Deep Ecology Essay

April 28, 2018 | Author: davywalsh6317 | Category: Environmental Ethics, Ecology, Epistemology, Truth, Metaphysics
Share Embed Donate


Short Description

I wrote this as a student; as such I had, and still do have, a lot to learn..... Please reference it, if you use it. Mor...

Description

1 A critique of deep ecology

The ‘deep ecology movement’ has been around now for three decades. Since its creation by Arne Naess in Norway in the early seventies the deep ecology movement has become widespread in all parts of the globe. The movement was made very  popular when Naess and George Sessions put together together an eight step platform outlining the principle beliefs of the supporters of this movement. As the movement took off, and deep ecology, as it were, became a household name, various philosophers started to develop their own theories which focused more on the question of man’s obligation or moral duty to nature. Philosophers like Singer, Regan, Rolsten III and Taylor were all trying to develop an environmental ethic which could be applied to this modern age. Whilst these theories were being developed the deep ecology movement was still in the background, becoming more sociably recognised as the years went by.

Around the late 80s early 90s deep ecologists found themselves defending deep ecology in the form of academic papers and in recognised Environmental Ethics Journals. It was at this point, and it is clear from early deep ecology papers, that a social movement had just met a philosophical debate. Since then, deep ecologists like Katz, Rothnberg, Light, Fox, Clark, Sylvan have all tried to develop the philosophical roots of deep ecology.

This essay addresses the philosophy of deep ecology as opposed to the deep ecology movement. There is a six point summary of the philosophy of deep ecology included in the appendix at the end of this essay, as opposed to the popular eight step platform which was devised for the social movement of deep ecology.

The purpose of this paper is to firstly give a detailed description of deep ecology and secondly to argue that deep ecology as a philosophical movement isn’t as successful as the deep ecologies social movement. My aim is to offer a fair and non-biased critique. The paper is broken into four sections entitled: Arne Naess, Self-realisation, Biocentricism and finally a conclusion.

Arne Naess

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

2

A deep ecology essay which does not mention Arne Naess is comparable to a  phenomenology essay which doesn’t mention Husserl. Arne Naess’ work introduced the themes the deep ecology for the first time. However to get a sense of where these themes came from I will give a brief picture of Arne Naess life, followed by two sections which analyse two key terms in deep ecology, which are Self-realisation and  biocentric equality.

Arne Naess was born in Olso, in 1912. As he was growing up he became an avid mountaineer. In fact it was mountaineering, along with his philosophical training, which encouraged him to develop an eco philosophy. In Ecology, community and  lifestyle, Arne reflects upon the week spent in a cold bleak mountain hut at the age of  15:

The effect of this week established my conviction of an inner relation  between mountain and mountain people, a certain greatness, cleanness, a concentration upon what is essential, a self-sufficiency; and consequently a disregard of luxury, of complicated mean of all kinds.

1

Later in his life, Arne built a simple cabin at a place called  Tvergastein. The term ‘Deep Ecology’ was coined by Arne Naess in 1972 and it was in this simple cabin that most of Arne’s work on ‘Deep Ecology’ was put together.2 Stephan Harding, a colleague of Arne’s, who teaches Gaia theory and deep ecology, claims that since becoming the youngest-ever professor of philosophy at the University of Oslo, whilst still in his twenties, Arne Naess revealed his brilliance by studying and writing extensively in many fields, including semantics, philosophy of  science, and the works of Spinoza and Gandhi. But he is much more 1

Arne Naess/ David Rothenberg, Ecology, Community and lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy , Cambridge University Press, 1990. p3 2 The famous 20th century philosopher Martin Heidegger also sought refuse for longs periods of time in a log cabin in the Black Forest. Whilst Heidegger is known for his phenomenological existentialism, his later works have a strong environmental theme, often coupled with kind poetic undertones. Cf. The Princple of Reason, Indiana Uni Press. 2001.

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

3

than an academic. His approach to ecology bears the stamp of his life's experience as a philosopher in the truest sense; as a lover of  wisdom, and as a lover of mountains.3 In 1969, Naess resigned as Professor of Philosophy after thirty years of work. The threat of an eco-catastrophe had become too obvious. Naess believes philosophy could chart the way out of the chaos, a philosophical praxis was needed; action without this underlying wisdom is useless. This is a fundamental belief in Arne’s philosophy. So what of Arne’s philosophy, what exactly are the beliefs which underlie Arne’s deep ecology? The concept of Self-realisation in Naess’ work forms the backbone of Naess’ deep ecology. Nearly all the aspects of deep ecology refer back to this concept, though some aspects carry a right of their own. It is a concept which some feel has very little philosophical grounding. In this section of the paper I would like to expound the concept of Self-realisation in Naess’ work, once I have established the principles of such a concept I will introduce various criticisms which I believe are valid and deserve a mention.

Self-realisation

 Naess explains that we are not outside the rest of nature and therefore cannot do with it, as we please, without changing ourselves. Naess claims we should take the view that humans are not the centre of the world; they are in fact only part of nature like any other life form. We are in a constant relationship, even if we do not know it, with other life forms, i.e. plants, birds etc. When one realises this constant relationship with nature we feel a strong sense of identification with nature. This process of  identification with nature is referred to as Self-realisation. During this transcendental relationship the self is no longer limited by the ego, it expands; we develop a wide identification with nature. Naess calls this expanded self the ecological self. We 3

WWW site: Stephan Harding, Deep Ecology http://resurgence.gn.apc.org/185/Harding185.htm

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

4  become aware of how reliant we are on other forms of life. This increased sense of  reliance brings empathy and concern for non-human life. As a result there is a natural inclination to protect all life.

The process of identification is a very important stage to Self-realisation. For  example, you have identification with your mother, father and siblings, in the sense that you feel a duty toward them. This identification can extend wider than your  family; it can extend to your friends, your neighbours and your country. Naess would say it can extend to the whole of humanity and it doesn’t stop there either. You can identify yourself with pets, with other animals, with plants and other natural elements. Through identification with others you find Self-realisation. The process of  identifying with plants and animals may seem alien to some but when we take a deeper look into Naess beliefs we see that identification is inherent to all life on this earth.

The identity of the individual, ‘that I am something’, is developed through interaction with a broad manifold, organic and inorganic. There is no completely isolatable I, no isolatable social unit.4

To distance yourself from the interaction with broad manifolds of organic and inorganic things is to distance yourself from the part of you which the ‘I’ is built upon. Your sense of self is shaped upon factors like family, home and surroundings. The more factors we can identify with the better. Naess claims that once Selfrealisation has occurred it is the rain forest in you that is dying. At this point it is clear  that what Naess is describing is not an environmental ethic rather it is an ontological  philosophy. Once self realisation occurs ethics seems absurd, for disrespecting anything would be a degradation of our self.

Self-realisation for Arne Naess is deeply rooted (excuse the pun) in emotion and intuition. He is undoubtedly describing a feeling which he himself felt or does feel from time to time. W.H. Murray wrote of feelings akin to Naess’ transcendental relationship after completing a first ascent of Tower Ridge on Ben Nevis in winter: 4

Arne Naess/ David Rothenberg, Ecology, Community and lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy , Cambridge University Press, 1990. p164

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

5

In the quiet I felt something of the limitation of personality fall away as desires were stilled; and as I died to self and became more absorbed in the hills and sky, the more their beauty entered into me; until they seemed one with me and I with them. Later, while we walked slowly across the plateau, it became very clear to me that only the true self, which transcends the  personal, lays claim to immortality.5

I cannot, and do not wish to convey any doubt to the sincerity of these feelings. However, I believe as Murray goes on to say, that all the above feelings are grounded in the spiritual side of man, not the philosophical. Naess, on the other  hand believes that spiritual, philosophical and religious beliefs are all relevant in determining an environmental ethic. Naess’ esoteric theory of Self-realisation has  been built a variety of academic disciplines that are quite distinct, however in  Naess’ work they are in union, which runs contrary to the traditions of  Continental Philosophy. 6

 Naess’ philosophy may be questionable if Self-realisation is entirely grounded on spiritual beliefs more so then philosophical beliefs, however I would like to address this issue later and see if this is a valid reason for casting deep ecology aside simply due to its lack of analytical methodology, for now though, I would like to introduce another fundamental belief of deep ecology.

Biocentricism

It seems fair to say that if an environmental theory supports biocentricism, it can be classed as a deep ecology of sorts7. Paul Taylor adheres to a biocentric outlook on nature and his four main components of this outlook sum up nicely what it means to 5

Murray, W.H. Mountaineering in Scotland, Baton Wicks Publications, 1997. p138 Recent works by Merleau-Ponty and Martin Heidegger actually encompass the embodied existence of  nature. 7 The definition used for deep ecology is taken from Naess’ seminal article ‘The Shallow and the Deep  Long-Range Ecological Movement’  in which he sets out the difference between deep and shallow ecology. 6

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

6 have a biocentric view point. Taylor’s four components are as follows: 1) Humans are thought of as members of the earth’s community of life, holding that membership on the same terms as apply to all the nonhuman members. 2) The earth’s natural ecosystems as a totality are seen as a complex web of interconnected elements, each  being dependent on the functioning of the other. 3) Each individual organism is conceived as a teleological centre of life, pursuing its own good in its own way. 4) The claim that humans by their very nature are superior to other species is a groundless claim and must be rejected.8 Taylor’s four components remain the same as  Naess’ and Sessions’ components for their biocentricism. However, it seems that  Naess and Sessions have emphasised biocentric equality more so than Taylor. Naess’ and Sessions’ deep ecology includes all organic matter which reside in the ecosphere. In Naess’ deep ecology a rock and a bird should be viewed as equal.

I would like to take a moment to examine this point of view and see if it is logically  possible to include non-living organic matter into the realm of biocentricism. This is a notable point as Taylor has been criticised in the past for his preference of a Protozoa (most basic of living entities) over a stalactite.9 Naess believes that a stalactite is of  the same worth as a protozoon. As a speleologist I must agree on some level with  Naess. There is a part of me which is willing to respect a stalactite for a multitude of  reasons; it is older than human existence, therefore existing before we did. It is a  beautiful natural object, it grows at an atomic rate, which I find admirable in this fast age of ours, its teleological end is perhaps to become a pillar, a straw or perhaps a curtain.10 The idea of a cave brings up another important point, which I feel is worth  pondering. Chemosynthesis was discovered in Moldeva Cave in Romania about a decade ago, this proved beyond reasonable doubt that life can exist without the sun  providing energy in the form of photosynthesis. In these caves Spiders and insects had managed to evolve entirely from bacteria to insect without light. The process is entirely chemical, evolution has occurred through chemical reactions which have a similarity to any other form of chemical reaction. If what we consider common living organisms, i.e. tree, as having a right to grow then there is little reason why a stalactite doesn’t. In the process of trying to logically prove that a stalactite should be viewed in 8

Pojman, P. Louis, Environmental Ethics, Reading in theory and application , Wadsworth Pub. Co, 1998. p 206 9 Brennan, Andrew, The Ethics of the Environment , Dartmouth Pub. Co Ltd. 1995. p31 10 Piller, Straw, Curtain are all names of speleothems. (cave formations made of calcite.)

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

7 the same light as a living organism I will need to refer to chemistry. The making of a stalactite is a complex process, and one which relies on a variety of conditions before it happens. One condition is the stalactite itself is in an environment which encourages growth, a bit like a plant being placed on the window sill to allow light at it. The cave, like the sun, provides energy for the stalactite to evolve through chemical processes. When rainwater percolates through the soil it picks up C02 from the organic material in the soil. The chemical process [Ca(2+) + 2HCO3(-) + H20 + CO2 ===> CAVE] shows how the acidic water eats away at the limestone and creates an environment which allows growth of the stalactite. From a scientific view point the above chemical  process is no more intricate then that of photosynthesis [6C02+6H20-SUNLIGHTC6H1206+6O2]. If allow science is to contribute to our argument, and I see no reason why we shouldn’t, then a stalactite may have more of an autotelic right than most would have thought. Arne Naess allows, but more so almost relies on this type of  scientific logic to get his point of view across. He often uses it in a matter-of-fact kind of way. In this sense the ‘Deep’ in the term Deep Ecology, has to be seen as the  philosophical ground, where as ‘Ecology’ is scientific in every aspect.

However, it is one thing to include organic matter; it is another to call it equal. Naess couldn’t be vaguer in regard to his philosophy of equality and rights. ‘Equality’ as  Naess suggests is a sort of quantification that is misleading. From the point of view of  analytical philosophy the term ‘right’ like many other terms in daily life is rather  suspicious. Does it have a meaning that can be clarified? According to Naess it does not, though he uses it in the sense that it provides the best expression of an intuition which he is unable to reject in all seriousness.11

This argument of equal intrinsic worth is a common debate among eco-philosophers, and one which has as much strength as it has weaknesses. Nevertheless, Arne Naess’ theories in this regard seem a bit weaker than most. George Sessions writes that Naess suggests that biocentric equality as an intuition is true ‘in principle’, although in the  process of living, all species use each other as food, shelter, etc.12

11

Arne Naess/ David Rothenberg, Ecology, Community and lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy , Cambridge University Press, 1990. p167 12 Sessions/ Devall, Deep Ecology, Living as if nature mattered . Gibbs Smith Pub. 1985, p67

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

8 Besides the ‘intuition principle’ Naess does offer a view that a living entity has an autotelic right to live. This view is similar to Paul Taylor’s view in regard to all individual organisms are teleological centres of life.13 In fact it was Aristotle who was the first to recognise living entities had a ‘good’ in their own right, an intrinsic value as it were. This line of argument is very common in environmental philosophy, and one which raises a lot of debate. I believe John O Neill’s article entitled ‘The varieties of intrinsic value’ goes a long way in clearing up the debate on intrinsic value. O  Neill’s thesis shows that while it is the case that natural entities have intrinsic value in the strongest sense of the term, such value does not entail any obligations on the part of human beings. 14

To continue this debate over biocentric equality seems fruitless in one regard. There is no doubt that this sort of debate can only help strengthen certain positions and offer  some clarity, but for deep ecologists like Naess, Sessions, Devall and Fox environmental axiology (i.e., environmental value theory) is of little importance. The majority of other eco-philosophers are primarily concerned with developing arguments to establish the fact that nonhuman entities — or certain kinds of  nonhuman entities — are intrinsically valuable (i.e., valuable in and of themselves, independently of their use value to humans). Indeed, this approach is so central in environmental ethics that many environmental philosophers persist in thinking that this is also the chief worry of deep ecologists. However, deep ecologists are not  primarily concerned with environmental axiology. Rather, deep ecologists are  primarily concerned with advocating the realisation of a certain state of being, specifically, a worldly realisation which manifests as the most expansive sense of self  as possible.15 Arguments for intrinsic value imply definite codes of conduct. In contrast, deep ecologists openly decline any move towards moral ought and seek  instead to invite and inspire certain states of being. Naess remarks “I’m not so much interested in ethics or morals. I’m interested in how we experience the world.”

16

I will

come back to this point in the conclusion, but let’s move on to some other criticisms which seem popular in the deep ecology debate. 13

Taylor, Paul, Respect for nature , Princeton University Press, 1986. Brennan, Andrew, The Ethics of the Environment , Dartmouth Pub. Co Ltd. 1995. p55 15 Trumpeter (1990) ISSN: 0832-6193 The Meanings of "Deep Ecology" Warwick Fox University of Tasmania. http://trumpeter.athabascau.ca/context/v7.1/fox.html (21-11-03) 16 Arne Naess/ David Rothenberg, Ecology, Community and lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy , Cambridge University Press, 1990. p20 14

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

9 I would like to discuss a view held by opponents of deep ecology which Fox calls the ‘anthropocentric fallacy’ that claim a human based environmental ethic must be anthropocentric in some shape or form. In keeping with this fallacy J .B. Callicott

holds the view that there can be no value apart from an evaluator...all value is as it were is in the eye of the beholder. The value that is attributed to the ecosystem, therefore, is humanly dependent or at least dependent upon some variety of morally and aesthetically sensitive consciousness.17 This statement implies that any environmentally sensitive ethic must be in principle anthropocentric. An easier way to say it is that any ethics conceived by a human must be anthropocentric. If this is the logic we’re going to adhere to then it seems that any values conceived by a Jew must be Jewish values. Any values conceived by a homosexual must be homosexual in nature. If we look at the argument from a hermeneutical stand point, which I believe a lot of this debate boils down to, we have to ask whether we can interpret something objectively. If we can interpret something from a non-subjective standpoint, ergo objectively, surely this is a ground for a biocentric viewpoint to be accepted. Gadamer’s hermeneutical theories set forth in Truth and Method claim that we are all connected through historical situatedness. Every time we interpret something we do so through the filter of the tradition we belong to. Using Gadamer’s hermeneutics when an Indian sees a bird flying south, it is his culture’s belief which allows him to understand the true significance of the situation. If the Indian’s cultural beliefs are holistic and biocentric than the Indian’s viewpoint is both holistic and biocentric.  Today’s modern society is not generally biocentric, though once you adhere to that indigenous tradition it may be possible, to understand through a biocentric viewpoint.

17

Dale T. Snauwaert, The Relevance of the Anthropocentric-Ecocentric Debate, Adelphi University www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES-yearbook/96_docs/snauwaert.html (22-10-03)

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

10

 The last point I wish to address is the anti-human notion which some people feel is inherent in deep ecology. Thanks to the remarks of  self proclaimed deep ecologist David Foreman, deep ecologists around the globe are now being painted with the same brush. I refer to remarks made in Simply Living, an Australian periodical where Foreman stated: When I tell people how the worst thing we could do in Ethiopia is to give aid – the best thing would be to just let nature seek its own balance, to let people there just starve – they think this is monstrous.18 It clear that Foreman will never win an award for his contribution to humanitarianism in times of need, yet the point which is unclear to some is that Foreman’s comments are not shared by Naess’ deep ecology. In Ecology, community and lifestyle there is a section entitled ‘The uniqueness of human kind should not be underestimated’ and in this particular section Naess addresses the misconception that humans should never have priority over non-human needs. Naess once again reiterates one of his environmental norms which states ‘You shall not inflict unnecessary suffering upon other living beings!’ It is clear that Foreman, a deep ecologist, has perhaps misunderstood what Naess is saying. For anyone who feels that deep ecology is antihuman please read the literature, you will be told otherwise. Conclusion  There were two points which I left unaddressed in the preceding sections which I wish to address now. The first was whether deep ecology should be cast aside due to its spiritual nature and the second was the fact that deep ecologists are not concerned with moral ought and obligation. I will address both these points 18

Pojman, P. Louis, Environmental Ethics, Reading in theory and application , Wadsworth Pub. Co, 1998. p156

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

11

simultaneously, as they both shape my overall opinion of deep ecology and help me to come to a conclusion in regard to the nature and essence of deep ecology. The main problem with commenting on deep ecology is trying to distinguish the philosophy from the movement. This process is difficult and due to the nature, and strength of the movement I believe it will be quite some time before there exists a solid break in each. Deep ecology like many great philosophical works was inspired by feelings and intuition. Is it not the case that most philosophies were shaped at the start by a feeling, intuition of some sort? Some times, as is in the case of great philosophically regarded work, feelings and emotions coincide with reality, and the insight gained through these feelings can led to solid philosophical work. I, however, believe that Naess has not accomplished this feat, yet.19 According to Naess the fundamentals of deep ecology, if verbalized are Buddhist, Taoist, Christian or of other religious persuasions, or philosophic with affinities to the basic view of Spinoza, Whitehead, Heidegger and others. The basic principles of the deep ecology movement are grounded in religion or philosophy.20 However as we have already stated Naess claims that ethics do not concern him, his philosophy as well as the movement are more concerned with the way we experience the world.  There are a few things that one notices about Naess after reading a lot of his work. Firstly, though philosophy is mentioned in his work, it is clear that what Naess is not in anyway relying on philosophy to ground his basic beliefs. Secondly, Naess usually refers to the deep 19

Some of Naess’ unpublished work show a form of holistic phenomenology. A phenomenology which allows much more then a cognitive processes to guide it. Naess has never given up the idea of creating a more solid grounded philosophy which ideally would be comparable to mainstream contemporary  philosophy. Katz, Light, Rothenberg, Beneath the Surface, Critical Essays in the Philosophy of Deep  Ecology. The MIT Press, 2000. p151-p167 20 Sessions/ Devall, Deep Ecology, Living as if nature mattered . Gibbs Smith Pub. 1985. p225

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

12

ecology as a movement, never as a philosophy. Thirdly, Naess uses a philosophical method which Spinoza used in his Ethics, this is only to try to define and clarify underlying premises which Naess has. In general, Spinoza’s geometric proofs are designed so that if we accept the definitions and axioms at the outset, and deductions from these are properly made, then we must accept the concluded propositions. In practice as Naess shows, Spinoza’s method is difficult to say the least. Why did Naess use such a rigorous and difficult method? I think Naess uses it because he really believed Spinoza to be correct in his formulation, that is, if the original premise is true then all deduction made from the first premise should also hold true. I believe it was the rigor of such a method which inspired Naess, though it was also this rigor which I believe, proved too much for him. It is from most other commentators of environmental ethics, and possible from Naess earlier writing that his theory lacks philosophical conviction. The question is whether it should have a place in environmental ethics at all, considering the fact that it is not an ethical theory. Some people like Bookchin claim it shouldn’t be allowed to make its way into our ethical discussions, other like Fox believe it should. I for one take Fox’s stance on this view. After reading various amount of environmental ethics literature I conclude that there are many ethical theories which lack ethics just as much as deep ecology, if not more. Writers like J.B. Callicot, A. Leopold, M. Bookchin, J. Lovelock all have wonderful theories but they too lack ethical credibility. Paul Taylor’s clinically written Respect for Nature provided us with a strong environmental ethic, yet an ethic which can, like all the rest, be argued with. I believe deep ecology has a right to stay in our conversations and books as much as other theories in regard to environmental ethics. Arne Naess’ deep ecology was always intended to be a social movement, this social movement was ground in somewhat weak

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

13

philosophy, yet the movement did bring about an ecological awareness, one of its fundamental goals. It has influenced and instilled philosophers around the globe to develop the theories of  deep ecology or perhaps to develop better and different theories of  environmental ethics. Arne Naess’ overriding ambition was to instill an ecological awareness in people which made them conscious of  what they could do to help right the environmental wrongs of  modern society. If environmentalists manage to right these wrongs using deep ecology or any other form of eco-philosophy, Arne Naess’ work will not have been in vain. As for the philosophy of deep ecology I believe it will become stronger and stronger, and hopefully someday it will become applicable enough that an ethics may be formed from it.

Appendix Six points of the Deep Ecology philosophy. What is the essential content of the philosophy of deep ecology? Eric Katz, David Rothenberg and Andrew Light have developed these six points which offer some philosophical content to deep ecology: 1.  The rejection of strong anthropocentricism. 2.  The consideration of ecocentricism as a replacement for anthropocentricism. (Ecocentricism and biocentricism are often used interchangeably.) 3. Identification with all life forms. 4.  The sense that caring for the environment is part of individual human realisation.

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

14

5. A critique of instrumental rationality. (The mode of thinking which makes efficiency and quantifiable results the goal of all human activity.) 6. Personal development of a total world view. (Six points were taken from Katz et al, Beneath the Surface, The MIT Press, 2000)

Bibliography:



Arne Naess/ David Rothenberg, Ecology, Community and lifestyle: Outline of  an Ecosophy, Cambridge University Press, 1990.



Blackstone, T. William, Philosophy & Environmental Crisis, University of  Georgia Press, 1974.



Brennan, Andrew, The Ethics of the Environment , Dartmouth Pub. Co Ltd. 1995.

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

15



Dale T. Snauwaert, The Relevance of the Anthropocentric-Ecocentric Debate,  Adelphi University www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PESyearbook/96_docs/snauwaert.html (22-10-03)



Honderich, Ted. The Oxford companion to philosophy. Oxford University Press, 1995



Murray, W.H. Mountaineering in Scotland, Baton Wicks Publications, 1997.



Pojman, P. Louis, Environmental Ethics, Reading in theory and application, Wadsworth Pub. Co, 1998.



Scherer, Attig, Ethics and the Environment , Prentice-Hall, 1983.



Sessions/ Devall, Deep Ecology, Living as if nature mattered . Gibbs Smith Pub. 1985, p6 Some of Katz, Light, Rothenberg,  Beneath the Surface, Critical   Essays in the Philosophy of Deep Ecology. The MIT Press, 2000.



Sessions/ Devall, Deep Ecology, Living as if nature mattered . Gibbs Smith Pub. 1985 .



Taylor, Paul, Respect for nature, Princeton University Press, 1986.



Trumpeter (1990) ISSN: 0832-6193 The Meanings of "Deep Ecology" Warwick Fox University of Tasmania. http://trumpeter.athabascau.ca/context/v7.1/fox.html (21-11-03)



WWW site: Stephan Harding, Deep Ecology http://resurgence.gn.apc.org/185/Harding185.htm

Davy Walsh

Environmental Ethics

View more...

Comments

Copyright ©2017 KUPDF Inc.
SUPPORT KUPDF