Huntology: Ontological Pursuits and Still Lives

March 15, 2019 | Author: Annie McClanahan | Category: Ontology, Jacques Derrida, Metaphysics, Martin Heidegger, Hunting
Share Embed Donate


Short Description

Essay from diacritics journal by Antoine Traisnel...

Description

HUNTOLOGY ONTOLOGICAL PURSUITS AND STILL LIVES

Antoine trAisnel

Nw th huntr stps asid . . . and th naturalist cs rward. — Richard Rhds,  John James Audubon At the beginning o the nineteenth century in Western Europe and North America, one hunt ended and another began. A orm o pursuit long associated with the acquisition o knowledge,1 hunting became all the more prevalent as a cultural and epistemological logic when technological advances secured the dominance o the human and made it no longer necessary to ensure the gain or deense o territory against animals. No longer a threat to humans, animals became objects o study and exhibition. While the analogy makes little sense today, in the mid-eighteenth century, hunting  was oten described as a orm o war. Diderot’s  Encyclopédie denes hunting as “all the sorts o wars that we wage against animals” (toutes les sortes de guerres que nous aisons aux animaux). J. M. Coetzee’s 2003 novel  Elizabeth Costello urther explores this analogy. The title character describes a time when humans were still at war with the animals: “We had a war once against the animals, which we called hunting, though in act war and hunting are the same thing (Aristotle saw it clearly),” Costello explains. “That war went on or millions o years. We won it denitively only a ew hundred years ago, when we invented guns. It is only since victory became absolute that we have been able to aord to cultivate compassion.”2 The very possibility or humans and animals to be at war with each other implies a relative symmetry and supposes that they share a common political territory. Costello proposes a history in which they cease to cohabit by imagining the conditions under which the humans’ victory became “absolute.” She nevertheless states that some animals remain unaware that the war is over (rats, we are told, have not surrendered). The problem that Costello raises is not so much that the hunt is a war but that this war is thought to be over. And that we are at peace. The supposedly absolute victory o the hunt resulted in a “distribution o the sensible” that demands to be reassessed.3 What has this antasized victory eected in the West, both or (what we call) humans and (what we call) animals?4 The human’s exceptional status proves but a recent development and one that emerges out o a predatory relation to other animals. Costello provocatively suggests that the introduction o guns had a proound impact on how the human’s status as überpredator has been naturalized to the point o invisibility.5 How and when has it been it possible or some humans to envision their victory as “absolute”? With technological progress, the dominance o the human over (other) animals became more pronounced, almost sel-evident. Beore this apparent victory, the war o the species could be perceived as ongoing, and even interminable.6 This essay argues that this “event” took place at the turn o the nineteenth century, when the human-animal relation underwent a proound transormation in the West. The hunt oers a compelling paradigm or reading this transormation. A certain epistemophilia that emerged during this period—as evidenced by Buon’s colossal  Histoire naturelle,7 Cuvier’s enterprise o systematic classication, and Darwin’s 1831 zoological expedition on the Beagle (named ater a hunting dog)8—can be seen as the continuation o the hunt by other means. The shiting valence o the hunt rom martial to episte-

DI ACR ITI CS Vlu 40.2 2012 4–25 ©2012 by Th Jhns Hpkins Univrsity Prss

Antin Traisnl is a PhD candidat in th Dpartnt  Cparativ Litratur at Brwn Univrsity. H als hlds a dctrat in Arican Litratur r th Univrsité CharlsdGaull, Lill 3. H is currntly cplting a bk anuscript, Blasted Allegories:  Après-coups critiques de Nathaniel  Hawthorne, which addrsss th critical

dinsins  allgry in Nathanil Hawthrn’s rancs rthcing r Aux orges de Vulcain, 2013.

6

Figure 1.

Jhn Jas Audubn GoLDeN eAGLe (  Aquila chrysaetos ), 1833 Watrclr, pastl, graphit, and slctiv glazing, 38 x 25 1/2 in. Cllctin  Th NwYrk Histrical Scity. Digital iag cratd by oppnhir editins.

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

Huntlgy

>>

7

Antin Traisnl

Figure 2.

Waltn Frd DeLIRIUm, 2004 Watrclr, guach, ink, and pncil n papr, 62 5/8 x 43 1/8 in. 159.1 x 109.5 c. Curtsy th artist and Paul Kasin Gallry

8

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

mological nds a burgeoning archive in the emergence o natural history museums and science institutions, which depended on the products o the hunt or their specimen collections. No individual is more representative o this shit than John James Audubon. Audubon created scientic documents and works o art at a moment when the United States was eager to dene and promulgate its intellectual identity as an emergent nation.9 The amed naturalist and artist was above all a hunter: “Audubon engaged birds with the intensity (and sometimes the erocity) o a hunter because hunting was the cultural rame out o which his encounter with birds emerged,” writes Richard Rhodes. “In early nineteenth-century America, when wild game was still extensively harvested or ood, observation or hunting had not yet disconnected rom observation or scientic knowledge.”10 Hunting emerges as the “cultural rame” o Audubon’s artistic and scientic practice. It is in this rame that the gaze o the artist-scientist is shown to be inextricable rom that o the hunter. Contrary to Rhodes, I argue that observation or hunting and observation or knowledge did not then get “disconnected.” Instead, at the moment when science is said to have become “objective,” hunting recedes rom overt consciousness, only to inltrate urther what could be called the epistemological unconscious. It is this very moment when the labor o the hunter ostensibly gets detached rom epistemological pursuits that demands critical attention. How can we account or the convergence o the artistic and the scientic that Audubon’s practice represents as one o  capture? What consequences, epistemological and ontological, do the predatory pursuits have, both or the hunted “object” and or the hunting “subject”? This essay elucidates the mechanism rom which the gure o “modern man” emerges in a dynamic relationship to the animal. I will call this dialectical mechanism o capture and exclusion huntology. >>

th excu f h subjc

. . . all huntrs lk alik. — Waltr Bnjain, The Arcades Project  In the oreground, almost too large to be contained by the painting, the eagle soars into the air, threatening to exceed the limits o the canvas. In the background, almost imperceptible on the immaculate coat o snow, the hunter is dwared by the majesty o the surrounding massis. Audubon’s Golden Eagle (1833), rom the celebrated 1838 volume o  etchings, The Birds o America, shows the imposing bird holding a dead or dying rabbit in its clenched talon (g. 1). The French-American naturalist’s painting is nearly identical to contemporary American artist Walton Ford’s Delirium (2004) (g. 2). The images, were they not separated by more than 170 years, might have ormed a d iptych. Audubon’s aim was to oer a aithul representation o the (then) exotic eathered auna o the New Continent. The depiction o the eagle is inormed by his careul scrutiny o the animal, and yet, despite its patent realism, the scene is imbued with an unnatural quality. The composition is elaborate. The impeccable whiteness o the prey

Huntlgy

>>

9

Antin Traisnl

reinorces the erceness o the eagle, the totemic animal par excellence. For Audubon, however, the Golden Eagle is not an allegory; he valued the bird or its ornithological singularity and uniqueness. And yet its allegorical dimension is undeniable. The eagle seems to have been recruited as a mascot or the American colonial project. In Audubon’s painting, the bird is soaring westward, charting the course o the American empire’s Maniest Destiny. As art historian Theodore Stebbins has noted, Golden Eagle appears to be modeled ater Jacques-Louis David’s painting,  Bonaparte Crossing the Alps at Grand-Saint-Bernard  (1800).11 I Walton Ford’s  Delirium can be said to be a descendent o Audubon’s Golden Eagle, then David’s  Bonaparte Crossing the Alps is its ancestor (see g. 3). Rhodes has noted the commonalities between the two, namely their mirroring color schemes, the pointing gesture o Bonaparte’s hand as reproduced in the eagle’s beak, and the upward trajectory o their nearly identical landscapes:

His triplpakd, snwcvrd untains ar brrwd r th distant ar right   Bonaparte, vd rward and cntrd bhind his dark, rcky landscap t irrriag th clrs and rs  th whit har and th dark agl. Light ding int bth picturs r th uppr lt illuinats th agl and its whit pry as it illuinats Napln and his whit hrs. Th drp  bld swating r th har’s trn y duplicats a rd tu ch  bridry at Napln’s waist. But th cnqurr and his raring whit hrs cbin in th agl int n agnicnt raptr, urging upward: th agl’s bating wings duplicat Napln’s gldn, windswirld cap, whil th agl’s pnbakd cry is th hrs’s pn uthd whinny and th agl’s glar  danc is th hrs’s bulging wild y. 12 While the eagle gets confated with Napoleon (and his white horse), Audubon seems to position himsel as a simple soldier. Despite this seeming modesty, as Rhodes suggests, Audubon has already climbed the mountain, contrary to his heroic model, and is “shinnying down the chasm with his prize.”13 Moreover, i Napoleon is the eagle, then what are we to understand o the dead eagle on the hunter’s shoulder? This relation invites a closer look at the place o Audubon’s oeuvre in the representation and dissemination o  the US imperial project.14 The predator literally replaces the imperial gure o Napoleon, and colonization thereby becomes naturalized through the moti o hunting. The lack o realism in Audubon’s painting is not only conveyed by the symbolic reading that it invites, but also by the rigid quality o the animals portrayed. The eagle and the rabbit appear as i they have just escaped rom a taxidermist’s workshop. Instead o 

Figure 3.

JacqusLuis David BoNAPARTe FRANCHISSANT Le GRAND-SAINT-BeRNARD, 1800 oil n canvas, 259 × 221 c. Pht: Gérard Blt. Réunin ds musés Natinaux / Art Rsurc, NY. Châtaux d malaisn t BisPréau, Ruilmalaisn, Franc lt Audubn, GoLDeN eAGLe right

10

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

the intended lielike impression o the bird o prey, Audubon presents us with something  more closely resembling a nature morte, or still lie. And as it happens, it was a still lie, as Audubon’s process is brought to light by Ford’s painting. With its smoking beak, its claw caught in a leghold trap, and the small metal spear piercing its heart, Ford’s raptor appears at rst glance to have been taken rom a book o ables. In a way, Delirium is ar more historically accurate than Audubon’s original, rom which it draws its inspiration. Ford, who specializes in large-scale animal watercolors, exposes the abricatedness o Audubon’s hunting scene. Audubon had been asked by Columbian Museum (Boston) proprietor Ethan Allen Greenwood to identiy a live eagle that Greenwood had purchased rom a man who hunted ox with spring-traps in New Hampshire’s White Mountains. He explains in his 1835 Ornithological Biography that Greenwood agreed to sell him the coveted animal. Having brought it home, Audubon conesses a ascination with the bird:

I ust acknwldg that as I watchd his y, and bsrvd his lks  prud disdain, I lt twards hi nt s gnrusly as I ught t hav dn. At tis I was hal inclind t rstr t hi his rd, that h ight rturn t his nativ untains; nay, I svral tis thught hw plasing it wuld b t s hi sprad ut his brad wings and sail away twards th rcks  his wild haunts; but thn, radr, s n sd t whispr that I ught t tak th prtrait  th agnicnt bird; and I abandnd th r gnrus dsign  stting hi at librty, r th xprss purps  shwing yu his sblanc. 15 The “little voice” that tells him to execute the animal might not be just that o his scientic instinct, but also Audubon’s uneasiness and ascination with the gaze o the animal, which seems to observe the naturalist in return (the execution acquires the quality o  a sacrice). Audubon’s rendition o the eagle’s “ace,” compared to that o Ford, is distinctly anthropomorphic. Finding it too challenging to draw it alive, Audubon considered electrocuting the animal but decided to asphyxiate the bird by shutting it in a small room with a pot o burning charcoal. “I waited, expecting every moment to hear him all down rom his perch,” he writes, “but ater listening or hours, I opened the door, raised the blankets, and peeped under them amidst a mass o suocating umes. There stood the Eagle on his perch, with his bright unfinching eye turned towards me, and as lively and vigorous as ever!” Audubon repeated the operation several times but the animal reused to die:

There stood the Eagle on his perch, with his bright unfinching eye turned towards me, and as lively and vigorous as ever!

W wr narly drivn r ur h in a w hurs by th stiing vapurs, whil th nbl bird cntinud t stand rct, and t lk danc at us whnvr w apprachd his pst  artyrd. His rc danur prcludd all intrnal applicatin, and at last I was c plld t rsrt t a thd always usd as th last xpdint, and a st ctual n. I thrust a lng pintd pic  stl thrugh his hart, whn y prud prisnr instantly ll dad, withut vn ruing a athr.16

Huntlgy

>>

11

Antin Traisnl

It is this invisible violence that Ford exploits as he satirizes the arti ciality o Audubon’s composition by not only mirroring it but also distorting the mirrored image. Ford capitalizes on the irony that made Audubon kill the bird only to reintroduce it aterwards, pictorially, in its natural habitat. “It’s that backstory,” Greg Cook observes, “that tale o conquest and colonization and accumulated injuries against nature, that is at the heart o Walton Ford’s allegories.”17 Ford explains that he became interested in using  watercolor because he wanted “things to look like Audubons.” He describes his paintings as “ake Audubons.” “I twisted the subject matter a bit and got inside [Audubon’s] head and tried to paint as i it was really his tortured soul portrayed,” Ford says, “as i  his hand betrayed him and painted what he didn’t want to expose about himsel. And it was very important to me to make them look like . . . he painted them, but that they escaped out o him.”18 In Ford’s watercolor, the eagle is eastbound and very much alive, despite the shackles that mark its enslavement to representation. Ford’s eagle is represented with a tiny spear in its heart and thick plumes o smoke escaping its beak. In contrast, the gure o the hunter, who in Audubon’s painting carries a dead eagle on his back, is instead pictured lying in the snow as i dead. Cook suggests that, “like an avenging spirit, Ford imagines Audubon as a tiny hunter in the background, stricken, collapsed into the snow at the top o a wintry hill.”19 Ford’s elucidation o the circumstances surrounding the production o Audubon’s painting accounts or the model’s “fat” appearance, its pictorial rigor mortis (g. 4). The eagle appears conned within the canvas, as i its rame were a kind o trap and the naturalist-cum-artist regarded nature with the eyes o a hunter. In Audubon’s original, the arrogant raptor had indeed been captured by the painter, who had included his own image in the let-hand corner dressed in hunting gear. The eagle is a hunter, a erce predator that lives o the fesh o other animals. Audubon makes an appearance in the painting as the arch-predator, the hunter’s hunter. This mise en abyme is all the more intriguing because Audubon has not usually been regarded as a particularly sel-refexive artist. The naturalist’s sel-portrait appears comically small, almost irrelevant, and yet the whole scene is depicted rom his perspective. In the painting, however, the hunter’s gaze is not directed toward the bird but appears to be ocused on what is in ront o him. In Golden Eagle, Audubon’s hunter/beholder presents himsel  as seeing the world rom below, whereas, as a painter, he adopts a God’s- or bird’s-eye view, typically associated with an all-encompassing perspective and betraying a antasy o omniscience. (Ironically, however, at the very moment that our hunter adopts a bird’s-

Figure 4.

Fil still r John James Audubon: Drawn rom Nature , 2007. Artist Waltn Frd dnstrats Audubn’s tchniqu  “psing” th dad anial n a grid in rdr t draw it. Th cag lik grid will thn b blitratd by th landscap paintd vr it.

12

 Animal (Bird)

Human (Hunter) Pictorial Style

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

eye view, his gaze is obstructed by a gigantic bird o his own making!) The painting literalizes the problem that representation poses to objective knowledge, which postulates an irreducible distance between the subject knowing and the object known. I the hunter depicted in the margin o Audubon’s painting is intended to represent the painter himsel, then the scene observed both rom above and below exposes the irreconcilable dualism o the observer. The purportedly realistic rendition is shown to be highly manuactured and hardly “natural,” i by natural one means something let untouched by the hand o man. Audubon represents two versions o the same eagle, which appears to be symbolically both captured (on the hunter’s shoulder) and ree (as a bird). The act that the eagle is at once dead and alive in the picture, not unlike JoHN JAmeS AUDUBoN WALToN FoRD Schrödinger’s cat in his box, establishes a Golden Eagle, 1833 Delirium, 2004 correlation between the killing o the emDpictd as living and r and Dpictd as dying but unttrd pirical animal and its transormation into as capturd and dad n th a representative specimen. Ford exposes huntr’s shuldr Audubon as having a split identity: he is both the naturalist ascinated with underLanding and acing astward Saring in th sky, wstward standing this living creature and the artist Aliv, straddling a tr alln vr Dad, lying n th grund, who must execute the object or the sake o  a prcipic “attnd ut” his own artistic execution. Yoking the lie and death o the animal Ralistic but with at quality and Figural, r paintrly but r to that o the hunter/observer, Audubon’s slightly vrwrught livly and Ford’s tableaux de chasse make maniest the dialectical character o the hunter’s Painting titld atr th zlgical original titl indicating that perspective. The chart above summarizes catgry  th anial rprsnt th painting ds nt hav any the important dierences between the two d, with Latin na in brackts bjctiv prtnsin paintings. Ford’s adaptation reveals the destinies o the hunter and the hunted to be deeply intertwined, suggesting that the hunter no longer has a raison d’être i the eagle breaks ree. One may go so ar as to perceive in Audubon’s painting the hunter’s unlikely “becoming bird” as he is himsel perched on a allen tree. The hunter is, urthermore, represented as under threat, balanced over a precipice, occupying a precarious position. The dynamic o the hunt is presented as not merely a question o the hunted but also, essentially, one o the hunter. Audubon’s painting indexes the problematic representation o the animal as inormed by a preconception o the human as a hunter. With huntology, I argue that our Western conception o the human is contingent upon such predatory representations o the animal.

Huntlgy

>>

>>

13

Antin Traisnl

ogca Puu

Thn wuldn’t that an d this st purly wh apprachs ach thing as ar as pssibl with thught itsl, and wh nithr puts any sight int this thinking nr drags in any thr sns alng with his rasning; but instad, using unadultratd thught itsl all by itsl, h attpts t hunt dwn ach  th bings  thēreuein tōn ontōn  that’s unadultratd and itsl all by itsl, and nc h’s rd hisl as ar as pssibl r ys and ars and, s t spak, r his whl bdy, bcaus it shaks th sul up and dsn’t lt hr attain truth and thughtulnss whn th bdy cuns with hr—isn’t this th an, Siias, i anyn, wh will hit upn what is? —Plat, Phaedo Michel Foucault’s study o Diego Velásquez’s 1656 painting,  Las Meninas, opening  The Order o Things, oers a reading o classical perspectivalism ounded on an irreducible invisibility. O the epistemic model presented by Velásquez, Foucault observes that “the proound invisibility o what one sees is inseparable rom the invisibility o the person seeing—despite all mirrors, refections, imitations, and portraits.” He argues that something (the author, the beholder, or the subject) is always let out o the rame: “the unction o that refection is to draw into the interior o the picture what is intimately oreign to it: the gaze which has organized it and the gaze or which it is displayed.”20 I the entire world were captured in the representation, it would not be a representation but the world itsel (or the world would be pure representation). This impossible coincidence between the subject and its representation heralds the emancipation o the human subject rom the world it represents. Velásquez insists on this representational divide, but, as Foucault suggests, the separation is also an elision o the subject, which he suggests will only be ully emancipated rom its object in the nineteenth century. The human subject, quite undamentally, creates itsel by extracting itsel rom the world that it seeks to describe. To paraphrase Cary Wole, the human gains knowledge o itsel as a knowing subject only to lose the world: by excepting himsel rom the picture, he has accidentally drawn the contours o  its own image. Nature is thus born out o  man’s dissociation rom it.21 Audubon’s animal representations are exemplary o the transition to the epistemological regime on which the modern ordering o things is grounded. In Objectivity, Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison situate Audubon in a time beore “mechanical objectivity” became the predominant epistemic virtue. O his depiction o the Crested Titmouse, they write: “Audubon’s bird drawings were printed on double elephant olio paper in order to approximate lie size as closely as possible. Yet Audubon’s insistence that birds be depicted in natural habitats and poses, observed rst-hand by the artistnaturalist, did not preclude mannered compositions . . . or anthropomorphic stances and descriptions.”22 They remind us o the extent to which Audubon’s paintings were

By excepting himsel rom the picture, he has accidentally drawn the contours o its own image. Nature is thus born out o man’s dissociation rom it.

14

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

“criticized by some contemporary naturalists as alsications o nature” whereas similar artistic method had won English naturalist George Edwards the Royal Society o  London’s Copley Medal in 1750.23 Ann Shelby Blum agrees that the “ethos o objectivity, expressed in the technical language o systematic description o generic and specic types, was deeply at odds with Audubon’s celebration o the observer as participant and his recording o singular events whose actors were individual creatures.”24 The ambition o the “truth-to-nature” regime in which Daston and Galison situate Audubon is to reveal “the one and only ur-orm o a plant, animal, or crystal,” while the mechanical objective paradigm wishes to remove entirely the knowing subject rom the known object.25 Audubon embodies the pivot between these epistemic regimes because, on the one hand, he highlights the labor (as an artist, hunter, and scientist) needed to produce his object, and, on the other hand, he hopes to render a lielike image o the bird as it really is. In the “mechanical objectivity” model, however, the sel qua sel is identied as the source o error and thus must be eliminated. This drive toward objectivity may explain why, when The Birds o America was published, the hunter had disappeared rom the background: “Whether on his own or on Audubon’s instruction, [the printer] Robert Havell removed the little woodsman rom the plate he made o the Golden Eagle, Plate 181 o The Birds o America, removing along with it a level o meaning that only the original watercolor has sustained.”26 It is this very eacement that gives birth to what Foucault has identied as modern man. The split described by Foucault between human observers and nonhuman others appears subconsciously literalized—and simultaneously obliterated—by Audubon’s rendition. However unrealistic, Audubon’s perspective is not shown as such. The painting purports to oer an unaltered image o what the wild animal really looks like. Contrary to the ingenious composition o  Las Meninas that is always chasing its subject out o the rame, Audubon’s painting achieves a allacious reconciliation between the human observer and the observed nature. Whereas Velásquez and Foucault articulate the paradox o the spectator/subject, Audubon reconciles the observer and nature through their mere juxtaposition within the painting. The creative gap between the sel and the world is thereby negated, and the human born out o this elision is let to contemplate proudly its own image in the representation o the animal. Placed side by side with Ford’s adaptation, the human’s biurcated subjectivity is revealed to be produced by the eect o taking itsel “out o the picture” (in the published version o the painting). The split perspective at work in Audubon’s painting is emblematic o a predatory drive at the heart o some Western modern representations o the animal. As many have compellingly argued, these representations constitute a humanist archive that privileges logics o mastery and domestication and rests upon a strict, i ill- dened, demarcation between human and non-human animals. At issue in humanist representations o  animals is more than “just” the way in which animals are treated but the very concept o humanity, and thereby o humanism.27 The political and ethical principles on which Giorgio Agamben’s work is ounded underline the inextricable anities binding the

Huntlgy

>>

15

Antin Traisnl

question o the animal to the practical issue o dening who gets to be called human and what, as a result o this partition, is excluded rom humanhood. In The Open, Agamben describes what he calls “the anthropological machine” as a simultaneously inclusionary and exclusionary apparatus:

Insar as th prductin  an thrugh th ppsitin an/anial, huan/inhuan, is at stak hr, th achin ncssarily unctins by ans  an xclusin which is als always alrady a capturing and an inclusin which is als always alrady an xclusin. Indd, pr cisly bcaus th huan is alrady prsuppsd vry ti, th achin actually prducs a kind  stat  xcptin, a zn  indtrinacy in which th utsid is nthing but th xclusin  an insid and th insid is in turn nly th inclusin  an utsid. 28 It is interesting that Agamben would call upon the metaphor o the machine to account or the process o separation at work in our humanistic culture, doubtless to indicate in a Nietzschean gesture the ahuman oundations o that atereect that is the human. The human is no longer homo aber (the maker) but homo actum (the “sel” made man), or, rather, he is both. Playully evoking Descartes’s animal-machine, the image o  the machine undermines the idea by which individual sovereignty and autonomous subjectivity constitute the logical premises o the human condition. Following Nietzsche, I would propose that the issue might not so much be, as Agamben suggests, to “stop” the anthropological machine,29 as to understand its modus operandi and recognize it as a machinic process over which “we humans” have little control. Instead o lamenting the violence committed against animals perceived as machines, Nietzsche recommends that we extend Descartes’s mechanical approach to the human being. One should “unlearn” to bind ethics and politics to questions o rational or divine agency: rom this perspective, rationality and spirituality are to be seen as nothing more than the undesirable byproducts o the anthropogenic machine.30 What is at issue in The Open is the exposure o the “irony” o the sel-perpetuating  mechanisms that dene the ontological status o the human. The machine should not be thought o as a simple dragnet catching all that is not human, i only because “what is human” is always yet to be decided. The problem is not one o “classication” but o “relation.”31 In act, Agamben seems to say, it is the chase and not the arrest—the capturing and not the capture—o the animal that determines who deserves to be labeled human and what is let over. The Open insists on the interminability, indeed the openness, o the twoold movement o capture and exclusion at work in the making o the anthropos . Instead o running ater yet another singular eature that would be “proper” to human beings, rather than trying to establish another decisive specic barrier between the human and the nonhuman, Agamben o ers to examine the stalling logic o the “proper.”

The machine should not be thought o as a simple dragnet catching all that is not human, i only because “what is human” is always yet to be decided.

16

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

The Open can be read as an attempt to re-dynamize an all-too-static anthropological ontology, which Derrida describes as “the fxism o the Cartesian cogito.”32 Near the conclusion o  The Open, Agamben synthesizes his baroque overview o  the human/animal dierentiation in Western philosophical discourses with a series o  theses. In his second thesis, Agamben argues that ontology, the branch o metaphysics that concerns itsel with matters o essence and being, is sustained by a logic o the chase that works to exclude animals:

ontlgy, r rst philsphy, is nt an inncuus acadic disciplin, but in vry sns th undantal pratin in which anthrpgnsis, th bcing huan  th living bing, is ralizd. Fr th bginning, taphysics is takn up in this stratgy: it cncrns prcisly that ta that cplts and prsrvs th vrcing  anial physis in th dirctin   huan histry.33 The overcoming o the human’s animal nature does not happen overnight; rather, it never happens inasmuch as it is ceaselessly happening  even though the human is, in eect, always presupposed  to be a meta-animal: rom the outset, “metaphysics is taken up” (or captured) in this ontological pursuit. The inclusionary/exclusionary logic at the heart o anthropological ontology is the result o huntology’s ongoing process o incorporation and expulsion. Oering a model or thinking the space maintained between man and animal, huntology queries the mode o apprehension o a philosophy that works to maintain the distance between the hunter and his prey, between the philosopher and his animal object. Huntology calls into question the deerral o knowing on which philosophical knowledge, in line with Descartes’s metaphysical school o thought, is based. This philosophy, Derrida hypothesizes, “governs, in the sense o being prevalent or hegemonic in, all domains that treat the question o the animal, indeed, where the animal itsel is treated: zoology, ethology, anthropology, but rst o all ontology, mastery by means o knowledge.”34 In  Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche delimits the ground o the “human soul” as a “hunting ground” or a “born psychologist and lover o the ‘big-game hunt.’”35 We might literalize Nietzsche’s analogy to suggest that the human subject is not merely studied but also constituted by his ontological p ursuits. As Heidegger has argued, tracking evidence o one’s humanity implies that one knows what one i s ater and thereore, that the human is both presupposed and deduced by such a metaphysical quest. 36 The validity o one’s hypothesis rests on evidence that, in turn, is sanctioned as such i and only i one already knows what one is looking or. Such vertigo-inducing recursivity turns The Fundamental Concepts o Metaphysics into a sort o thriller in which Heidegger investigates the appropriate method to “initially approach and subsequently pursue” his “subject matter,” namely, the animal, one that huntology aspires to render apparent and tactical.37 As in the case o Audubon’s Golden Eagle, the hunter who has “gone ater” the animal is motivated by a certain idea, sustained by a certain ideal that he pursues. The living  animal in turn poses a resistance to, that is it opposes , the hunter, who, “or the express purpose o shewing his semblance” to the beholder has to execute it and paradoxically to

Huntlgy

>>

17

Antin Traisnl

lose his object.38 Audubon’s example is characteristic o the raptorial character o certain representations o animals and, subsequently, o the production o knowledge derived rom these representations. In the end, it is not the bird in its irreducible singularity that is described but the hunter’s antasized relationship to the bird as exemplary o its subspecies. The “capture” o the animal inorms us not so much about the animal as such but rather about our negative relationship to what we call “the animal,” and by extension, about the ormation o  our ontological status as human beings. I the anthropological machine is relentless, this is because the hunt is not so much concerned with catching the prey but with the hunt itsel, or rather with the way it ensures the human dominion by catching and rejecting the animal in the same gesture. “I ear that this is the origin o hunting,” writes Michel Serres. “The only things hunted are those that have to be chased away.”39 It is revealing that the French word chasser contains within it two seemingly irreconcilable meanings. This double meaning expresses the apparent paradox at the heart o a concept that means simultaneously to hunt—that is, to go ater, to chase—and to repel—that is, to chase away rom onesel (or instance, chasser le naturel40 ). Whereas the English “to hunt” would seem to privilege the pursuit o the prey (indulging the antasy o ultimate capture), the polysemy o the French illuminates the complexity o the term that illustrates the production o knowledge about the animal. In Specters o Marx, Derrida plays on the double valence o the word to show that the hunt (here, the antagonistic ascination Karl Marx had or the German philosopher Max Stirner) is interminable and nds its object not in the prey it pursues but in itsel:

In the end, it is not the bird in its irreducible singularity that is described but the hunter ’s antasized relationship to the bird as exemplary o its subspecies.

I chas you. I pursu yu. I run atr yu t chas yu away r hr. . . . And th ghst ds nt lav its pry, naly, its huntr. It has undrstd instantly that n is hunting it just t hunt it, chasing it away nly s as t chas atr it. Spcular circl: n chass atr in rdr t chas away, n pursus, sts  in pursuit  sn t ak hi , but n aks hi , distancs hi, xpulss hi s as t g atr hi again and rain in pursuit. on chass sn away, kicks hi ut th dr, xcluds hi, r drivs hi away. But it is in rdr t chas atr hi, sduc hi, rach hi, and thus kp hi cls at hand. 41 Derrida exploits a similar semantic ambiguity in his posthumous The Animal That There ore I Am, in which he laments Western philosophy’s ailing o the animal. He challenges the ethics o a philosophy sustained by a logic o hunting that would strive to rame the animal in a tableau de chasse (“stilling the wildlie,” so to speak). From Descartes to Lacan, Derrida asserts, philosophers have labored to preserve the ontological dierence between man and animal by consistently depriving the animal o the capacity to respond. Derrida evokes the mythic gure o Bellerophon: “He deserves a ten-day conerence alone. He represents, as is well known, the gure o the hunter. He ollows. He is he who

18

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

ollows. He ollows and persecutes the beast. He would say: I am (ollowing) (  je suis ), I pursue, I track, overcome, and tame the animal.”42 The title,  L’animal que donc je suis, characteristically plays on the double meaning o  the French “je suis” that can be translated as both “I am” and “I ollow,” which orces the translator to write each time “I am (ollowing).” Derrida tricks language into orcing  the reader’s identication with the animal (“I am the animal”) and into recognizing the distance maintained by the one who goes ater the animal (“I am ollowing the animal”). This conceit enables him to apprehend the anthropological ontology as a relational economy rather than a predetermined state o things. I chase the animal ergo sum. This is huntology: the injection o a dynamism—oten unacknowledged, as Agamben makes clear—inside an overly static, lieless anthropological ontology. Not only does the term huntology intend to conjure up the repressed dynamic out o which the gure o the human emerges, not only does it demand, ollowing Derrida, that we develop an “alternative ontology o animal lie, an ontology in which the human-animal distinction i s called radically into question,”43 it also renders visible the violence done to the living beings (or example, women or oreigners along with beasts and vermin) that are chased away rom the category o the human. This exclusion recalls Derrida’s notion o carnophallogocentrism, denoting the traditionally masculinist dimension o the hunt, a critique o  which remains to be developed in uture work. Questioning the premise o any unqualied distinction between human and nonhuman animals, huntology oers the opportunity to rethink what is usually excluded rom the realm o ontology. Hence the transparent echo with Derrida’s “hauntology,” a key principle o which is the welcoming in philosophy o what philosophy tends to discard, namely, specters, ghosts, and other ephemeral appearances that lack ontological substance. In Specters o Marx, Derrida himsel makes the relationship between hunting and haunting explicit:

This lgic and this tplgy  th paradxical hunt whs gur, bginning br Plat, will hav travrsd th whl histry  philsphy, r prcisly  th ntlgical inqust r inquisitin shuld nt b tratd as a rhtrical rnant whn n rads The Maniesto o the Communist Party : its rst sntncs, as w saw, idiatly assciat th gur   haunting with that  hunting.44 Arming the possibility o accounting or that which is not recognized by ontology, Derrida deontologizes philosophy. This essay wishes to expand the scope o this gesture by opening ontology, with the concept o huntology, to animal li e. Huntology is both a critical paradigm or “tracking down” the anthropocentric prejudice undergirding a dominant Western philosophical discourse and a reparative theory that seeks to nuance the dogmatism o human/animal demarcations and to rethink, without necessarily doing  away with, that which calls itsel human.

Huntlgy

>>

>>

19

Antin Traisnl

Ccu: ergo sum 

N cnsciusnss that w wuld rcgniz as cnsciusnss. N awarnss, as ar as w can ak ut,  a sl with a histry. What I ind is what tnds t c nxt. Thy hav n cnsciusnss thereore. Thrr what? Thrr w ar r t us th r ur wn nds? Thrr w ar r t kill th? — J. m. Ctz, Elizabeth Costello So then, what, thereore? What comes ater the human, as the notion o posthumanism would seem to herald? To answer this question, Derrida proposes that we invent a dierent, “unheard-o grammar”45 to articulate dierently the relationship between the human and the nonhuman. The Animal That Thereore I Am is punctuated by a series o “thereores”—recalling Descartes’s cogito ergo sum. It adopts, as well as mocks, the predatory logic o this grammatical hinge that poses, really imposes , a methodical connection between a series o proposals or events. One recalls that Derrida amously opens his essay “Diérance” with a “thereore” that is not preceded by anything in order to show the potential violence made possible by this adverb. The “thereore” postulates a logical sequence, it presupposes a “beore” and an “ater” and determines a hierarchical order, as is shown by the Bellerophon passage. But it also implies a categorical statement. There is something authoritative and nal in the binding character o the thereore, something exclusive. “When we say ‘thereore,’ when we consider a proposition as concluded, we make it the object o an assertion,” writes Deleuze. “We set aside the premises and arm it or itsel, independently. We relate it to the state o aairs which it denotes, independently o the implications which constitute its signication.”46 The dismissal o the premises upon which the “thereore” depends echoes the way in which the human excepts himsel rom the picture he paints o the animal. Huntology exposes the temptation o a purely logical discourse that would enorce a rational order on the heterogeneity o animal lie. The point is neither to abolish all notions o order, nor is it to “stop” the anthropological machine, nor still to cease hunting. Rather, the imperative is to reassess what kind o relationship the human has to the animal. Right ater mentioning the logic that, according to him, guided the most “paradigmatic, dominant, and normative” gures o Western philosophy (namely, Kant, Heidegger, Levinas, and Lacan), Derrida writes:

The point is neither to abolish all notions o  order, nor is it to “stop” the anthropological machine, nor still to cease hunting.

Th stratgis  this right   or more  to ollow  [drit d suit] that I hav just vkd r sbl ths  th hunt, whthr th anial thrby llws its dsir, what is dsirabl in its dsir r in its nd, as will b said by ths wh wish, ut  dsir r nd, t bliv in an irnclad distinctin btwn th tw, dsir and nd, just as in th distinctin btwn an and anial, r whthr, whil llwing its driv, th anial nds itsl llwd, trackd by

20

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

th driv  th thr. And w shuld nt xclud th pssibility that th sa living cratur is at th sa ti llwr and llwd, huntr knwing itsl t b huntd, sducr and sducd, prscutr and ugitiv, and that th tw rcs  th sa stratgy, indd  th sa vnt, ar cnjugatd nt nly in th sa anial, th sa animot , but in th sa instant.47 The logic o ollowing presupposes the possibility o an a nity (o a relation as a relative) and yet, in the same gesture, contributes to producing the very dichotomy it promises to eradicate. In lieu o chasing the animal, the hunter chases it away. For Derrida, “hauntology” evokes and revokes in the same gesture the violence o ontology: it exceeds the connes o ontology, it is irreducible to it, but it is also what makes ontology possible, what  justies it. Likewise, huntology a ccounts or the ormation o anthropological ontology and oers a poetic grammar or deconstructing the “ironclad” demarcation between the nonhuman and the human animal. Huntology should be understood as eluding the logic o philosophical language, dreaming instead o a non-hypotactic, illogical grammar that would upset certain preestablished associations concerning the animal and disturb the unyielding predation o grammatical predication. I huntology i s not ossied into an ontology, i it is not stabilized, i it remains cynegetic, i it opens itsel to other orms o  existence, i it does not try to erase the traces o its own process, it might provide the grounds or an alternative, non-nihilistic posthumanist perspective.

Huntlgy

>>

21

Antin Traisnl

Notes Th ntanglnt  hunting with th acquisi tin  knwldg is nthing nw. Prhistric cav paintings, r xapl, dnstrat a lngstanding intrdpndnc btwn ritual, pistlgical, and prdatrial practics. 1

Ctz, Elizabeth Costello, 104. on th issu  slavry in Politics 1–8., Aristtl argus that war r th purps  acquisitin can b just, and th kind  acquisitin h is thinking  invlvs acquiring thr huans wh ar “intndd by natur t b gvrnd” i.., slavs. H thn likns this war t hunting th “acquiring”  wild basts. Aristtl was prhaps inuncd by Xnphn’s Cynegeticus, or Treatise on Hunting, in which hunting is dscribd as “an xcllnt prparatin r th tils  war”  Xnphn, Minor  Works, 368, r by Plat’s The Laws, whr th yuths ar advisd t hunt in rdr t b ailiar with thir cuntry in cas it ust b dndd against nis Plat, The Laws, 192. Fr Plat, th hunt cncrns anials and huans indirntly: “w als hav t tak int accunt th hunting  n, nt rly by thir nis in war . . . but by thir lvrs, wh ‘pursu’ thir quarry r any dirnt rasns, s adirabl, s xcrabl”  The Laws, 272. 2

As Jacqus Rancièr dns it, “th distributin  th snsibl [is] th syst  slvidnt acts   sns prcptin that siultanusly disclss th x istnc  sthing in cn and th  dliitatins that dn th rspctiv parts and psitins within it”  The Politics o Aesthetics , 12. This ssay prpss t undrstand th birth  drn an, alngsid th narrativs  clnizatin, industrializatin, and tchnlgical prgrss that cnsuatd th divrc btwn huans and anials, by rviving a rgttn r rprssd rivalry that cntributd t dtrin th  drn partitin  a shard spac. 3

Fr Drrida, th war cntinus t b wagd in arnas thr than hunting grunds, such as in lan guag. Whnvr “a philsphr, r anyn ls, says ‘Th Anial’ in th singular and withut urthr ad, claiing thus t dsignat vry living thing that is 4

hld nt t b huan,” Drrida afrs, “h dclars,  just as a disas is dclard by ans  a sypt, h rs up r diagnsis th statnt ‘I a uttr ing an asinanity [bêtis].’ And this ‘I a uttring an asinanity ’ shuld cnr nt nly th aniality that h is disavwing but his cplicit, cntinud, and r ganizd invlvnt in a vritabl war  th spcis” Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 31. Th ar that tchnlgy wuld hav a ngativ inunc n th huan huntr is nt nw. In The Laws, Plat praiss hunting but ppss th captur  birds and sh with nts and traps: “Frinds, w hp yu’ll nvr b sizd by a dsir r passin t sh in th sa r t angl r indd t hunt watr anials at all; and dn’t rsrt t crls, which a lazybns will lav t catch his pry whthr h’s aslp r awak. W hp yu nvr l any tptatin t captur n n th high sas and tak t piracy, which will ak yu int brutal huntrs and utlaws. . . . Nr shuld any yung an vr b sducd by a ancy t trap birds. . . . All n wh wish t cultivat th ‘divin’ curag hav nly n typ  hunting lt, which is th bst: th captur  urtd anials with th hlp  dgs and hrss and by yur wn xrtins, whn yu hunt in prsn and subdu all yur pry by chasing and striking th and hurling wapns at th” Plat, The Laws, 273. 5

This accunts r hw th cnvrsatin culd b radically changd by Jry Bntha, r wh th qustin cncrning th anial was nt “can thy think” but, ausly, “can thy sur?” Sinc thn, th war was n lngr wagd vr th qustin  rasn but, Drrida suggsts, “vr th attr  pity.” Th last tw cnturis “hav bn ths  a struggl, a war whs inquality culd n day b rvrsd bing wagd btwn, n th n hand, ths wh vilat nt nly anial li but vn and als this sn tint  cpassin, and, n th thr hand, ths wh appal r an irrutabl tstiny t this pity” Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 28–29. 6

22

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

Jacqus Rgr rinds us that th knwldg  th anial displayd in Bun’s Histoire naturelle was that “ th huntsan” and that th philosophe Fridrich mlchir Gri “usd th articl ‘Hunt’ in th Encyclopédie t pps Bun’s psitin” Rgr, Buon, 89, 270n5.

as that  a huntr in rdr t prit a spurius idnti catin with hi.

Darwin dscribs th auna  th Galapags Archiplag as bing naturally “ta.” Th trrstrial birds  ths islands “ar tn apprachd suf cintly nar t b killd with a switch, and stis, as I ysl trid, with a cap r hat. A gun is here almost   superfuous; r with th uzzl I pushd a hawk  th branch  a tr.” Far  an is an acquird instinct, Darwin cntinus: “It wuld appar that th birds  this archiplag, nt having as yt larnt that an is a r dangrus anial than th trtis r th Ablyrhynchus, disrgard hi, in th sa an nr as in england shy birds, such as agpis, disrgard th cws and hrss grazing in ur lds” Darwin, The Voyage o the Beagle, 356; phasis in.

12

Rhds, John James Audubon, 376.

13

Ibid.

7

8

This sldnitin, as is wll knwn, rstd havily upn an iprialistic cncptin nt nly   natur but als  ths wh wr dsignatd as th “naturals.” “Audubn, th sltaught rntirsan risn t innc in eurp and at h ,” Blu xplains, “was th naturalist par excellence  th Jacksnian ra, whil at th sa ti his idalizatin  natur, and stablishnt  a privilgd vantag pint r viwing it, appald t th Whig lit   Nw england. Audubn’s cntprary culturhr cuntrparts pnd th orgn Trail and rad th bstslling ctin  Jas Fnir Cpr. Th wildrnss clbratd in ths ythaking wrks and dds was abut t b subjctd t spculatin, igratin, and cultivatin. Audubn, lik Lathr stcking, syblizd th apprpriatin r th eur pan ppulatin  th intiat knwldg  natur assciatd with th Indian” Blu, Picturing Nature, 118. Cpr’s rprsntatin  Lathrstcking can b sn as an xplary i prblatic cnatin   th Arican iprial prjct with th “natural” and “ancstral” activity  th hunt. A “whit an” raisd by th “rd n,” Lathrstcking a.k.a. Drslayr, La Lngu Carabin, Trappr, r Hawky is, as his aliass indicat, th übrhuntr. Hunting as a cultural idntity r Aricans ca abut whn it casd t b a practical, vryday activity, but als whn th iag  th Arican Indian was bing rashind 9

10

Rhds, John James Audubon, 74–75.

Stbbins, “Audubn’s Drawings  Arican Birds,” 20. 11

Th manist Dstiny that ths iags illustrat is als riniscnt  eanul Lutz’s Westward the Course o Empire Takes Its Way  1862 r Jhn Gast’s American Progress 1872, in which a sris  archtypal Arican gurs ar acing th wild and prising trritris  th Wst. During th Arican Civil War, Lutz was cissind by th Cngrss t paint this ural in th Capitl clbrat ing manist Dstiny. Gast’s painting clbrats th prgrss  civilizatin vr savagry pitizd by Nativ Aricans ing wstward and untad natur rprsntd by a hrd  bisn huntd by n n hrss. 14

15

Audubn, Writings and Drawings, 355.

16

Ibid., 355–56.

17

Ck, “Waltn Frd,” par. 2.

18

Sllins, Art 21, 124.

19

Ck, “Waltn Frd,” par. 8.

20

Fucault, The Order o Things , 16, 15.

Wl suarizs brilliantly Stanly Cavll’s analysis  th irrducibl gul sparating th knwing subjct and th phnnal wrld in Kant’s phils phy: “Cavll has plubd th cnsquncs  what it ans t d philsphy in th wak  what h calls th Kantian ‘sttlnt’ with skpticis. As h charactrizs it in In Quest o the Ordinary , ‘T sttl with skpticis . . . t assur us that w d knw th xistnc  th wrld, r rathr, that what w undrstand as knwldg is o th wrld, th pric Kant asks us t pay is t cd any clai t knw th thing in itsl, t grant huan knwldg is nt   things as thy ar in thslvs. . . . But i, n Cavll’s rading  Kant, ‘rasn prvs its pwr t itsl, vr itsl’ by lgically driving th dirnc btwn th wrld  r apparancs phnna that w 21

Huntlgy

>>

can knw and th wrld  th Ding an sich nu na, which ur knwldg nvr tuchs, thn w  nd urslvs in a psitin that is nt just dd but in act prundly unsttling, r philsphy in a undantal sns thn ails prcisly insar as it succds. W gain knwldg, but nly t ls th wrld”  Wl, Intrductin, 4–5. 22

Dastn and Galisn, Objectivity, 80.

Ibid., 79. Fr a dtaild accunt  th skpti cis and criticiss with which Audubn’s paintings wr t by th naturalist cunity  th ti, s Blu, Picturing Nature, 111–18. “Th iprving psitin  th n arts and  thir practitinrs in Arican scity and th incrasing ppularity   landscap painting nhancd Audubn’s rputatin at h. At th sa ti, th grwing distinctin btwn naturalist and illustratr in scintic practic cratd th basis r cntrvrsy vr dning his tru calling. . . . In an iprtant sns, Audubn, an and wrk, pitizd th transratin  th practic  th naturalistillustratr int th ths  th artist naturalist” 115. 23

24

Blu, Picturing Nature, 88.

25

Dastn and Galisn, Objectivity , 363.

26

Rhds, John James Audubon, 379.

I shuld ak it clar that th huanis at issu hr is n whs thrtical rts ar lcatd in th Wstrn taphysical traditin inuncd by Dscarts and r th st part by his llwrs. It is this ntthlgical taphysics that Drrida is atr in The Animal That Thereore I Am . on th sinal psitin ccupid by Dscarts in this philsphical traditin, s Fntnay, Le silence des bêtes , 275–88. 27

28

Agabn, The Open, 37.

29

Ibid., 38.

Nitzsch always dscribs an as anthr anial—that is, as an anial ang thrs, and nt as ssntially thr t anials. A larg sctin   The Genealogy o Morals is dvtd t rhistriciz ing th sparatin btwn an and anial s r instanc 70; II.8, 85; II.16, 87; II.18, and 95; II.24. In The Anti-Christ , Nitzsch playully wishs t xtnd Dscarts’s cncpt  th anialachin t th huan: “man is abslutly nt th crwn  cratin: vry cratur stands bsid hi at th sa stag 30

23

Antin Traisnl

 prctin. . . . And vn in assrting that w assrt t uch: an is, rlativly spaking, th  st unsuc cssul anial, th sicklist, th n st dangrusly strayd r its instincts—with all that, t b sur, th st interesting!—As rgards th anials, Dscarts was th rst wh, with a bldnss wrthy  rvr nc, vnturd t think  th anial as a machine: ur whl scinc  physilgy is dvtd t prving this prpsitin. Nr, lgically, d w xclud an, as vn Dscarts did: ur knwldg  an tday is ral knwldg prcisly t th xtnt that it is knwl dg  hi as a achin”  The Anti-Christ, 136. on th ipssibility  dtrining what is prpr t th huan and th plitical and scintic cnsquncs  such a liitatin, s th last chaptr  Sith, Scandalous Knowledge , “Anial Rlativs, Difcult Rlatins.” 31

32

Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 130.

33

Agabn, The Open, 79.

34

Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 89.

35

Nitzsch, Beyond Good and Evil , 74.

36

Hidggr, “Lttr n Huanis,” 225–26.

37 Hidggr, The Fundamental Concepts o  Metaphysics, 201. Hidggr hisl cnts

n th circularity  his philsphical inquiry at th bginning  The Fundamental Concepts o Metaphysics, th 1929 sinar whr h ditats at lngth n th nn plac th anial ccupis in th wrld. Whil this rcursivity tstis t Hidggr’s attpt at cing t trs with th qustin  th anial, his invstigatin is thrughly thtic in that it hlds unyildingly t th axi that th anial is “pr in wrld”  weltarm  whil an is “cnguratr  wrld”  weltbildend  . Hidggr dscribs th anial ssnc as a r  prannt “nubnss” r “captivatin”  Benommenheit  —n is tptd t say  “captur.” It ss that th anial, as it is prsntd in Hid ggr’s sinar, plays th rl  a tragic hr trappd int an inluctabl pattrn  rptitin. I d nt hav th ti hr t labrat n this, but it wuld b in trsting t lk at th xapls  th b cut in hal  that cntinus t drink, unawar that it will nvr b satiatd gur  Tantalus; th b unabl t rturn h gur  Ulysss; th th whs wings ar burnt by th lap gur  Icarus.

24

DIACRITICS

>>

2012

>>

40.2

Works Cited 38

Audubn, Writings and Drawings, 355.

39

Srrs, The Parasite, 77.

Signicantly, th scnd hal  th prvrb is “t il rvint au galp,” which suggsts that i yu try t chas natur away, it nds a way t gt back at yu, acting as s srt   revenant . It is wrth nting that natur cs back galloping, at th swit pac  th urdsticatd anial. 40

Drrida, Specters o Marx , 175; phasis in riginal. 41

42

Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 66.

Calarc,  Zoographies, 141. Calarc gs n t say that Drrida’s œuvr pavs th way r a “rla tinal and achinic ntlgy  singularitis, n that is inrd as uch by Nitzschan and Dluzan atrialis as by Hidgrrian and Lvinasian ph nnlgy. This is prhaps th st radical strain  Drrida’s thught n th qustin  th anial, and it is th clsst t th argunt dvlpd in this bk—r this lin  thught taks away th grund r aking any kind  binary huananial distinctin. I what w call ‘anial li’ is cnstitutd by a ‘htrgnus ultiplicity’  ntitis and a ‘ultiplicity  rganizatins  rlatins’ btwn rganic and inrganic li rs, thn what sns can b ad  an insuprabl divisin btwn huan and anial? D nt ‘huan bings’ blng t this ultiplicity  bings and rlatins? Ar w t bliv that huan bings ar shw xpt r th play  dirncs and rcs,  bcings and rla tins?” ibid., 142. 43

44

Drrida, Specters o Marx , 175–76.

Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am, 64. Drrida’s dra can b rad as a rspns t Nitz sch’s ar in The Twilight o the Idols that w ar nt rid  Gd bcaus w still bliv in graar. S Nitzsch, The Twilight o the Idols , 48. 45

46

Dluz, The Logic o Sense , 19–20.

47

Drrida, The Animal That Thereore I Am , 55.

Agabn, Girgi. The Open: Man and Animal. Translatd by Kvin Attll. Stanrd: Stanrd Univrsity Prss, 2002. Audubn, Jhn Jas. Writings and Drawings. Nw Yrk: Library  Arica, 1999. Bnjain, Waltr. The Arcades Project . Translatd by Hward eiland and Kvin mcLaughlin. Cabridg: Harvard Univrsity Prss, 1999. Blu, Ann Shlby. Picturing Nature: American Nineteenth-Century Zoological Illustration. Princtn: Princtn Univrsity Prss, 1993. Calarc, matthw. Zoographies: The Question o  the Animal rom Heidegger to Derrida . Nw Yrk: Clubia Univrsity Prss, 2008. Ctz, J. m. Elizabeth Costello. Nw Yrk: Viking, 2003. Ck, Grg. Rviw  art xhibitin, Waltn Frd, “Tigrs  Wrath,” Brklyn musu, Nvbr 3, 2006–January 28, 2007. The New England   Journal o Aesthetic Research blg, January 27, 2007. http://asthtic.grgckland.c/2007/01/ waltnrd_116994251314210711.htl. Darwin, Charls. The Voyage o the Beagle: Journal  o Researches into the Natural History and Geology  o the Countries Visited During the Voyage o H. M. S. Bagl Round the World . Nw Yrk: mdrn

Library, 1991. Dastn, Lrrain, and Ptr Galisn. Objectivity . Nw Yrk: Zn Bks, 2007. Dluz, Gills. The Logic o Sense. Translatd by mark Lstr. Nw Yrk: Cntinuu, 2004. Drrida, Jacqus. The Animal That Thereore I Am . Translatd by David Wills. Nw Yrk: Frdha Univrsity Prss, 2008.

Huntlgy

>>

25

Antin Traisnl

———. Specters o Marx: The State o the Debt, the Work o Mourning and the New International . Trans latd by Pggy Kau. Nw Yrk: Rutldg, 1994.

Rgr, Jacqus. Buon: A Lie in Natural History. Translatd by Sarah Lucill Bnni. Ithaca: Cr nll Univrsity Prss, 1996.

Fntnay, elisabth d. Le silence des bêtes: La  philosophie à l’épreuve de l’animalité. Paris: Fayard, 1998

Srrs, michl. The Parasite. Translatd by Lawrnc Schhr. Baltir: Jhns Hpkins Univrsity Prss, 1982.

Fucault, michl. The Order o Things. An Archaeology o the Human Sciences . Nw Yrk: Rutldg, 2007.

Sith, Barbara Hrrnstin. Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth, and the Human . Durha: Duk Univrsity Prss, 2006.

Hidggr, martin. The Fundamental Concepts o  Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. Translatd by Willia mcNill and Nichlas Walkr. Bl ingtn: Indiana Univrsity Prss, 1995.

Sllins, Susan. Art 21: Art in the Twenty-First Century   2. Nw Yrk: Harry N. Abras, 2003.

———. “Lttr n Huanis.” In Basic Writings, ditd by David Farrll Krll, 213–67. San Francisc: Harpr, 2008.

Stbbins, Thdr e., Jr. “Audubn’s Drawings   Arican Birds, 1805–38.” In John James Audubon: The Watercolors or the Birds o America, ditd by Anntt Blaugrund and Thdr e. Stbbins, Jr., 3–26. Nw Yrk: Villard, 1993.

Nitzsch, Fridrich. Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy o the Future. Translatd by R. J. Hl lingdal. Nw Yrk: Pnguin Classics, 1990.

Wl, Cary. Intrductin t Philosophy and Animal  Lie, by Stanly Cavll, Cra Diand, t al., 1–41. Nw Yrk: Clubia Univrsity Prss, 2008.

———. On the Genealogy o Morals and Ecce Homo. Translatd by Waltr Kauann and R. J. Hl lingdal. Nw Yrk: Vintag, 1989.

Xnphn. Minor Works. Translatd by J. S. Watsn. Lndn: Hnry G. Bhn, 1857.

———. Twilight o the Idols and The Anti-Christ . Trans latd by R. J. Hllingdal. Nw Yrk: Pnguin, 1990. Plat. The Laws. Translatd by Trvr J. Saundrs. Nw Yrk: Pnguin, 2004. ———. Phaedo. Translatd by eva Brann, Ptr Kalkav ag, and eric Sal. Nwburyprt, mA: Fcus Publishing, 1998. Rancièr, Jacqus. The Politics o Aesthetics . Translatd by Gabril Rckhill. Nw Yrk: Cn tinuu, 2006. Rhds, Richard. John James Audubon: The Making o  an American. Nw Yrk: Knp, 2004.

View more...

Comments

Copyright ©2017 KUPDF Inc.
SUPPORT KUPDF