soul (206b7). At first sight this definition picks out the erotic as a special case of the general pursuit that all human
of happiness. become beings
But
since
pregnant
Diotima and have
goes on to claim a natural to desire
procreate, and that at the biological level this can be seen as a pursuit of immortality shared even by the animals, it turns out that specifically sexual activity connected with begetting counts less as a species lastingly
as a sample of eros structure The good.
than
conceived revealed
as the pursuit of what case of biological
in the
is
CHARLES H. KAHN
94 will
procreation artists,
in every
be found and
lawgivers
of eros.
type
live different
parents
ordinary
and
poets
Heroes, kinds
of erotic
lives because they identify in different ways what the Lysis calls "that which is truly and primarily dear," that for the sake of which are valued. things Thus the more popular characterized different by
all other
surveys
theory choices
of
the
different
forms
of
ultimate
erotic
object.
But the Lysis had pointed to a single proton philon. for the erotic makes unique enterprise object announces the last section, where Diotima "for
love, The
the
sake
universal
desire
for
lasting
other
its appearance final
the
mysteries of what
possession
informed
matters,
correctly of the beautiful.
session
these
The notion of a of mysteries exist" (210al). is good, by pro
tiful body to the love of all beautiful love
of souls,
being
wants,
the
then upwards
bodies,
led in
nature and pos love of one beau
the
concerning pass from
One must
in
only
in beauty, can be fully satisfied only if one is rightly
creation erotic
of which
love,
to the
of moral
of knowledge, to the and finally excellence, true knowledge of true beauty, the Beautiful itself. the phi Only can in contact Form the achieve with what every human losopher in possession
immortality
of the good,
since
the
only
Form is itself wholly good and lasting, imperishable (211a-b) and divine (211e3). Diotima's ladder of love is not only the true way to philosophic ness. That
knowledge; is, I suggest,
this present cal associates
doctrine
it is also
the
why Plato not in intimate
true
path
has
arranged conversation
to human to have
happi Socrates
with
philosophi but at a prominent social occasion (as in the Phaedo) a group in Athenian of leading before life and culture. The figures over crown the poets in the contest for the of victory philosopher's is not
wisdom public Plato
to be
claim chose
I believe,
the
this
the
occasion
some
of
achievement teacher
all men
of what
to reveal
narrow
his mature
but specialist want to know.
doctrine
for the first time) and in connection with it was
to make
clear
that
Beauty
alone,
highest
object not only of knowledge concern
momentous Diotima's
account
to all men of the
the reality
of Forms
a If (as
the Form of
of Forms
was
the
but also of desire, and hence of not
only to philosophers. ascent clearly implies
and lover's
that
it is
a single desire that begins by taking beautiful bodies as its object and ends with the beatific vision of the Form, just as in the Republic it
is a
turned
single around,
cognitive faculty from the shadows
that on
must the
be
converted, literally cave wall to the vision of
95
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE in the objects for procreation
fully
the desire
serves precisely to link the carnal lover to as participants of a common in the pursuit the metaphysical lover, the Platonic philosopher, us with of Plato's the problem But that presents
attain.
on the
consistency
as
of eros
characterization
lover
the metaphysical only goal, which can
The
sunlight. in beauty
of desire.
subject
V
The theoretical
of desire in the Symposium
unification
ismade
reason of desire between the bifurcation only by ignoring possible was in and the documented which and sensual Gorgias, appetite,
which reappears in the Phaedo before being replaced by the trifur in In following the Meno and Euthydemus cation of the Republic. as a rational desire for happiness desire the universal in effect considers of Diotima is good, the doctrine only the alto calls boulesthai, and ignores the Gorgias kind of desire which a con As Calliclean of the broader "appetites." spectrum gether which conflict of psychic the phenomena it also sequence ignores construing for what
of the richer so large in the Republic. Once we take account the conception how are we to reconcile of the Republic, psychology sources more or with Diotima's of desire of three there independent loom
doctrine
of eros,
which
but
ends
production
Beauty?
How
with the
Or must
we
admit
the
tripartite a new model
innovation, human motivation
of tripartition trace of it in the
hint
and
contemplation
passion that the
sium is simply incompatible with Now
sexuality
and
theory
truth, of eros
the Republic
drive
incorporeal
that
to be
is, for the
in the Sympo
of the Republic? is certainly
an
to the
of diversity justice there is a of conflict. Although there is as far as I can see no clear to do
designed the facts
in the Phaedo, Symposium
the
the psychology of
psychology
for
to re
the of
is the sexual drive rooted in the epithym?tikon into a rational
"transformed" Forms?
begins with
or
in any
earlier
dialogue.27
The
27 the at Phaedo of tripartition We have a foretaste 68cl-3, where else rational love of wisdom and learning here, philomathes (philosophos "love of the body" with the non-rational e.g., 67b4) is contrasted where, as "love of money and honor, either one or both." which is characterized as as loves soon these two "corporeal" Plato emerges splits Tripartition 82c5-8. Some scholars have found the apart, as he does in fact at Phaedo
CHARLES H. KAHN
96 the Symposium
is not whether
then
question
the Re
anticipates
There
are,
considerations
several
however,
this
with
it is incompatible public theory of desire but whether seem as to be. at first sight it might theory,
the
against
as
sumption that the two dialogues are flatly incompatible on the subject of desire. The first consideration is the doctrine of Forms, identical in the Symposium, Phaedo, and which is substantially be would It strange (though of course not impossible) Republic. that Plato three
have
should
one
dialogues,
his mature metaphysical presented a psychological contains of which
the
as a form
of philosophy
of eros
account
The
of the Symposium. theory of Diotima's last in the love part sophical taken for granted but actually contradicted tation
in
two. (I indicate below how the less fully articulated than that of with it.) Even more striking is two dialogues has certainly not
compatible with that of the other psychology of the Phaedo, though the Republic, is entirely consistent the fact that Plato in the other abandoned
in
theory doctrine
is not speech Plato in his by
in the Phaedo
of philo only not presen
and Republic.28
On this score it is not only the metaphysics but also the psychology None of this of the three dialogues that forms a unified whole. with is tripartition; but it compatible proves that Diotima's theory at
does
least
I suggest
an attempt justify two different ways
eros
be to take of
any
energy ian
not
part, single or motivation
id or
libido
as
as
for all
we might
an
a pool of be identified
proposal
eros will
complex The
with the relationship or first, quasi-Freudian,
parts, instinctual with
other
source
of psychic of the Freud
On my
energy. desire
two parts of eros
view
as the desire
on the model
rational
ta combine
nor
desire
undifferentiated
three
try
My first proposal will
to rational
as restricted but
the
in which
and Republic.
the theories of the Symposium
two.
to reconcile
alone, of the soul. is suggested
second but
by
in a
an
at reference the "three vaguer types of life" in the much or eros love of in to turn to who "those 205d money-making Symposium or love of wisdom So Cornford, (philosophia)". sports (philogymnastia) in G. Vlastos, "The Doctrine of Eros in Plato's Symposium", ed., Plato: A also 123. Cornford 2 Collection Critical Books, 1971), (Anchor Essays of at Symp. 208c3 with "the spirited the pursuit of fame (philotimia) connects we have only the raw part of the soul" (ibid., 125). But in the Symposium it is on its way to being organized in the Phaedo for tripartition; material in triads. 28 490b2-7. Phaedo 65c9, 66b7, 66e2-3, 67b9, 68a2-7, Rep. 6.485b-d, doctrine
of
97
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE
on the rechannelling of desire in Republic 6. passage important one a we in know incline "When desires direction, strongly person's in other directions, that they will be weaker like a stream of water directed to flow
one
into
off
towards
the pleasures sures of the
ing the channel learning
would
cording
to which
Taken
the of
part
of some
the notion
to direct
of bodily pleasure
standard the
source
for
leav
towards ac
of the Republic theory has its own distinctive
soul
de
to different
belong parts. pleasure bodily a generalized notion of eros as the common of of each part, we see how the strengthening
the desires
in one
desires
themselves
and
since sires, learning introduce But if we here
set
have
the
literally,
contradict each
desires
itself
if he
(6.485d).
Republic,
someone's
with be concerned like, they will will itself and abandon the by plea is truly a lover of wisdom (philo-sophos)" and
learning of the soul
body,
So when
channel.
in weakening for other desires in ex model is used Freud very by hydraulic of sublimation. Libidinal his concept says impulses, to one another like a network of communicating "are related
desires objects. plaining Freud,
will
direction
result
same
The
canals filled with fluid"; these impulses show a great "capacity for their
that
displacement," the
redirecting ble or acceptable. calls "sublimation,"
is, for abandoning same towards impulse This
original an aim that
sexual
aim
is more
and
accessi
is the process
of rechannelling which Freud the grounds the that society will recognize as a eros as view aim The of surrogate suggests parallel "higher."29 a common to be distributed between the energy pool of motivational more one means a for for that in such less three psychic way parts on
another.
out
force.
doctrinal
for his
to rechannelling is not a random is of central The view expressed
reference
Plato's
theory
of the virtues
and
their
unity
in the Republic and also in the Phaedo make
psychologically and love for wisdom
virtues:
other
desirable perfection
29 viere,
will
pursuits
to one who of
plausible truth will
in wisdom.
importance Both here
the philosopher's his possession of the other
claim
guarantee seem petty
In comparison
S. Freud, A General Introduction (Garden City, N.Y., 1943), 302.
with
(see 69a-b) this view helps to
Plato's
and
that
other
is gratified by intercourse with
the Forms.
image
with
such
to Psychoanalysis
less
pleasures
the being and an object
trans.
nei
Joan Ri
CHARLES H. KAHN
98 ther any ance
profit serious will
nor
nor
and sensual will hold luxury indulgence so that the virtues of and temptations, honesty temper be trivial of this redirection of desire into consequences power
eros. The philosophical how the pursuit of wisdom sible
for moral The
of eros
self, would
reasons,
psychology the
tyrant's
represents less called
of Oedipal dreams recognition one of the more to explain help
of the Republic,
the
in the desires
motivation, psychic
unity of psychic
of each
to Plato.
of the divergence and consequently
conflict
control
that
are
the
the
other
two with
strictly incompatible sium in terms of the universal
everyone we
find
in
passion
part.30 It would
three
parts
to account
nothing center of attention
(205a).
parts. psychic the presentation boul?sis
this view of
do nothing to account as independent sources for in books
Nor does it shed any clear light on the dynamics can
in the
energy that finds
as itmay be, I very much doubt whether
can be attributed radical
points
is essentially criminal and destructive and of is neverthe eros, opposite philosophical the very same name: er?s or lust (9.572e5, 573b7, d4). nomenclature for the two polar extremes would then
Attractive eros
It
noticed).
puzzling
that the dominant
namely
point to eros as the underlying expression
already
it
soul, which the extreme
by identical
This
respon
(the tripartition
psychology
the
also
to see
as a pool of libidinal is attractive energy of the fascinating with Freudian parallel
in view
insights at other points of Plato's and
us
permits be causally
virtue.
conception
for many
image of rechannelling so understood might
the
for of
facts
of
4, 8 and
by which
9.
reason
Above
for good
is all, this view in the Sympo on the part of things
of eros
For this is just that rational desire for the good
in the Gorgias,
Meno,
and Euthydemus
as prefiguring
both
Aristotle's
boul?sis and Plato's conception of the logistikon in the What these parallels with Aristotle and with other Republic. works of Plato strongly suggest is that eros in the Symposium 30 This Freudian eros in terms of libido was of Platonic interpretation See his "Group Psychology and the Analysis accepted by Freud himself. of the Ego," in the Standard Edition of Freud's work, vol. 18, p. 91, where he cites studies by Nachmansohn and Pfister that treat Plato as a precur sor of psychoanalysis. is a similar comment There in the preface to the on Sexuality", 4th edition of "Three Essays Standard Edition I 7, p. 134. am indebted here to some unpublished work by G. Santas.
99
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE be seen
should directed more
as undifferentiated
not
concern by a rational of rational conception
for what eros
can
that
as desire
but
energy psychic is good. And
it is only this to the close
do
justice between the erotic ascent of the upon coincidence, verging of and the the Cave and the Sun. progress cognitive Symposium can eros in then becomes: The question how the interpretation of parallel,
terms
of rational
desire
posium and the rechannelling I want which
the
suggest and cognitive so
that
every level, over the other reason
native
parts
of desire
"enslaving"
And
As we
phenomenon.
it is not
for
by
their
own
of
as alter
have
ends
rule
seen,
it is
that the in the
de
of
lies behind the metaphors force
but
by persuasion,
for its own judgment of what
is beneficial,
by
that
and thus can harmonize principles and integrate the psyche soul," by its by its "care for the entire one of what is for each and for the whole "knowledge advantageous reason
which
can
rule
over
the
is good and desirable
reason
viant lives of Republic 8-9: that iswhat gaining acceptance
to degree in hand go hand the
emphasizes
components of desire and rechannelling of the soul can be understood
in using
reason.
in the Sym
in the Republic?
desiderative the
our judgment of what succeed
of eros
scope
that
solution
parts of the same
descriptions
by perverting lower
a
to
at
the broad
explain
the
other
is common to all three" (441e5,442c6).
What
lies behind the
and the rule of reason is the com of psychic metaphors harmony or resistance of emotional interference absence to, the with, plete our is in rational of what best interest. appraisal have
We reason
sl vivid
in the Phaedo
to be enslaved
by
the
lower
of what it means for description of this the which in parts soul,
dialogue are presented as the desires (epithymiai) connected with the body. The philosopher, who is here designated as the philo the mathes, and fastened from which (82e-83a). bodily these
will of learning, that his soul is fettered recognize in a cunning to the body constructed of desire, prison it by gentle he must release admonition and persuasion as far as possible will abstain from The philosopher lover
pleasures,
and desires because he sees that to undergo pains, one feels is to suffer harm: "when in cognitive
experiences or pain concerning pleasure as clearly real this regard thing tense
a given and
true,
object, although
one
to
is forced it is not.
. . .
Each pleasure and pain is like a nail which clasps and rivets the soul to the body
and makes
it corporeal,
so that
it takes
for
real what
CHARLES H. KAHN
100 ever
the body cave
one's
constructed and
ambition
the
by
sensual
for honor:
competition
favorite
lightened
it is enlightened
Unless
(83c-d).31
reason is obliged to live in the darkness of the cogni
by philosophy, tive
to be so"
declares
pursuits.
or by thymos, appetites one's ontology is affected as reason
Conversely,
that good moral
(and assuming
of the
lower
by by en
is progressively
is also available),
training
will
the guidance of the cognitive aspect parts accept own reason to what is their will and moder concerning advantage to the judgment of reason. ate their own claims is This according as the rechannelling described of de phenomenon is the of half reinforcement sire. reason's progressive (The other own preoccupation It is not that with and the Good.) knowledge or political is transformed ambition into the love sensual appetite one
half
of
the
these by definition, But they now objects.
of wisdom; proper reason. directed economy How
a result
As
to its own
of
this
proper
The
remain
operate
within
to their
the
limits
the
desires
by assigned of reason
subordination, will be predominant
place
prison-house
is explained of carnal
own
attached
in the over-all
object
of the psyche. takes this change
the Symposium.
desires
in the
ladder
in
of love
is represented
desire
by the first stage, in which the initiate is enamoured of a single beautiful body (210a). But a skillful erotic guide will use the initial triggering
effect
sense-perception get the lover exemplar
of
sexual
in the Phaedo's to see his
desired
of a desirable
of effect (like the triggering account in order to of Recollection) as as an and hence object beautiful,
attraction
principle
that
is to be found
as
elsewhere
This is the first step in the cognitive liberation of the rational principle that will permit it to turn its attention towards its proper object. What is affected by this first step is not the sensual desire to the epithym?tikon) but the as such (which belongs essentially
well.
cognitive
component
to
the extent
that
it represents
the rational
prin
to a lovely body, as ciple temporally trapped in the attachment as an object of to real and hence be and good something judged misplaced
31
rational
desire.
What
happens
in the
course
of erotic
cites William James In this connection (who Shorey appropriately all turn to the most in Locke and "Among sensations, Berkeley): appeals or of pain." W. James, are those productive of pleasure belief-compelling 2 in The Principles 1950), 306, cited by Shorey (Dover, of Psychology, in G. Vlastos, "Plato's Ethics," ed., Plato 2, p. 28 n. 129.
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE is that this rational element
initiation
for a single
passion
The
soul as more precious
that
cess of altering
bodies:
this
intense
it a small
of
weakening,
in a recognition
sensual
by an
essentially
under which
in
it is the
movement.
In
lust to
of desire from physical
place
the description
mat
of "beauty
to the upward
is the key
takes
passion
metaphysical
in all
relax
thinking
hence
then
the rechannelling
the Symposium,
same"
than that in body" (210b6-7): again
r??valuation
cognitive
"upwards," first
shift to a higher form of beauty
and
devaluation, continues process
the
and
stage it and
despising
body,
is directed "he will
in the
result
desire.
"one
this
Thus the cognitive
ter" (210b5-6). will
as
of beauty recognition the lover has reached
to the when
101
pro
epistemic
the object
is initially
the lover's attention from a view of the and thus converting desired, a as to of individual world bodies vision of the incorpo consisting from which this phenomenal real principles world derives whatever and
beauty
structure
rational
it possesses.
tion requires just the sort of dialectical so
6-7,
Republic images
that
the
as images
precisely
This
come
initiate may of a higher Beauty.
to see Like
a cognitive is essentially Symposium enterprise, to an inadequate attachment from rational desire to its proper
true
"the
goal,
in
the
beautiful
the conversion
the education of eros in the
of the "eye of the soul" in the Republic,
redirection
redirec
cognitive
exercise that is described
knowledge
the
liberation
of
and its object which is knowl
edge of Beauty itself" (211c7). What the Symposium makes clear is what is only partially indicated by the description of rechannelling in the Republic: the same time
of enlightenment for reason of reeducation for the desires.32
the process
that
a process
is at
VI
has view
In conclusion, certain definite of reason
ego and
id.
I want
and
The
advantages desire and
advantage
a faculty of cognition
32 account
to suggest
that over
both also
over cases
in both
and judgment
Irwin, Plato's Moral of the ascent.
Theory,
Plato's
theory
of desire
the Humean-Davidsonian the Freudian is that
conception reason for Plato
of as
is at the same time equipped
167-71,
gives
a partially
analogous
CHARLES H. KAHN
102
if not simply identical to, its own autonomous with, as good the recognition of an action Hence vation. or as a component to contribution one's welfare?is of in favorable
and
reason,
the act.
performing us relieves
the
of
The icant.
decision
advantage For Freud,
"the
issues
motivation, in reason
is after
ego
for itself
a pre-existent
in action.33
seems
view
a
ipso facto
this practical power Admitting of artificial necessity inventing over Freud's
of moti
or beneficial?
a sufficient
circumstances
a rational
whenever
desire
source
to me
even more
a part
all only
of the
signif id, a part
purposively modified by its proximity to the dangers of reality. From a dynamic point of view it isweak; it borrows its energy from the
Freud
id."34
of rational
principle begins
with
babies,
a
of the ego, as the conception his because of he knowledge, genetic approach: sense of "reality." who have a very weak But a such
has
limited
of rational from an in faculty cognition to understand is poorly rational equipped pleasure-principle to account unable for the development and wholly decision-making the motiva and mathematics. of theoretical science By deriving theory fantile
tion sires
which
for
derives
rational
to know
the
the
knowledge truth and
and
action
from
irreducible de basic, is good, and on the other structure of reason the from
what
obtain
the content and by deriving as structured of intelligibil of things by objective principles more can account for the existence science and than of do ity, Plato for some people, for example, He can also explain why, philosophy. hand
nature
for a devoted the world, when we
scientist,
and why, somehow
know very well
for all of us, cannot
is the most
knowledge bring
is the best
it is such ourselves
is best is seen
thing in
a frustrating experience to do something that we
thing for us to do.
of akrasia in an experience involved for what desire tration of a rational
important
The frustration
understood
as the
frus
to be good.35
33 rea in conceiving For a sensitive discussion of the issues involved see C. M. Korsgaard, son as a source of motivation about "Scepticism 83 (1986): 5-25. The Journal Practical Reason," of Philosophy 34 on Psycho-analysis, trans. Lectures Introductory Freud, New 107. York: W. J. H. Sprott Norton, 1933), (New 35 or eudaimonia If one appeals here to a standing desire for welfare we have in effect Aristotle's to explain notion the efficacy of deliberation, of boul?sis or rational desire, which gets focussed on a particular action by a judgment to act (prohairesis), the fusion of issuing in a choice or decision reason and desire the fusion, saw Plato, recognizing (NE 6. 2,1139b4-5). no advantage in splitting the two apart. On the question of whether his see Section VII. is defensible, position
103
PLATO'S THEORY OF DESIRE VII
simply
that
Although content,
surely they and the contrast
tudes; as a difference
thought?
propositional
atti propositional be vividly characterized
them
can
of "fit":
the urge to know the truth, which manifests
could be identified with as in a judgement reason that Plato of as a single
thought
same
different
very
between
of rational the
is or
the world
require construed
grant
may
represent
of desire
our beliefs to fit the world, "We require but to fit our desires."36 If the desire is for good as an effort to change to see how it is hard it the world,
we
itself
have
two
the
of judgement
element
in any analysis
a desire
and
to the
happens
is fundamental a belief
of
be
What
incoherent.
belief
suggested, by a partisan as a form of reason conception
It might Plato's
Postscript. that factor view,
to what and
psychic
is in fact the
desire
case.
the
knowledge it does not seem
principle,
even
So
for
if we be
might coherent
to
identify this principle with desire for the good. Plato might well respond by suggesting that desire for good is to be
own
our
and
capacity
to change to "imitate
effort
pattern: and this will
judgements
include
in conformity
to conform
but reality the divine"
by setting
our
setting with
the
cognitive nature of
Coming to know the world as it iswould be part of what
things. means
us
for
to
knowing
the good
the
imitate
as it is will
world
an
to an objective in order, soul
ourselves our
as
not
construed
But
divine.
include knowing what and
loving
it will
be only
for
Plato
is good.
knowing
At
notionally
not
it the
the limit, psycho
logically distinct. Much
more of
something prepared love and
to the
would this
sort
interpret climb out
have
to be
is surely his elaborate of the
cave
said
such
a view. unless
by Plato, the between parallel as a mere coincidence.37
implied
The 36 Richard
to defend
University
we ladder
But are of
of Pennsylvania
The Thread of Life (Cambridge: Harvard Uni Wollheim, versity37 Press, 1986), 53. An earlier version of this paper was delivered at the University of Helsinki in March 1983 and before various audiences since then, including a lecture at the Catholic of America in October 1983. I am University indebted to my auditors for many valuable and am particularly comments, to Myles and Alexander Nehamas for their detailed grateful Burnyeat criticism.