Download Juslin, P. N. (2003). Five Facets of Musical Expression. a Psychologist's Perspective on Music Performance....
Psychology of Music http://pom.sagepub.com
Five Facets of Musical Expression: A Psychologist's Perspective on Music Performance Patrik N. Juslin Psychology of Music 2003; 31; 273 DOI: 10.1177/03057356030313003 The online version of this article can be found at: http://pom.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/31/3/273
Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com
On behalf of:
Society for Education, Music and Psychology Research
Additional services and information for Psychology of Music can be found at: Email Alerts: http://pom.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://pom.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations (this article cites 44 articles hosted on the SAGE Journals Online and HighWire Press platforms): http://pom.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/31/3/273
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
273
A RT I C L E
Five facets of musical expression: a psychologist’s perspective on music performance
Psychology of Music Psychology of Music Copyright © Society for Education, Music and Psychology Research vol (): ‒ [- () :; ‒; ]
PA T R I K N . J U S L I N UPPSALA UNIVERSITY
A B S T R A C T The aim of this article is to outline a psychological approach to expression in music performance that could help to provide a solid foundation for the teaching of expressive skills in music education. Drawing on previous research, the author suggests that performance expression is best conceptualized as a multi-dimensional phenomenon consisting of five primary components: (a) Generative rules that function to clarify the musical structure; (b) Emotional expression that serves to convey intended emotions to listeners; (c) Random variations that reflect human limitations with regard to internal time-keeper variance and motor delays; (d) Motion principles that prescribe that some aspects of the performance (e.g. timing) should be shaped in accordance with patterns of biological motion; and (e) Stylistic unexpectedness that involves local deviations from performance conventions. An analysis of performance expression in terms of these five components – collectively referred to as the GERMS model – has important implications for research and teaching of music performance. K E Y W O R D S : computational modelling, emotion, expression, music education, music
performance
He put the bow to his instrument . . . and then, the first notes, bold and fiery, sang through the hall. At once the spell began to work. Was this really the music of a violin? What grandeur in these slurred notes, what absolute purity! There came roulades of double-stop harmonic notes, and a long run across four octaves, played staccato in a single stroke of the bow . . . Then came a noble, moving theme, which sounded as though a human voice was singing . . . After the seemingly endless applause had subsided, Paganini began to play the second movement. It was an adagio, and showed the virtuoso from quite a different angle. There were none of the devilish tricks that had stunned the audience during the first movement. A sublime, angelic song of great noblesse and simplicity touched the hearts of the listeners . . . The notes followed one another as
sempre :
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
274
Psychology of Music 31(3) though growing out of the instrument, and it seemed incredible . . . that this wooden object was not an integral part of the man who played it, a part of his very soul . . . The audience sat as though paralysed until the rhythm of a graceful rondo changed their mood . . . an infinitely tender pizzicato accompanied the melody, and it finally soared away into a happy dance tune. (Farga, 1969: 171–2)
In this description of a music performance by Nicolo Paganini in Vienna 1828, many of the recurrent ideas about musical expression are included: the captivating experience, the voice-like quality of certain musical instruments, the idea that music may alter a listener’s moods, the close connection between music and expression of emotions, the notion that expression is embodied in acoustic parameters of the performance, the belief that expression ‘springs from the performer’s very soul’, the importance of the musical piece itself in shaping the expression, and the ‘devilish tricks’ commonly attributed to the expressive virtuoso.1 Could researchers ever hope to explain this seemingly inexplicable phenomenon? Judging from the comments by some performers, we would be inclined to think not (Dubal, 1985). As noted by Sloboda (2000), ‘the folk psychology of the musical world can often seem to be designed to keep the answers shrouded in mystery’ (p. 398). Yet I believe that it is not only possible for psychologists to investigate musical expression successfully, it is a matter of responsibility. I argue that the primary aim of a psychological approach to music performance should be to explain performance expression in order to provide a solid foundation for teaching of expression in music education. To explain musical expression may be difficult, but it is no more difficult than many other problems that psychologists struggle with every day (e.g. explaining consciousness). For much too long, psychologists have deferred to philosophers in matters concerning expression. I believe it is time for psychologists to reclaim the study of expression.2 Many, if not all, issues concerning expression are such that they can be resolved empirically. Why do I regard expression as the primary topic? Because expression is largely what makes music performance worthwhile. It is expression that makes people go through all sorts of trouble to hear human performances rather than the ‘dead-pan’ renditions of computers; it is expression that makes possible new and insightful interpretations of familiar works; and it is on the basis of expressive features that we prefer one performer rather than another. Moreover, questionnaire research indicates that most musicians and music teachers regard expression as the most important aspect of a performer’s skills (Lindström et al., in press; Laukka, 2003). However, despite the importance attributed to expression in music performance, there is evidence that expressive skills are often ignored in teaching (e.g. Persson, 1993; Rostwall and West, 2001; Tait, 1992). As I have noted elsewhere (e.g. Juslin and Persson, 2002), one reason may be that teachers lack a theory of performance expression that can guide teaching. The problem is compounded by
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
the fact that musical expression involves tacit knowledge that is difficult to convey from teachers to students. Research on expression could help to render the tacit knowledge explicit. Rather than surrender to individual differences in expressive ability in the name of musical talent, we could address them through theoretically informed teaching. Thus, a proper and scientifically grounded understanding of the mechanisms that underlie musical expression has scientific as well as social and educational implications (Sloboda, 2000). In this article, I consider the role of the performer in musical expression. I want to convince the reader that performance expression is a problem amenable to empirical investigation, and that psychological theory is critical to an understanding of this problem. Looking back, psychologists have tended to approach performance expression mainly by measuring various acoustic variables of music performances (e.g. Gabrielsson, 1999, 2003, this issue). Often, a purely descriptive approach has been taken, in accordance with the tradition first established by Seashore (1938) and his co-workers. As a consequence, the notion of expression has been poorly conceptualized.3 Matters of expression have largely been reduced to tables or graphs of acoustic data, whereas the question of what these data actually tell us about the origins of musical expression has somehow been lost. But perhaps psychology is uniquely suited to investigating expression? After all, psychology was right from the beginning studying the kinds of psychophysical relationships that seem to underlie musical expression (Leahey, 1987). Yet, psychology has arguably not fulfilled its potential role in helping to provide a theoretical organization of the field. In my view, a psychological approach to performance expression should consider how this phenomenon reflects basic human abilities and characteristics that are not necessarily unique to the musical domain. Recent research reviewed in this article will provide some support for this view. The remainder of this article is structured as follows: first, I provide working definitions of interpretation, expression and communication, and consider problems in performance research that have prevented cumulative progress. Second, I outline a psychological approach to musical expression that distinguishes five aspects of expression. Unfortunately there are few attempts to integrate these different aspects; and so, I outline a meta theory of music performance, which is an attempt to integrate different aspects of expression. Not very surprisingly, empirical findings derived from this model suggest that emotion is a major aspect of expression. Therefore I briefly review findings about emotion in music performance. Finally, I consider various implications of a psychological approach for performance research and music education, and also acknowledge some limitations of this approach.
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
275
276
Psychology of Music 31(3)
Working definitions Interpretation, expression and communication are complex concepts, and no matter what I say about them here, I am sure that this article will not be the final word on these topics. However, for the practical purposes of this article, we need to have at least preliminary working definitions of each term. The term interpretation typically refers to the individualistic shaping of a piece according to the musical ideas of the performer (Palmer, 1997: 119). This might involve an intention to express something (e.g. an idea, an emotion) beyond the musical structure (Gabrielsson, 1999), but such expression is usually accomplished through the ways in which the structure is articulated (in how it is played). The process of interpretation is still little investigated (but see Hallam, 1995; Persson, 1993), although it seems to be influenced by both ‘internal’ (e.g. emotions, wanting to express something personal) and ‘external’ factors (e.g. musical style, the structure of the piece, the composer’s intentions) (Lindström et al., in press; Persson, 2001: 278–81). Expression, in my view, refers to a set of perceptual qualities that reflect psychophysical relationships between ‘objective’ properties of the music, and ‘subjective’ (or, rather, objective but partly person-dependent) impressions of the listener. Expression does not reside solely in the acoustic properties of the music (different listeners may perceive the expression differently), nor does it reside solely in the mind of the listener (different listeners usually agree about the general nature of the expression in a performance). Expression depends on both of these factors, in ways that, although complex, can be modelled in a systematic fashion (Juslin, 2000). Our perception of expressive music performances reminds us, somehow, of the ways humans express their states of mind in real life (why would we otherwise use the term expression in the first place?). Indeed, we have an ‘anthropomorphic’ tendency to perceive expressive form even in inanimate objects (e.g. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1989). Occasionally the perception of an expressive performance will also evoke an emotion in the listener (he or she is ‘moved’), or even an aesthetic response (a more complex and profound response that involves emotional, cognitive and social factors; Konecˆni, 1979), but such a response is not required for a listener to hear the music as expressive (Davies, 1994). The emotion induced in the listener may be the same as that expressed (through emotional contagion; Juslin, 2001), or it may be a complementary response (Juslin and Zentner, 2002). As Clynes (1977: 60) notes, when we hear a convincing expression, this is perceived as ‘sincerity’; we therefore tend to feel sympathy for the performer of the music. If the general notion of expression is accepted, the question is: what does music express. A survey of the literature suggests a large number of different ideas about what music may express. Music has been regarded as expressive of emotion, physical aspects (motion, force), tension and release, personality characteristics, beauty, events, objects, musical conventions, religious belief and social conditions (Gabrielsson and Juslin, 2003). A generous view on
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
expressivity would hold that there is truth to all of these ideas as long as there are individual listeners who claim that they find music expressive of these qualities. One problem with this generous approach is that it tends to embrace any arbitrary association that one could have to a music performance. This would be simply a form of conditioning that does not relate to the performance as such; it says more about the listener than it says about the music. It seems more fruitful to look for expressive aspects that relate to the nature of the music, at least if we want to explain performance expression. A more restrictive approach to expression that is common in research holds that music is expressive of a certain quality only to the extent that there is some minimum level of agreement among the listeners (presumably because there is something in the actual performance that gives rise to similar listener percepts). Thus, for example, we might agree that the slow movement of Beethoven’s Eroica symphony is expressive of, say, sadness (although the expression could, of course, change rapidly during the piece). In such cases of intersubjective agreement, we may be inclined to say that ‘this piece has a sad expression’. But note that expression (as defined here) does not require an expressive intention. The concept of communication (of emotion, for instance), in contrast, goes further: accurate communication, I believe, requires that there is both a performer’s intention to express a specific concept and recognition of this concept by a listener. Perhaps, it may seem strange to talk about communication accuracy in the context of music. Still, most performers are probably – or should be – worried about whether their musical interpretation is actually perceived by listeners the way they intended it. (What is the purpose of a specific interpretation if every listener fails to perceive it?) The performer may, for instance, wish to highlight an emotional character that is latent in the composition. The extent to which performer and listener agree about the emotional expression of the performance could pragmatically be seen as a measure of the accuracy of the communication. (Precisely which perceptual qualities I think are involved in performance expression is discussed later in the description of a psychological approach.)
Problems in research on performance expression To do music performance justice as a meaningful event in a particular time and place, with certain individuals taking part (Small, 1999), we would have to take into account a very large set of complicated real-world relationships. To get some sense of the difficulties involved in such an endeavour, consider the list of factors that – in principle – may influence expression (Table 1). As can be seen, this includes numerous factors related to the piece, the instrument, the performer, the listener and the performance context (for further discussion of factors that might be relevant, see Gabrielsson, 2003, this issue; Rink, 2003, this issue). To model all the factors simultaneously may be
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
277
278
Psychology of Music 31(3)
outright impossible. To simplify matters, researchers have been forced to bracket most of the factors listed in Table 1, and to focus instead on core principles of performance that transcend a particular time and place (in the Western world, at least). In practice, this has meant focusing on measurement of performances, with occasional attempts to relate the measures to other aspects (e.g. the score, the performer’s intention, the listener’s perception, etc.). Yet, even with this narrow focus researchers have been struggling to account for the nature of a typical performance of music. Why is this so? Clearly, there are many problems that performance researchers are confronted with. First, it is usually difficult to obtain large samples of music TA B L E
1 Examples of factors that might influence expression in music performance
Type
Examples of factors
Piece-related
The musical composition itself Notational variants of the piece Consultations with composer or composer’s written comments Musical style/genre
Instrument-related
Acoustic parameters available Instrument-specific aspects of timbre, pitch, etc. Technical difficulties of the instrument
Performer-related
The performer’s structural interpretation The performer’s expressive intention with regard to the mood of the piece The performer’s emotion-expressive style The performer’s technical skill The performer’s motor precision The performer’s mood while playing The performer’s interaction with co-performers The performer’s perception of/interaction with audience
Listener-related
The listener’s music preferences The listener’s music expertise The listener’s personality The listener’s current mood The listener’s state of attention
Context-related
Acoustics Sound technology Listening context (e.g. recording, concert) Other individuals present Visual performance conditions Larger cultural and historic setting Whether the performance is formally evaluated
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
performances from expert musicians (however, see Repp, 1998). This problem can be partly overcome through large investments of time and money, and also by trying to conduct research more on the performers’ own terms. Second, even if we do manage to obtain sufficiently large samples of performances, it is a difficult and time-consuming task to analyse all relevant acoustic variables (Palmer, 1997). There are currently some promising attempts to develop computer algorithms for automatic extraction of such variables (e.g. Friberg et al., 2002), which might help researchers to analyse larger samples of performances quickly. Thus this problem may eventually be solved. The most serious problem for studies of performance is perhaps not to obtain sufficient amounts of data, but rather to find ways of interpreting the wealth of data in a meaningful way (Gabrielsson and Juslin, 1996). It is here that psychological theory can make a crucial contribution to how we conceive of expression. I think that the greatest impediment to progress in explaining expression has been the common tendency to regard expression as a single entity, a homogeneous natural category. Given the controversy that has surrounded the concept of expression throughout history (Davies, 1994), it is perhaps understandable that many researchers have tended to leave the concept undefined or simply ‘defined’ it in terms of ‘deviations from the score’. But it is troubling to note how many studies have treated expression as a mysterious quality of which there is simply ‘more’ or ‘less’, without specifying what is meant by the term expression (the expression is simply ‘appropriate’, ‘exaggerated’, or ‘lacking’). There is no serious consideration of what is expressed, or how it is expressive, which implies that there is only one way of performing expressively (by ‘appropriate expressive deviations’). At times, it seems that expression is simply equated with everything that might be good about a performance, but what is good is, of course, not specified. What is at stake is not the usefulness of the generic word ‘expression’ as such, it is rather whether this is the most fruitful level at which to investigate and teach expression (‘Put some expression into it’). I reject on empirical grounds the idea that music can be expressive ‘in general’ without being expressive in some particular way, because any music performance has certain acoustic features that renders it different in expression from a performance with different acoustic features. (Two performances with the same rated level of ‘expressivity’ or ‘emotionality’ may exhibit quite different acoustic characteristics, and may be perceived quite differently with regard to how they are expressive.) Even more important, the expressive variations that are typically found in a human music performance are not all of the same kind; they do not all share the same origins, and they should therefore not all be taught in the same manner. In my estimation, the ‘single-factor approach’ to expression has contributed to the fragmented state of affairs in studies of performance. It has not encouraged integrative attempts even among researchers who have recognized that expression is multidimensional. I argue that a satisfactory
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
279
280
Psychology of Music 31(3)
model should incorporate the fact that expression is a multi-dimensional phenomenon including distinct components of information. Precisely what these components are is a theoretical and empirical matter. In the following discussion, I take stock of what previous research on music performance can teach us about this problem.
A psychological approach to performance expression The ultimate goal of research on expression in music performance is to understand what, exactly, the performer ‘adds’ to a written piece of music. It may be instructive to look closer at what this endeavour actually entails. Performance researchers are faced with complex patterns of behaviour; they must describe and explain the nature and origin of intricate patterns of variability in acoustic measures shown over the time-course of a performance of music (see Figure 1). The problem is that ‘using measurements of actual performances alone, it is difficult to separate the effects of combined, though psychologically distinct, expressive actions’ (Thompson et al., 1989: 64). This explains why single-factor conceptions of expression have been so prevalent. %
Note. The solid line shows the first performance, the dotted line the repetition. (Reproduced with kind permission of the Royal Swedish Academy of Music) 1 Deviations in timing from mechanical performance in a performance of Mozart’s Piano Sonata in A Major (K 331) from a classic study by Gabrielsson (1987).
FIGURE
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
As long as the expressive features are simply lumped together as ‘expressive deviations from the score’, it is hard to reach beyond a single factor. One heuristic tool could be to rely on the advice of professional performers, as shown by the work by Sundberg (1988) and co-workers. However, performers are commonly unable to explain the details of how they apply expressive features (Sloboda, 1996). Psychologists early realized the limitations of introspection in explaining psychological mechanisms (e.g. Leahey, 1987), and many of the mechanisms that underlie music performance are clearly not available to introspection. What is needed, I believe, is a psychological theory of expression. What would such a theory look like? First, a psychological approach would involve an attempt to go beyond the performance and to consider the nature of the person behind the performance. ‘What are the proximate and ultimate causes of the behaviour in the performer, and how can we make sense of this behaviour from what we know about humans?’ Second (and partly as a consequence of what we know about humans), it would have to be a component approach. Some researchers have suggested a general mechanism to account for performance expression (e.g. Todd, 1992), though it seems that a single mechanism cannot successfully account for all the variability in a music performance. Such a model is bound to be incomplete in certain respects, as indicated by some recent studies (Clarke and Windsor, 2000; Juslin, 2000; Repp, 1989; Van Oosten, 1993; Thompson et al., 1989). A careful review of the literature suggests that performance expression is better thought of as a multi-dimensional phenomenon, consisting of five components of expression that I collectively refer to as the GERMS model. The five components are summarized in the following sections (for more extensive reviews, see Gabrielsson, 1999, 2003, this issue). GENERATIVE RULES ( G )
One function of performance expression may be to convey the musical structure to listeners as clearly as possible. This forms the basis of the so-called generative approach (Clarke, 1988). In this line of research, expression is regarded as rule-based transformations of nominal score values that originate in the performer’s cognitive representation of the hierarchical structure. By means of variations in such acoustic variables as timing, dynamics and articulation, a performer is able to clarify group boundaries (Gabrielsson, 1987), metrical accents (Sloboda, 1983) and harmonic structure (Palmer, 1996). One of the most robust findings is that tempo variations (rubato) have a strong tendency to be determined by the phrase structure; phrase endings are usually marked with decreases in tempo, and the amount of slowing reflects the depth of embedding in the hierarchical structure (Todd, 1985; see also Figure 1). This is the most well-studied aspect of expression, and to the extent that a performer aims to clarify the structure, we may explain part of the variance in the acoustic features. However, the absence of a generally accepted system for structural analysis still makes prediction difficult.
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
281
282
Psychology of Music 31(3)
Furthermore, rules for the transformation of a generative structure into patterns of expression are highly dependent on conventions related to specific musical styles. The generative approach dominated research on music performance until the 1990s (for excellent reviews, see Clarke, 1988, 1995). But there is clearly more to expression than merely the conveying of structure (Shaffer, 1992; see also Rink, 2003, this issue). EMOTIONAL EXPRESSION ( E )
A second function of performance expression might be to render the performance with a particular emotional expression. As noted by Shaffer (1992), ‘a performer can be faithful to the structure and at the same time have the freedom to shape its moods’ (p. 265). A series of studies in the 1990s indicated that professional performers are able to communicate discrete emotions to listeners. To accomplish this goal, the performers use a large number of acoustic variables in the performance. For example, if a performer would like to express tenderness in a performance, he or she may use slow tempo, low sound level, legato articulation, ‘soft’ timbre, slow tone attacks, regular timing, reduced contrasts between ‘long’ and ‘short’ notes, and an intense vibrato (for a review, see Juslin, 2001). This component of expression is actually the last to receive attention in performance research, but it could well be one of the most crucial as far as music performers and listeners are concerned (see Lindström et al., in press; Persson, 2001). One reason for the relative neglect of this component may be that it not always operates on the explicit level that is required in order to study it empirically. (The emotion component is discussed in more detail in a later section of this article.) RANDOM VARIABILITY ( R )
A third aspect of performance expression that has mostly been studied in domains other than music is random variability. It appears to be generally agreed that human music performance is not controlled by a completely deterministic motor-system (e.g. Repp, 1997a; Yamada, 1998). Performance expression always contains some random fluctuations, although they may be quite small. How is this feature relevant in understanding expression, especially since practice usually aims at minimizing error? From an aesthetical point of view, random variations contribute to the ‘living’ character of music – that slight unpredictability that makes each performance absolutely unique. Research on human limitations in perceptual-motor skills, mainly studies of isochronous interval finger tapping, have revealed that the random variations have certain characteristics: (1) the magnitude of random fluctuations increases with inter-onset-interval duration, so that longer intervals tend to yield larger deviations (Wing and Kristofferson, 1973; see also Repp, 1997a); (2) there is a negative first-order dependency with regard to interonset-interval durations; that is, a performed interval that is shorter than the mean is usually followed by one that is longer than the mean, yielding zig-zag
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
patterns (Madison, 2000); (3) there is a positive higher-order dependency, or tempo drift, over time (a linear trend that can be extracted from tapping data; Madison, 2000); and (4) the random fluctuations may be successfully simulated by a combination of 1/f noise and white noise, two kinds of random variability (Gilden et al., 1995). Although these random variations are subtle – in expert performance, at least – they do contribute to the sound of a human music performance. Therefore, if we really intend to model performance expression, this component should be included also (Juslin et al., 2002). MOTION PRINCIPLES ( M )
A fourth aspect of performance expression is motion. There is a common assumption that music and motion are closely related to one another. However, this hypothesis needs to be made more specific to be useful. Shove and Repp (1995) argue that ‘without proper constraint the idea that change in music induces an experience of motion has little explanatory power’ (p. 58). One way to constrain the hypothesis is to limit it to a specific kind of motion called biological motion (e.g. Johansson, 1973). This refers to the dynamic patterns of movement that are characteristic of humans. It should be noted that such patterns in music performance may be of two kinds. First, it can be assumed that performers intentionally (though not necessarily consciously) try to re-create such patterns. Shove and Repp propose that an aesthetically pleasing performance is ‘one whose expressive microstructure satisfies basic constraints of biological motion’ (p. 78). One example is the shaping of final ritardandi. Friberg and Sundberg (1999) showed that final ritardandi of music performances follow a mathematical function similar to that of runners’ decelerations. (This was also the ritardando function preferred by listeners in a listening test.) A second kind of biological motion is non-intentional patterns of variability that reflect anatomical constraints of the body in connection with motor requirements of specific musical instruments (e.g. Penel and Drake, 1999). STYLISTIC UNEXPECTEDNESS ( S )
An additional way in which a performance may be expressive involves the fact that musical emotions often occur when musical expectations are violated in some way. Thus, Meyer (1956) suggested that expressive variations in a music performance may serve an aesthetic function by ‘delaying an expected resolution’, or otherwise ‘creating psychological tension’ (p. 206). This could happen when a performer deviates from stylistic expectations with regard to performance conventions for a certain part of the structure. For example, the performer might be expected to clarify the structure in a certain manner (as described by generative rules), but instead he or she does something completely different. This momentarily creates psychological tension that is resolved when the performer resumes ‘expected playing’. Something of the
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
283
284
Psychology of Music 31(3)
effect is captured in the following description of the Italian style of performance at the beginning of the 18th century: He’ll have passages of such an extent as will perfectly confound his auditors at first, and upon such irregular notes as shall instill a terror as well as surprise into the audience, who will immediately conclude that the whole concert is degenerating into a dreadful dissonance; and betraying [them] by that means into a concern for the music, which seems to be on the brink of ruin, he immediately reconciles [them] by such regular cadences that everyone is surprised to see harmony rising again, in a manner, out of discord itself and owing its greatest beauties to those irregularities which seemed to threaten it with destruction. (François Raguenet, cited in Meyer, 1956: 208)
This component is probably the least researched so far, but it may be critical to developing a truly original interpretation. For examples of music performances by experts that feature various bold and unexpected patterns of expression, see, for example, Repp (1997b). No attempt has yet been made to model this component in terms of expressive rules, perhaps because of the paradox inherent in developing rules for how to break other rules, and the difficulty in deciding precisely on what basis such rule breaking is done (not all rule breaking is musically satisfying). TOWARDS A THEORY OF PERFORMANCE EXPRESSION : THE GERMS MODEL
Research on the five components of expression outlined previously has tended to be descriptive, and to the extent that theoretical models have been proposed, they have not been integrated with other models. (For an overview of various models of music performance, see Gabrielsson, 1999, 2003, this issue.) Therefore, I propose a model of expression – the GERMS model – that integrates different facets of expression (see also Juslin et al., 2002). The assumption is that, in principle, it is possible to decompose patterns of expression into five different components (Generative rules, Emotional expression, Random variability, Motion principles, Stylistic unexpectedness). Further, it can be assumed that the different components of expression: (1) (2) (3) (4)
have different origins involve patterns with different characteristics are processed by somewhat different brain regions have different effects on listeners’ perception of music
The last of these criteria also means that each GERMS component will tend to make a unique contribution to the emotional and aesthetic impact of a given performance. Although the aesthetic impact of a music performance is a complex topic indeed, it may be hypothesized that it involves commonly suggested features, such as beauty, recognition, symmetry, tension/resolution, arousal, order, originality and personal expression (Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1989; North and Hargreaves, 1997). We are, in my view, only just beginning to explore differences between
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
different components, which is why my suggestions on how they might differ should be treated as hypotheses rather than as established facts. Table 2 shows some of the hypothesized characteristics of the components. The G-component originates in generative transformations of the notated musical structure, and reflects basic characteristics of human cognition, such as categorical perception and gestalt laws (Bregman, 1990). It recruits the human capacity for syntactical processing, which is also involved in language. A positron-emission tomography study of sight reading in piano performance showed activated cortical brain areas distinct from, but adjacent to, those underlying language operations (Sergent et al., 1992), consistent with the task of translating a generative structure in a musical notation into expressive markings of structure. A magnetoencephalography study of musical perception suggested that musical syntax is processed in Broca’s area, which is also involved in syntactic processing during auditory language comprehension (Maess et al., 2001). Generative rules are mainly bottom-up (i.e. determined by the local structure), but also reflect the hierarchical structure of the music. By conveying the structure and creating coherence and order, generative rules add to the beauty of the music. They may further have an arousing effect, but mainly by enhancing the emotional impact inherent in the structure. The E-component originates in emotion-specific patterns of cues in vocal expression (Juslin and Laukka, in press) and reflects evolutionary ancient human abilities for non-verbal communication of emotion. This involves a large set of probabilistic (uncertain) albeit partly redundant cues that are additive and compensatory in nature (one cue can to some extent compensate for another, see Juslin, 2000). Perception of the E-component can be instantaneous (Peretz et al., 1998) and involves parallel processing mainly in the right hemisphere of the brain (Bryden et al., 1982), perhaps in the basal ganglia, which are involved in perception of emotion in vocal expression (Cohen et al., 1994). The E-component is mainly top-down (i.e. a holistic interpretation of the mood of the piece influences local acoustic parameters), and offers a parallel channel of affective information, which may support or contradict the expression of the composed structure. The E-component contributes to the recognition aspect of art, but could also enhance arousal (Juslin, 2001) and personal expression (Lindström et al., in press).4 The R-component originates in a hypothesized ‘internal timekeeper’ and associated motor delays (Gilden et al., 1995), and reflects human limitations regarding perceptual-motor precision. This involves two kinds of random patterns: 1/f noise (noise for which the power varies inversely with the frequency) that reflects the timekeeper and changes according to the interonset-interval duration, and uncorrelated white noise that reflects motor delays that are constant across different inter-onset-interval durations. It may be hypothesized that the internal time-keeper is localized in the lateral and medial parts of the cerebellum (see Ivry et al., 1988). This component
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
285
286
2 Summary of hypotheses regarding the primary components of performance expression according to the GERMS model Component
Characteristic
G
Origin of pattern
R
M
S
Generative Emotion-specific transformations of patterns of acoustic the musical structure cues deriving from vocal expression
Internal timekeeper and motor delay variance reflecting human limitations
Biological motion; distinct patterns of movement typical of human beings
Deviations from expected performance conventions
Nature of pattern
Local expressive features related to the structural interpretation
Mainly overall levels of multiple uncertain, partly redundant cues that are compensatory
Semi-random patterns 1/f noise and white noise; very small in magnitude, irregular
Dynamic, noncompensatory patterns; smooth and global
Local; not predictable from the structure
Salient brain regions
Left hemisphere (adjacent to Broca’s area)
Right hemisphere (the basal ganglia)
Lateral and medial parts of the cerebellum, plus the motor cortex
Left hemisphere (adjacent to the superior temporal sulcus)
Anterior cingulate cortex
Perceptual effects
Clarifies structure; affects the inherent expression of a piece
Expresses emotions and moods (mainly in broad categories of emotion)
Generates a ‘living’ and natural quality
Yields expressive form that is similar to human gestures
Heightens tension and unpredictability
Knowledge dependence
Medium
Low
None
Low
High
Aesthetic contribution
Beauty, order, coherence
Recognition, arousal, personal expression
Unevenness, novelty
Balance, unity, recognition
Novelty, arousal
Yes
No
Yes, partly
Yes
Under voluntary control Yes, mostly
E
Psychology of Music 31(3)
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
TA B L E
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
involves involuntary patterns of variability that contribute a certain unevenness to a performance, and also may enhance the novelty aspect of art. The M-component originates in patterns of human movement (biological motion), like arm gestures, which reflect the unique construction of the human body (e.g. the unique composite of anatomical proportions, including both geometrical dimensions and distribution of mass between parts of the body). Perception of the M-component partly reflects the human ability to distinguish animate objects from inanimate objects on the basis of patterns of sounds, which could have great survival value. This involves complex, dynamic and non-compensatory temporal patterns that are processed by the left hemisphere (Natale, 1977; Peretz, 1990), possibly by brain regions adjacent to those that analyse biological motion in vision, like the superior temporal sulcus (Allison et al., 2000). The M-component contributes to the recognition aspect of art – by signalling human intentionality – but also lends balance and smooth gesturing to a performance. The S-component originates in a general human tendency to create schematic expectations that can guide behaviour, and the consequent monitoring of such expectations that may give rise to emotional arousal, signalling that something important has happened. This notion is recurrent in psychological theories of emotion since the beginning of the 20th century (e.g. Oatley, 1992). As regards music performance, I have hypothesized that the S-component reflects a performer’s deliberate attempt to deviate from stylistic expectations concerning performance conventions in order to add tension and unpredictability to the performance. The S-component involves locally focused expressive features that contribute to the novelty, originality and arousal aspects of art. Monitoring of expectations is believed to be processed by parts of the anterior cingulate cortex (Ochsner and Feldman Barrett, 2001). What is the relationship of the S-component to the others? My guess is that the first four components are sufficient to achieve an acceptable performance, but that the S-component is what makes a performance really special. Thus, much of the artistic process aims at turning GERM performances into GEMS. That is, reducing random fluctuations to a minimum and increasing the originality of the musical interpretation. A PRELIMINARY IMPLEMENTATION
Can this kind of psychological theory be turned into something useful in empirical terms? In a recent study, we made the first attempt to implement a component approach in a computational model, the GERM model, that simulates different aspects of expression (Juslin et al., 2002).5 The model comprised only four main sources of variability (Generative rules, Emotional expression, Random variability, Motion principles), since we had not figured out how to implement the fifth component, S, at the time. The model takes as its input (a) a musical notation, and (b) a performer interpretation. We assume that there is both a structural interpretation (e.g. phrase structure)
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
287
288
Psychology of Music 31(3)
and a mood interpretation (e.g. ‘joy’). Then, for each component, there is a module featuring a set of algorithms that convert the notation into patterns of expression. Space does not permit description of the rules, but some of them are derived from the KTH rule system (see Friberg, 1995), others were presented in Juslin et al. (2002). In a preliminary experiment, a subset of the rules featured in the GERM model was used to synthesize expressive performances of a brief piece of music. The aim of this experiment was to examine (1) whether the four components would yield predicted effects on listeners’ judgements of the performances, and (2) whether the components would yield at least partly independent effects on these judgements (for further information about this experiment, see Juslin et al., 2002). The basic idea was to manipulate the four components of the GERM model in a factorial design; this was done by generating all possible combinations (16) of the presence and absence of each GERM component. For instance, a condition with only the G-component present and all other components absent would include only those rules that serve to convey the structure to listeners. We asked musically trained listeners to rate all 16 performances on scales believed to reflect various aspects of expression (clear, sad, human, gestural, musical, expressive). The results of this experiment suggested, first of all, that the different components yielded predicted effects on listeners’ ratings of the performance. For instance, the G-component yielded high ratings on the ‘clear’ scale; the Ecomponent yielded high ratings on the ‘sad’ scale; and the M-component yielded high ratings on the ‘gestural’ scale. Multiple regression analyses revealed that listeners’ judgements of overall expressivity could be successfully predicted on the basis of a linear combination of the GERM components, which all contributed significantly but in different degrees to the judged expressivity; R = .77, F(4,184) = 66.143, p < .0001, with beta weights in order of predictive strength: Emotional Expression, β = .64, p < .0001; Motion Principles, β = .32, p < .0001; Generative Rules, β = .23, p < .0001; Random Variations, β = .14, p < .01). There were, of course, some interactions between the four components in how they affected listeners’ judgements. However, only 20 percent of the total number of possible interactions were actually significant, and the interaction effects were smaller than the main effects. Finally, the components produced different and at least partly independent effects on listeners’ judgements. This tendency is seen in examples of dissociations between the four components. For instance, the performance with only G present yielded a high mean rating on the ‘clear’ scale, but low mean ratings on the ‘sad’, ‘human’ and ‘gestural’ scales (Juslin et al., 2002). IMPLICATIONS FOR RESEARCH
What can we conclude from these preliminary data? First, the GERM model suggests that different aspects of performance expression can be integrated
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
into a common model. The reader may disagree with me about the specifics of this model, but the important point is that there are different facets of expression. I suspect that researchers have found performance data confusing partly because they have treated them as if they reflected a single factor. If we are unaware of the different aspects of performance expression, or ignore some of them, we are likely to be confused by data that reflect some unknown mixture of the different modes of behaviour. Indeed, even some of the more sophisticated systems for synthesis of music performances, such as Director Musices (Friberg et al., 2000), may not have sufficiently differentiated between different kinds of expressive features. The rules in Director Musices were simply designed to make a synthesized music performance sound as good as possible, without categorizing expressive features theoretically. This makes perfect sense from an engineering point of view, although, unfortunately, it muddles important distinctions between psychologically different components of expression. Rules that reflect acoustic characteristics of certain musical instruments are mixed with rules that convey structure (Friberg, 1995), and rules that function to convey structure are ‘turned backwards’ to express emotions (Bresin and Friberg, 2000). A genuine understanding of performance expression may require that we take greater care in distinguishing different categories of expressive features. Distinguishing different components of expression could help us to better explain individual differences among performers. Different performers may be characterized in terms of the relative weights they give to different aspects of expression. (Some may emphasize precision, others may emphasize emotional expression at any cost, yet others may emphasize structural communication.) Furthermore, different musical styles may put different emphasis on different facets of expression; the G-component may be crucial to the classical pianist, but is less important to the blues guitarist. Finally, a componential approach might help to resolve some inconsistent findings in the previous literature. For example, the fact that experienced listeners have shown refined ability to detect expressive aspects in some studies but not others (Rohwer, 2001) could be explained by the fact that these studies have investigated different components of expression (e.g. generative structure vs emotional expression). How can we be sure that the particular components I have postulated are the appropriate ones? This is, ultimately, an empirical question, which is far from settled. I remain open to the possibility that a different set of components can provide a more cohesive account. However, I have argued that psychological theory in combination with findings from listening experiments, performance measurements, and brain imaging could help us to resolve this problem. As should be apparent, I hypothesize that all components in the GERMS model have their origins in human phenomena outside the music domain. (From this perspective, it may be premature to view some components as more ‘musical’ than others.) Thus, one implication of the GERMS model is that it agrees with Palmer’s (1997) view of music performance as ‘a
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
289
290
Psychology of Music 31(3)
seemingly unique human ability that is not unique in its underlying cognitive mechanisms’ (p. 134). But far from depreciating the performance of music, this idea suggests that music performance is an activity that recruits many different aspects of human behaviour in a wonderful way. It also implies that psychological theory about various aspects of human behaviour such as language, emotion, motor-coordination, movement and expectancy may be highly relevant to an understanding of performance expression. IMPLICATIONS FOR MUSIC EDUCATION
The GERMS model offers an example of how research could benefit teaching by helping to ‘demystify’ expression. Indeed, based on my research on expression over the last decade, I have come to believe that there are certain myths about expression, which have had a negative impact on music education. (For a discussion of common myths about expression, see Juslin et al., in press.) One of these myths is that ‘expression cannot be studied objectively’. This myth is associated with the notion that expression is a completely subjective quality, which cannot be explained in scientific terms. However, as demonstrated by the GERM study, acoustic correlates of perceived expression can readily be obtained and manipulated in performances, and listeners’ ratings of expression can be systematically and reliably related to these correlates. This paves the way for a more theoretically informed approach to teaching of expression. One implication is that, at certain stages of learning, different aspects of expression might need to be taught separately, since they have different characteristics. According to the GERMS model, a music performance should (a) convey the structure of the music, (b) express emotions, (c) exhibit motor precision, (d) be suggestive of human motion and gesture, and (e) deviate from stylistic expectations in creative and aesthetically pleasing ways. The conveying of structure (G) is perhaps the aspect that has received most attention in music education, presumably because it is the most tangible aspect; ‘structure can be seen, heard, demonstrated’ (Epstein, 1995: 126). Certainly there is no substitute for a thorough understanding of the musical structure in shaping an interpretation. This aspect of expression may be guided by structural analysis, by consulting the composer’s writings, and also by studying visual graphs of performance variables alongside the score. The motion component (M) can be trained by using some of the methods outlined by Davidson and Correia (2002: 246–7), like having a student conduct the expression in the playing of the teacher, and developing a non-verbal narrative of physical gesture for individual phrases. The stylistic unexpectedness component (S) requires extensive knowledge of musical styles and performance conventions, and an ability to conceive of the performance structure in terms of a ‘narrative’ of musical expectations that may be experimented with in creative ways. The aspect of expression in most need of a formalized teaching strategy is emotion (E). This is regrettable, considering that the strongest
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
predictor of listeners’ judgements of expression in the GERM experiment was the emotion component. This suggests that music teaching should pay more attention to the emotion component of expression. And, so, in the final part of my article, I turn specifically to emotion.
Emotion and communication Although music and emotion is a topic that has attracted much interest since ancient Greece (Juslin and Sloboda, 2001; Sloboda and Juslin, in press), a systematic research program on emotions in music performance did not take off until the 1990s. There are several reasons for this: first, the structuralist approach in musicology rendered expressive aspects of music off-limits for research until the rise of the ‘new’ musicology (see Cook and Dibben, 2001). Second, researchers may have sensed ‘a general aversion among musicians to scientific study of music, especially when related to topics such as emotion, expression and aesthetics’ (Woody, 2002: 214). Finally, although it may appear obvious to the reader that emotion is strongly related to musical expression, this very idea has been questioned by some authors. On what basis can we claim that expression is about emotion, or even communication of emotion? A questionnaire study featuring 135 expert musicians from three countries (England, Italy, Sweden) revealed that the great majority of the musicians defined expression mainly in terms of ‘communicating emotions’ and ‘playing with feeling’, as indicated by their own free responses (Lindström et al., in press). When directly asked whether music expresses emotions, 99 percent of the musicians thought that this was the case. Numerous biographies and interviews with performers confirm that they conceive of expression in terms of emotions and communication (e.g. Boyd and George-Warren, 1992; Carreras, 1992; Menuhin, 1996; King, 1996; Persson, 1993; Schumacher, 1995; see also Mills, 2003, this issue). Some composers may have argued that music is ‘absolute’ and ‘expresses nothing but itself ’, but this is simply not how most people think of music. When Small (1999) argues, plausibly, that the origins of ‘musicking’ (a term that serves to highlight that music above all is an activity, and that performance is its essence) are to be found in the ancient gestures, in which we affirm and explore our human relationships, it is perplexing that he denies that this involves communication of emotion, which is at the very heart of human relationships: . . . to my mind the idea of music . . . as the communication of emotions doesn’t jibe at all with my own experience. I cannot remember ever being happy by a happy piece of music, or sad by a sad piece of music, and I am not sure I could tell you which was which. (p. 18)
Be that as it may (although I am certain that Small would be able to tell
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
291
292
Psychology of Music 31(3)
happy and sad pieces apart), we cannot ignore that most performers and listeners seem to think of music as a means of emotional communication. I do not claim that communication is the sole or main purpose of music, but 83 percent of music students in a questionnaire study claim that they try to express specific emotions in their performance ‘always’ or ‘often’ (Lindström et al., in press), and we know that listeners are able to recognize at least certain emotions expressed by performers (Juslin, 2001). This suggests that the concept of communication is viable in music, even if not every instant of music performance may be an example of the phenomenon. To what extent do music performers actually succeed in communicating emotions to listeners? In the most extensive review of emotional expression in music performance to date (Juslin and Laukka, in press), including 41 studies, a metaanalysis of communication accuracy showed that professional performers are able to communicate basic emotions (happiness, anger, sadness, fear, tenderness) to listeners with an accuracy approximately as high as in facial and vocal expression of emotions. The overall decoding accuracy was π = 0.89, which is equivalent to a raw accuracy score of pc = .70 in a forced-choice task with five response alternatives (i.e. the average number of emotions included in studies of music performance so far).6 Amateur musicians communicate emotions less accurately, and tend to apply acoustic features inconsistently (see Juslin and Laukka, 2000; Rohwer, 2001). The available evidence indicates that the communicative process operates on a fairly broad level of emotion categories, whereas finer distinctions within the categories are difficult to convey (Juslin and Lindström, 2003), at least without some context (London, 2002; see also Juslin, 1997c). It is not that music performances intended to express, say, anger and jealousy sound exactly the same or that listeners cannot hear a difference, it is just that they are not able to tell which performance is which. It has been argued by some authors that the specific ordering of successive emotional states could help to communicate subtler or more complex states (Levinson, 1990). This is an interesting possibility, but it remains to be demonstrated that this is possible. (In reviewing these findings, I do not intend to imply that performances that do not reliably convey a specific emotion are without value, because, as I have tried to demonstrate in this article, musical expression involves a lot more than just emotion; and sometimes musicians may deliberately aim for emotional ambiguity.) Many studies have tried to capture the acoustic cues that musicians use to convey specific emotions (e.g. Jansens et al., 1997; Juslin, 1997a; Juslin and Madison, 1999; Kotlyar and Morozov, 1976; Mergl et al., 1998). These cues involve changes in tempo, sound level, articulation, timbre, timing, tone attack and decay, intonation, vibrato extent and frequency, accents on particular notes, etc. Earlier studies have mostly been limited to a few emotions. Figure 2 offers examples of patterns of acoustic cues used by professional performers to express 12 emotions in a recent study (Juslin and Lindström,
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
Intended Emotion
Intended Emotion
Note. Sound level is expressed in decibels (dBs) down from an arbitrary reference level. 2 Overall levels of sound level and tempo (means and SDs) in professional pianists’ renditions of 12 emotions in performances of a theme by Haydn (adapted from Juslin and Lindström, 2003).
FIGURE
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
293
294
Psychology of Music 31(3)
2003). Both ‘basic’ (e.g. sadness, anger, fear) and ‘complex’ (e.g. jealousy, shame, pride) emotions were featured in an attempt to accommodate the subtleties of musical expression. In reality the emotional expression will often change quickly within a piece, or even within a single note. Thus we have recently experimented with real-time analysis of emotional expression over time (Friberg et al., 2002). That the relevant cues have been described may be confirmed by programming synthesized performances of music on the basis of empirical data. Computerized performances with appropriate acoustic features can communicate emotions as reliably as human performers can (Juslin, 1997b), although they sound less musically satisfying (presumably because they lack other components of expression). An important question concerns the origins of the acoustic cues used by performers. Some authors have argued that emotions expressed in music have nothing in common with other forms of expression: ‘Musical feelings have their own character . . . the emotions [music] formulates are not identical with those accompanying extra-musical experience’ (Lippman, 1953: 569). It is getting exceedingly hard to make such a case. A review of 145 studies (101 speech and 41 music studies) strongly indicates that patterns of musical cues used to convey discrete emotions mainly derives from the non-verbal aspects of emotional speech (Juslin and Laukka, in press), as proposed by Spencer (1857). Hence, musical emotions touch us deeply not because they are so different from everyday emotions, but because they are so similar. This may explain why music students find extramusical sources (e.g. life situations) useful in developing expression (e.g. Woody, 2000). One reason why singing musical phrases seems to be such good practice for instrumentalists (e.g. Dubal, 1985: 221; see also Mills, 2003, this issue) could be that this helps the performer to connect with fundamental principles of vocal expression of emotion.7 Although it may be tempting to connect musical expression of emotion to motion (Woody, 2002), a theoretically more plausible and parsimonious view holds that the origin of the emotion component is to be found in involuntary and emotion-specific physiological changes associated with emotions, which strongly influence different aspects of voice production (Juslin and Laukka, 2001; Scherer, 1986). Music performance shares with vocal expression of emotions not just the code but also the coding: the cues used to express emotions are uncertain but redundant to some extent, as conceptualized by the lens model (Juslin, 2000). This can account for some interesting phenomena, for instance that communication of emotion in music is generally successful despite individual differences in utilization of acoustic cues among both performers and listeners (Juslin, 2000) and different cues available on different musical instruments (Juslin and Laukka, in press). I envisage several important directions for future research. First, there has been almost no attempt to study how the emotional expression of a performance interacts with the expression of the piece. In our recent work, we are
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
using an expanded version of the lens model, which features both composed and performed cues (Juslin and Lindström, 2003). Second, it is important that basic research is turned into useful applications for performers. We are thus currently trying to develop computer software that may provide performers with detailed feedback about their performances (Juslin et al., in press). Finally, it is crucial to explore how the emotion component interacts with other components of expression in yielding an expressive performance, which could explored by means of theoretical models (e.g. along the lines of the GERMS model).
Limitations of a psychological approach Performers are sometimes sceptical about research on expression, perhaps partly because research on performance lags far behind the actual performance of music (to the extent that these endeavours can actually be compared), in terms of maturity and sophistication. Like the performer who first learns to play a musical instrument, studies of music performance have progressed from a consideration of basic principles of expression (e.g. how does the performer convey the phrase structure?) towards more subtle and individualistic aspects (e.g. what makes a performance truly special?). But music has been played since the beginning of recorded time whereas psychological studies of music performance have been conducted for only a century; perhaps researchers should be excused for not having reached the same level of sophistication as the performers? There are many limitations of the psychological approach to performance expression. One limitation involves the fact that psychological research requires that all relevant concepts are formally operationalized, so that they can be measured with precision. This requirement severely limits the complexity that can be handled in any single empirical investigation. Thus, psychological studies are often criticized by musicians for their ‘simplicity’. Clearly, psychologists must strive to study music at an appropriate level of complexity. At the same time, musicians must also appreciate the conditions under which empirical research is carried out. Seemingly ‘crude’ models, for instance, could reflect practical limitations rather than insensitivity regarding musical matters. (The GERM model, for example, is admittedly simple as compared to the long list of factors that can influence performance expression in Table 1. Still, you might be surprised how complicated that model is!) Practical limitations of a psychological approach are perhaps redeemed by the power with which experiments allow us to draw valid conclusions about causal relationships. Thus, folk theories of expression may ultimately be replaced, or at least improved, by empirically validated knowledge. Such a development may be welcomed by some performers (Dubal, 1985: 250), but not all are so inclined. A common sentiment is that too much knowledge
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
295
296
Psychology of Music 31(3)
‘destroys the magic’, or interferes with the artistic process (Dubal, 1985: 245). Ultimately, this could reflect the different needs of scientists and artists. Elsewhere, I have argued for an attempt to bridge the gap between art and science (Juslin and Zentner, 2002; see also Rink, 2003, this issue), because I believe that musicians and researchers have much to learn from each other. Art and science share many characteristics: they are both interesting ways of exploring the world around us; they both involve creativity; and they both provide certain perspectives or ways of looking at the world. However, I believe that we must accept that there will always be some tension between art and science, since art and science, ultimately, have different aims. Thus, for instance, research on performance expression aims to develop general models (i.e. simplified descriptions and explanations of a specific phenomenon), whereas the performing artist often strives to create something unique and personal. (The scientist usually opts out at the point where the artist thinks things are getting interesting.) There is no way in which a psychological focus on general models can fully capture the rich, personal and piecespecific ways in which musicians tend to approach their work artistically. And – after all – the most useful approach to performance as an artist may not be the most useful approach to performance as a researcher, given the quite different aims of these endeavours. But there is one important reason why we should at least try to establish some common ground: the teaching of performance expression clearly appears to benefit from explicit instruction and knowledge about expression (Juslin et al., in press; Woody, 1999). Hence, in this article, I have suggested that the primary goal of a psychological approach to music performance should be to explain the nature of performance expression in order provide a solid foundation for the teaching of expressive skills in music education. It remains to be seen whether this challenge can be met in coming years. But even if it is not, I am sure that we can learn something important along the way. AC K N OW L E D G E M E N T S
This is an expanded version of an invited paper presented at the conference Investigating Music Performance, 12–13 April 2002, Royal College of Music, London. The research was supported by The Bank of Sweden Tercentenary Foundation. I am grateful to the members of the Feel-ME project for fruitful collaboration. NOTES
1.
2.
Some musicians, including Nicolo Paganini and blues singer Robert Johnson, have been accused of ‘selling their soul to the devil’ in order to gain their exceptional skills. One notable reason for doing so is that philosophical inquiry does not lend itself easily to applications in music education. To take but one example: which music teacher could seriously claim to have gained a better sense of how to teach
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
expressive skills after having read Scruton’s (1997) complex chapter on musical expression? Meyer (1956) notes that ‘because Seashore advances no theory or attempts no explanation of the relationship between deviation and affective aesthetic experience, his viewpoint lacks substance and plausibility’ (p. 203). The reader may wonder why Clynes’s (1977) work has not been included here. The reason is that independent attempts to replicate his essentic forms have yielded mixed results (Gorman and Crain, 1974; Nettelbeck et al., 1989; Trussoni et al., 1988). A computational model means that the relevant relationships are expressed in terms of mathematical procedures. The calculations are handled by implementing the model in a program, which permits simulation of the phenomenon under investigation. Rosenthal and Rubin’s effect size index, pi (π), allows researchers to transform accuracy scores involving any number of response alternatives to a standard scale of dichotomous choice, on which .50 is the null value and 1.00 corresponds to 100 percent correct recognition. Recall also the use of principles from vocal rhetoric among composers in the 18th century.
REFERENCES
Allison, T., Puce, A. and McCarthy, G. (2000) ‘Social Perception from Visual Cues: Role of the STS Region’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4: 267–78. Boyd, J. and George-Warren, H. (1992) Musicians in Tune: Seventy-Five Contemporary Musicians Discuss the Creative Process. New York: Fireside. Bregman, A.S. (1990) Auditory Scene Analysis: The Perceptual Organization of Sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bresin, R. and Friberg, A. (2000) ‘Emotional Coloring of Computer-Controlled Music Performance’, Computer Music Journal 24: 44–62. Bryden, M. P., Ley, R. and Sugerman, J. (1982) ‘A Left-Ear Advantage for Identifying the Emotional Quality of Tonal Sequences’, Neuropsychologia 20: 83–7. Carreras, J. (1992) Sjunga med själen (Singing with soul). Uddevalla: Vocalis. Clarke, E.F. (1988) ‘Generative Principles in Music Performance’, In J.A. Sloboda (ed.) Generative Processes in Music: The Psychology of Performance, Improvisation, and Composition, pp. 1–26. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Clarke, E.F. (1995) ‘Expression in Performance: Generativity, Perception, and Semiosis’, In J. Rink (ed.) The Practice of Performance: Studies in Musical Interpretation, pp. 21–54. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clarke, E.F. and Windsor, W.L. (2000) ‘Real and Simulated Expression: A Listening Study’, Music Perception 17: 277–313. Clynes, M. (1977) Sentics: The Touch of Emotions. New York: Doubleday. Cohen, R.A., Riccio, C.A. and Flannery, A.M. (1994) ‘Expressive Aprosodia Following Stroke to the Right Basal Ganglia: A Case Report’, Neuropsychology 8: 242–5. Cook, N. and Dibben, N. (2001) ‘Musicological Approaches to Emotion’, in P.N. Juslin and J.A. Sloboda (eds) Music and Emotion: Theory and Research, pp. 45–70. New York: Oxford University Press. Davidson, J.W. and Correia, J.S. (2002) ‘Body Movement’, in R. Parncuttand G.E. McPherson (eds) The Science and Psychology of Music Performance: Creative
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
297
298
Psychology of Music 31(3) Strategies for Teaching and Learning, pp. 237–50. New York: Oxford University Press. Davies, S. (1994) Musical Meaning and Expression. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Dubal, D. (1985) The World of the Concert Pianist: Conversations with 35 Internationally Celebrated Pianists. London: Victor Gollancz. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1989) Human Ethology. New York: Aldine. Epstein, D. (1995) ‘A Curious Moment in Schumann’s Fourth Symphony: Structure as the Fusion of Affect and Intuition’, in J. Rink (ed.) The Practice of Performance, pp. 126–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Farga, F. (1969) Violins and Violinists, 2nd edn. London: The Cresset Press. Friberg, A. (1995) ‘A Quantitative Rule System for Musical Performance’, doctoral dissertation, Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm. Friberg, A. and Sundberg, J. (1999) ‘Does Music Performance Allude to Locomotion? A Model of Final Ritardandi Derived from Measurements of Stopping Runners’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 105: 1469–84. Friberg, A., Colombo, V., Frydén, L. and Sundberg, J. (2000) ‘Generating Musical Performances with Director Musices’, Computer Music Journal 24: 23–9. Friberg, A., Schoonderwaldt, E., Juslin, P.N. and Bresin, R. (2002) ‘Automatic RealTime Extraction of Musical Expression’, in Proceedings of the International Computer Music Conference, Göteborg, 16–21 September 2002, pp. 365–7. San Francisco: International Computer Music Association. Gabrielsson, A. (1987) ‘Once Again: The Theme from Mozart’s Piano Sonata in A Major: A Comparison of Five Performances’, in A. Gabrielsson (ed.) Action and Perception in Rhythm and Music, publication no. 55, pp. 81–103. Stockholm: Royal Swedish Academy of Music. Gabrielsson, A. (1999) ‘The Performance of Music’, in D. Deutsch (ed.) The Psychology of Music, 2nd edn, pp. 501–602. San Diego: Academic Press. Gabrielsson, A. (2003) ‘Music Performance Research at the Millennium’, Psychology of Music 31(3): 221–72. Gabrielsson, A. and Juslin, P.N. (1996) ‘Emotional Expression in Music Performance: Between the Performer’s Intention and the Listener’s Experience’, Psychology of Music 24: 68–91. Gabrielsson, A. and Juslin, P.N. (2003) ‘Emotional Expression in Music’, in R.J. Davidson, H.H. Goldsmith and K.R. Scherer (eds) Handbook of Affective Sciences, pp. 503–34. New York: Oxford University Press. Gilden, D.L., Thornton, T. and Mallon, M.W. (1995) ‘1/f Noise in Human Cognition’, Science 267: 1837–9. Gorman, B.S. and Crain, W.C. (1974) ‘Decoding of “sentograms”’, Perceptual and Motor Skills 39: 784–6. Hallam, S. (1995) ‘Professional Musicians’ Approaches to the Learning and Interpretation of Music’, Psychology of Music 23: 111–28. Ivry, R.I., Keele, S.W. and Diener, H.C. (1988) ‘Dissociation of the Lateral and Medial Cerebellum in Movement Timing and Movement Execution’, Experimental Brain Research 73: 167–80. Jansens, S., Bloothooft, G. and De Krom, G. (1997) ‘Perception and Acoustics of Emotions in Singing’, in Proceedings of the Fifth European Conference on Speech Communication and Technology, Vol. IV, pp. 2155–8. Rhodes, Greece: ESCA. Johansson, G. (1973) ‘Visual Perception of Biological Motion and a Model for its Analysis’, Perception and Psychophysics 14: 201–11.
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression Juslin, P.N. (1997a) ‘Emotional Communication in Music Performance: A Functionalist Perspective and Some Data’, Music Perception 14: 383–418. Juslin, P.N. (1997b) ‘Perceived Emotional Expression in Synthesized Performances of a Short Melody: Capturing the Listener’s Judgment Policy’, Musicae Scientiae 1: 225–56. Juslin, P.N. (1997c) ‘Can Results from Studies of Perceived Expression in Musical Performances Be Generalized across Response Formats?’, Psychomusicology 16: 77–101. Juslin, P.N. (2000) ‘Cue Utilization in Communication of Emotion in Music Performance: Relating Performance to Perception’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 26: 1797–813. Juslin, P.N. (2001) ‘Communicating Emotion in Music Performance: A Review and a Theoretical Framework’, in P.N. Juslin and J.A. Sloboda (eds) Music and Emotion: Theory and Research, pp. 305–33. New York: Oxford University Press. Juslin, P.N. and Laukka, P. (2000) ‘Improving Emotional Communication in Music Performance through Cognitive Feedback’, Musicae Scientiae 4: 151–83. Juslin, P.N. and Laukka, P. (2001) ‘Impact of Intended Emotion Intensity On Cue Utilization and Decoding Accuracy in Vocal Expression of Emotion’, Emotion 1: 381–412. Juslin, P.N. and Laukka, P. (in press) ‘Communication of Emotions in Vocal Expression and Music Performance: Different Channels, Same Code?’, Psychological Bulletin. Juslin, P.N. and Laukka, P. (in press) ‘Emotional Expression in Speech and Music: Evidence of Cross-modal Similarities’, in P. Ekman (ed.) Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. New York: New York Academy of Sciences. Juslin, P.N. and Lindström, E. (2003) ‘Musical Expression of Emotions: Modeling Composed and Performed Features’, manuscript in preparation. Juslin, P.N. and Madison, G. (1999) ‘The Role of Timing Patterns in Recognition of Emotional Expression from Musical Performance’, Music Perception 17: 197–221. Juslin, P.N. and Persson, R.S. (2002) ‘Emotional Communication’, in R. Parncutt and G.E. McPherson (eds) The Science and Psychology of Music Performance: Creative Strategies for Teaching and Learning, pp. 219–36. New York: Oxford University Press. Juslin, P.N. and Sloboda, J.A. (eds) (2001) Music and Emotion: Theory and Research. New York: Oxford University Press. Juslin, P.N. and Zentner, M.R. (2002) ‘Current Trends in the Study of Music and Emotion: Overture’, Musicae Scientiae (special issue 2001/2): 3–21. Juslin, P.N., Friberg, A. and Bresin, R. (2002) ‘Toward a Computational Model of Expression in Music Performance: The GERM Model’, Musicae Scientiae (special Issue 2001/2): 63–122. Juslin, P.N., Friberg, A., Schoonderwaldt, E. and Karlsson, J. (in press) ‘FeedbackLearning of Musical Expressivity’, in A. Williamon (ed.) Enhancing Musical Performance: A Resource for Performers, Teachers and Researchers. New York: Oxford University Press. King, B.B. (1996) Blues All Around Me. London: Hodder and Stoughton. Konecˆni, V.J. (1979) ‘Determinants of Aesthetic Preference and Effects of Exposure to Aesthetic Stimuli: Social, Emotional, and Cognitive Factors’, in B.A. Maher (ed.) Progress in Experimental Personality Research, Vol. 9, pp. 149–97. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Kotlyar, G.M. and Morozov, V.P. (1976) ‘Acoustic Correlates of the Emotional Content of Vocalized Speech’, Soviet Physics: Acoustics 22: 370–6.
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
299
300
Psychology of Music 31(3) Laukka, P. (2003) ‘Instrumental Music Teachers’ Views on Expressivity: A Report from Music Conservatories’, manuscript submitted for publication. Leahey, T.H. (1987) A History of Psychology: Main Currents in Psychological Thought. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Levinson, J. (1990) Music, Art, and Metaphysics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Lindström, E., Juslin, P.N., Bresin, R. and Williamon, A. (in press) ‘Expressivity Comes From Within Your Soul: A Questionnaire Study of Music Students’ Perspectives on Expressivity’, Research Studies in Music Education. Lippman, E.A. (1953) ‘Symbolism in Music’, Musical Quarterly 39: 554–75. London, J. (2002) ‘Some Theories of Emotion in Music and their Implications for Research in Music Psychology’, Musicae Scientiae (special issue 2001/2): 23–36. Madison, G. (2000) ‘On the Nature of Variability in Isochronous Serial Interval Production’, in P. Desain and W.L. Windsor (eds) Rhythm Perception and Production, pp. 95–113. Lisse, The Netherlands: Swets and Zeitlinger. Maess, B., Koelsch, S., Gunter, T.C. and Friederici, A.D. (2001) ‘Musical Syntax is Processed in Broca’s Area: A MEG Study’, Nature Neuroscience 4: 540–5. Menuhin, Y. (1996) Unfinished Journey. London: Methuen. Mergl, R., Piesbergen, C. and Tunner, W. (1998) ‘Musikalisch-improvisatorischer Ausdruck und erkennen von gefühlsqualitäten’, Musikpsychologie: Jahrbuch der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Musikpsychologie 13: 69–81. Meyer, L.B. (1956) Emotion and Meaning in Music. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Mills, J. (2003) ‘Musical Performance: Crux or Curse of Music Education’, Psychology of Music 31(3): 324–39. Natale, M. (1977) ‘Perception of Nonlinguistic Auditory Rhythms by the Speech Hemisphere’, Brain and Language 4: 32–44. Nettelbeck, T., Henderson, C. and Willson, R. (1989) ‘Communicating Emotion through Sound: An Evaluation of Clynes’ Theory of Sentics’, Australian Journal of Psychology 41: 17–24. North, A.C. and Hargreaves, D.J. (1997) ‘Experimental Aesthetics and Everyday Listening to Music’, in D.J. Hargreaves and A.C. North (eds) The Social Psychology of Music, pp. 84–103. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Oatley, K. (1992) Best Laid Schemes: The Psychology of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Ochsner, K.N. and Feldman Barrett, L. (2001) ‘A Multiprocess Perspective on the Neuroscience of Emotion’, in T.J. Mayne and G.A. Bonnano (eds) Emotions: Current Issues and Future Directions, pp. 38–81. New York: Guilford Press. Palmer, C. (1996) ‘Anatomy of a Performance: Sources of Musical Expression’, Music Perception 13: 433–53. Palmer, C. (1997) ‘Music Performance’, Annual Review of Psychology 48: 115–38. Penel, A. and Drake, C. (1999) ‘Seeking “One” Explanation for Expressive Timing’, in S.W. Yi (ed.) Music, Mind, and Science, pp. 271–97. Seoul: Seoul National University Press. Peretz, I. (1990) ‘Processing of Local and Global Musical Information by Unilateral Brain-Damaged Patients’, Brain 113: 1185–205. Peretz, I., Gagnon, L. and Bouchard, B. (1998) ‘Music and Emotion: Perceptual Determinants, Immediacy, and Isolation after Brain Damage’, Cognition 68: 111–41. Persson, R.S. (1993) ‘The Subjectivity of Musical Performance: An Exploratory Music-Psychological Real World Enquiry into the Determinants and Education of
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
Juslin: Five facets of musical expression Musical Reality’, unpublished doctoral dissertation, Huddersfield University, UK. Persson, R.S. (2001) ‘The Subjective World of the Performer’, in P.N. Juslin and J.A. Sloboda (eds) Music and Emotion: Theory and Research. New York: Oxford University Press. Repp, B.H. (1989) ‘Expressive Microstructure in Music: A Preliminary Perceptual Assessment of Four Composers’ “pulses”’, Music Perception 6: 243–74. Repp, B.H. (1997a) ‘Variability of Timing in Expressive Piano Performance Increases with Interval Duration’, Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 4: 530–4. Repp, B.H. (1997b) ‘The Aesthetic Quality of a Quantitatively Average Music Performance: Two Preliminary Experiments’, Music Perception 14: 419–44. Repp, B.H. (1998) ‘A Microcosm of Musical Expression: I. Quantitative Analyses of Pianists’ Timing in the Initial Measures of Chopin’s Etude in E major’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 104: 1085–100. Rink, J. (2003) ‘In Respect of Performance: The View from Musicology’, Psychology of Music 31(3): 303–23. Rohwer, D. (2001) ‘Instrumental Music Students’ Cognitive and Performance Understanding of Musical Expression’, Journal of Band Research 37: 17–28. Rostwall, A.-L. and West, T. (2001) ‘Interaktion och kunskapsutveckling (Interaction and Learning: A Study of Music Instrument Teaching), doctoral dissertation (with a summary in English), Stockholm University. Scherer, K.R. (1986) ‘Vocal Affect Expression: A Review and a Model for Future Research’, Psychological Bulletin 99: 143–65. Scruton, R. (1997) The Aesthetics of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schumacher, M. (1995) Crossroads: The Life and Music of Eric Clapton. New York: Hyperion. Seashore, C.E. (1938) Psychology of Music. New York: McGraw-Hill. Sergent, J., Zuck, E., Tenial, S. and MacDonall, B. (1992) ‘Distributed Neural Network Underlying Musical Sight-Reading and Keyboard Performance’, Science 257: 106–9. Shaffer, L.H. (1992) ‘How to Interpret Music’, in M.R. Jones and S. Holleran (eds) Cognitive Bases of Musical Communication, pp. 263–78. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association (APA). Shove, P. and Repp, B.H. (1995) ‘Musical Motion and Performance: Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives’, in J. Rink (ed.) The Practice of Performance: Studies in Musical Interpretation, pp. 55–83. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sloboda, J.A. (1983) ‘The Communication of Musical Metre in Piano Performance’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 35: 377–96. Sloboda, J.A. (1996) ‘The Acquisition of Musical Performance Expertise: Deconstructing the ‘Talent’ Account of Individual Differences in Musical Expressivity’, in K.A. Ericsson (ed.) The Road to Excellence, pp. 107–26. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Sloboda, J.A. (2000) ‘Individual Differences in Music Performance’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4: 397–403. Sloboda, J.A. and Juslin, P.N. (in press) ‘Affektive Prozesse: Emotion, Gefallen und Präferenzen (Affective Processes in Music: Emotion, Liking, and Preference)’, in T.H. Stoffer and R. Oerter (eds) Enzyklopädie der Psychologie, Musikpsychologie, Bd.1. Allgemeine Musikpsychologie. Göttingen: Hogrefe. Small, C. (1999) ‘Musicking: The Meanings of Performance and Listening: A Lecture’, Music Education Research 1: 9–21. Spencer, H. (1857) ‘The Origin and Function of Music’, Fraser’s Magazine 56: 396–408.
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.
301
302
Psychology of Music 31(3) Sundberg, J. (1988) ‘Computer Synthesis of Music Performance’, in J.A. Sloboda (ed.) Generative Processes in Music: The Psychology of Performance, Improvisation, and Composition, pp. 52–69. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Tait, M. (1992) ‘Teaching Strategies and Styles’, in R. Colwell (ed.) Handbook of Research on Music Teaching and Learning, pp. 525–34. New York: Schirmer Books. Thompson, W.F., Sundberg, J., Friberg, A. and Frydén, L. (1989) ‘The Use of Rules for Expression in the Performance of Melodies’, Psychology of Music 17: 63–82. Todd, N. (1985) ‘A Model of Expressive Timing in Tonal Music’, Music Perception 3: 33–58. Todd, N. (1992) ‘The Dynamics of Dynamics: A Model of Musical Expression’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 91: 3540–50. Trussoni, S.J., O’Malley, A. and Barton, A. (1988) ‘Human Emotion Communication by Touch: A Modified Replication of an Experiment by Manfred Clynes’, Perceptual and Motor Skills 66: 419–24. Van Oosten, P. (1993) ‘Critical Study of Sundberg’s Rules for Expression in the Performance of Melodies’, Contemporary Music Review 9: 267–74. Wing, A. and Kristofferson, A.B. (1973) ‘Response Delays and the Timing of Discrete Motor Responses’, Perception & Psychophysics 14: 5–12. Woody, R.H. (1999) ‘The Relationship between Explicit Planning and Expressive Performance of Dynamic Variations in an Aural Modeling Task’, Journal of Research in Music Education 47: 331–42. Woody, R.H. (2000) ‘Learning Expressivity in Music Performance: An Exploratory Study’, Research Studies in Music Education 14: 14–23. Woody, R.H. (2002) ‘Emotion, Imagery and Metaphor in the Acquisition of Musical Performance Skill’, Music Education Research 4: 213–24. Yamada, M. (1998) ‘Temporal Fluctuations in Musical Performances: Fluctuations Caused by the Limitations of Performers’ Controllability and by Artistic Expression’, in S.W. Yi (ed.) Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference on Music Perception and Cognition, pp. 353–63. Seoul: Seoul National University.
N . J U S L I N is Associate Professor of Psychology at the Department of Psychology, Uppsala University, Sweden, where he teaches courses on emotion, perception, and music psychology. He is the director of the inter-disciplinary research project Feedback-Learning of Musical Expressivity (Feel-ME) (http://www.psyk.uu.se/ hemsidor/musicpsy/). He is a member of the International Society for Research on Emotions (ISRE), and received ESCOM’s Young Researcher Award in 1996. He co-edited the book Music and Emotion (Oxford University Press, 2001) with John Sloboda. As well as his work as a researcher, Juslin has worked professionally as a guitar player and toured internationally with blues/jazz bands. Address: Patrik N. Juslin, Department of Psychology, Uppsala University, Box 1225, SE – 751 42 Uppsala, Sweden. [email:
[email protected]]
PAT R I K
Downloaded from http://pom.sagepub.com at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 17, 2008 © 2003 Society for Education, Music, and Psychology Research. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution.