Chiaradonna Universals Commentators-libre
April 8, 2017 | Author: GiancarloBellina | Category: N/A
Short Description
Chiaradonna_Universals_Commentators-libre.pdf...
Description
33 SEMINARI E CONVEGNI
Universals in Ancient Philosophy edited by Riccardo Chiaradonna Gabriele Galluzzo
© 2013 Scuola Normale Superiore Pisa isbn 978-88-7642-484-7
Table of contents
Introduction Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo
1
Universals before Universals: Some Remarks on Plato in His Context Mauro Bonazzi
23
Plato’s Conception of the Forms: Some Remarks Francesco Ademollo
41
Plato’s Five Worlds Hypothesis (Ti. 55cd), Mathematics and Universals Marwan Rashed
87
Plato and the One-over-Many Principle David Sedley
113
Universals, Particulars and Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Forms Laura M. Castelli 139 Universals in Aristotle’s Logical Works Mauro Mariani
185
Universals in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Gabriele Galluzzo
209
Epicureans and Stoics on Universals Ada Bronowski
255
Alexander, Boethus and the Other Peripatetics: The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators Riccardo Chiaradonna
299
One of a Kind: Plotinus and Porphyry on Unique Instantiation Peter Adamson
329
Universals, Education, and Philosophical Methodology in Later Neoplatonism Michael Griffin
353
Universals in Ancient Medicine Riccardo Chiaradonna
381
Universals in the Greek Church Fathers Johannes Zachhuber
425
Bibliography
471
Index locorum
509
Index of names
537
Alexander, Boethus and the Other Peripatetics: The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
1. Dexippus, Simplicius and Peripatetic universals his is how one must answer the arguments of the associates of Alexander and Boethus and the other Peripatetics [τοῖς περὶ Ἀλέξανδρον καὶ Βόηθον τοῖς τε ἄλλοις Περιπατητικοῖς ἐπιχειροῦσιν] and it is appropriate for those interpreting the Metaphysics to show that Aristotle gives priority to common items (τὰ κοινά) even when considering sensible things (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 27-31 Busse)1.
hese lines from Dexippus provide signiicant evidence about the theory of universals developed in the Aristotelian commentary tradition. he passage quoted above has a parallel in Simplicius (Simpl., In Cat., 82, 22 f. Kalbleisch), who also mentions the common source that lies behind both his report and that of Dexippus, i.e. Iamblichus’ lost Commentary on the Categories (Simpl., In Cat., 82, 10 and 83, 21 Kalbleisch). Unlike what happens elsewhere, however, here Dexippus provides a crucial detail which is missing in Simplicius. Whereas Simplicius only names Alexander of Aphrodisias, Dexippus provides a fuller list of Peripatetic opponents which includes Boethus, Alexander and the other Peripatetics2. hus, Dexippus makes an overt connection between Boethus of Sidon (irst century BCE) and Alexander of Aphrodisias (second-third century CE), the two main Aristotelian
1
English translations are generally adapted from those published in the series «he Ancient Commentators on Aristotle». See, in particular, de Haas, Fleet 2001; Chase 2003 (for Simplicius’ Commentary on the Categories); Dillon 1990 (for Dexippus). I have also made use of the translations in Sharples 2010, pp. 75-89 (Ontology). 2 It is unclear to me whether in mentioning Boethus Dexippus was drawing from Iamblichus or whether he added the name of Boethus to those found in his source. Dexippus does not usually name his predecessors: this may speak in support of the irst hypothesis. On Dexippus, see now the excellent discussion in Barnes 2009.
300 Riccardo Chiaradonna
commentators in the post-Hellenistic age. Some recent studies have convincingly shown that Boethus and Alexander developed two diferent and alternative Peripatetic readings of Aristotle, which mirror two stages in the history of the reception of Aristotle’s school treatises3. In this contribution I aim to develop this point and show that Dexippus’ criticism sets out Boethus’ and Alexander’s positions misleadingly, since Dexippus (or his source Iamblichus) conlates the theories of his opponents without considering their mutual diferences within a common Peripatetic philosophical background4. It is worth quoting Dexippus’ passage in full: SELEUCUS But what could we say to those who dispute this very point, claiming that in fact universals are not prior in nature to particulars, but posterior to them? DEXIPPUS Well, if we were to consider the question carefully, we would ind that they actually take as agreed what is disputed. For when they say that the universals are prior in nature to each thing taken individually, but on the other hand absolutely5 posterior in nature, they are postulating that particulars are prior also by nature6, and are proceeding invalidly in taking as a irst principle that very thing that requires demonstration. Such attempts at proofs [ἐπιχειρήματα] as the following are also supericial: if the common item exists, it is necessary that an individual exists also (for individuals are comprehended in common items), but if an individual exists, it does not always follow that a common item exists, if at least a common item belongs to many (instances). For it is obvious that a particular can be an individual only 3
See, irst and foremost, the illuminating discussion in Rashed 2007. Also, see Chiaradonna, Rashed 2010 and the discussion of Rashed’s volume by Kupreeva 2010. 4 Signiicantly, Dexippus’ simplifying account was shared by such an eminent scholar as Paul Moraux. See Moraux 1973, p. 156: «Für Boethos und Alexander […] ist das Gemeinsame nichts anderes als ein Produkt der abstrahierenden Fähigkeit des Geistes, das aus den enzig un allein in der Wirklichkeit vorhandenen Einzeldingen gewonnen wird; es besitzt nichts von der Selbständigkeit und von der Priorität der platonischen ideellen Wesenheiten» (my italics). Recent scholarship on Alexander has changed this picture radically. 5 At 45, 17 Busse Dillon reads πάντων instead of πάντως (MSS), but this seems unnecessary to me. 6 καὶ τῇ φύσει (45, 17-18 Busse) and not only «with respect to us» (πρὸς ἡμᾶς) as Dexippus too recognises (see 45, 6 Busse).
301 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
if a common item is immanent in it and completes its essence, for a particular human being is also Human Being. And it is also false to say that, when the common item is removed, the individual is not altogether removed; for if the being of the common item consists in extending to all the things ranked under it, the person who removes this immediately removes the whole existence of the individual7, his is how one must answer the arguments of the associates of Alexander and Boethus and the other Peripatetics and it is appropriate for those interpreting the Metaphysics to show that Aristotle gives priority to the common items [τὰ κοινά] even when considering sensible things (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 12-31 Busse)8.
According to Dexippus, the Peripatetics hold that universals or common items are posterior in nature to particulars, because they are posterior to the extension of the particulars under them. Dexippus (see Simpl., In Cat., 82, 22-26 Kalbleisch) replies that his opponents simply take it for granted that particulars are prior in nature, but do not provide any demonstration of this fact. Simplicius’ parallel discussion gives further details, since he remarks that Alexander of Aphrodisias claims – without any proof – that common items (τὰ κοινά) derive «their being and their essence» (τὸ εἶναι καὶ τὴν οὐσίαν) from particulars (παρὰ τῶν καθ’ ἕκαστα, Simpl., In Cat., 82, 24-25 Kalbleisch). Some lines above, Simplicius sets out this thesis as distinctively Peripatetic (82, 7-8 Kalbleisch): koina do not exist at all independently, but have their being in particulars (τὰ κοινὰ οὐδέ ἐστιν ὅλως καθ’ ἑαυτὰ ἐν ὑποστάσει, ἀλλ’ ἐν τοῖς ἀτόμοις ἔχει τὸ εἶναι). he Peripatetic view rejected by Dexippus and Simplicius is not easy to assess. As a matter of fact, the claim that universals do not exist by themselves, independently of particulars, but are in particulars and depend on them for their existence is an ambiguous statement that can be interpreted in two diferent ways. (a) Universals do not possess any kind of existence distinct from that of particulars: they are in particulars since nothing exists but particular entities; (b) universals are entities distinct from particulars, although they are not independent of particulars and could not exist without particulars. he reading (a) 7
At 45, 27 Busse I read τοῦ ἀτόμου instead of τοῦ κοινοῦ (MSS). As I see it, the parallel with Simpl., In Cat., 82, 34-35 Kalbleisch is decisive. For discussion, see Dillon 1990, p. 83 note 34 (who, however, retains τοῦ κοινοῦ). 8 καὶ ἐν τῇ τῶν αἰσθητῶν θεωρίᾳ: on Dexippus’ καὶ at 45, 30 Busse, see the last section of this article.
302 Riccardo Chiaradonna
of the Peripatetic thesis is equivalent to an extensional position which would lead us to equate universals with mere collections of particulars. he reading (b) is instead equivalent to a moderate kind of realism according to which universals are entities that can be determined in themselves and are not identical to collections of particulars; however, these entities only exist insofar as there is some particular that instantiates them. According to (a), deinitions ultimately refer to the particulars that belong to the extension of a certain predicate. According to (b), deinitions refer to a feature proper to each particular; such a feature satisies the intension of the deinitional account and is an entity in some sense of the word9. As I aim to show, the view (a) is that held by Boethus, whereas the view (b) is that held by Alexander. Furthermore, both (a) and (b) are diferent from (c), Iamblichus’ strong realism about universals, according to which universals are universalia ante rem, i.e. self-subsistent paradigmatic entities that are prior, metaphysically separate and independent with respect to particulars. At the level of the sensible world Iamblichus and his followers posit immanent common entities (universalia in re), which are lower than the universalia ante rem and partake in them, but are nevertheless prior to particulars. Ater outlining the Peripatetic view on the priority of particulars, both Dexippus and Simplicius focus on the arguments (ἐπιχειρήματα, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 19 Busse; ἀποδείξεις, Simpl., In Cat., 82, 26 Kalbleisch) developed by the Peripatetics in support of their theory. Dexippus and Simplicius (who follow their common source Iamblichus) discard these arguments as unsatisfying (ἐπιπόλαια, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 19 Busse; σαθραί, Simpl., In Cat., 82, 26 Kalbleisch). he two arguments rejected by Dexippus and Simplicius can be seen as complementary parts of the same demonstration, since they adopt two canonical rules of natural priority that were taken to be equivalent by the commentators: (1) Fs are prior to Gs if and only if F co-removes but is not co-removed by G; (2) Fs are prior to Gs if and only if F is co-introduced by but does not co-introduce G10. 9
For the distinction between the extensional and the intensional reading, see Rashed 2007, p. 168 and passim. Also, see Kupreeva 2010, p. 225. 10 On the rules of natural priority, see Barnes 2003, pp. 248-53.
303 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
he Peripatetics apply both rules to the relation between particulars and universals, since (2) individuals are co-introduced by but do not co-introduce universals and (1) individuals co-remove but are not coremoved by universals. Interestingly, however, these rules of priority are compatible with both the reading (a) and the reading (b) outlined above. According to (a), i.e. the extensional reading of the Peripatetic position, individuals are co-introduced by universals since universals are nothing but collections of particulars: thus, given a certain collection, the particulars that belong to this collection are also given. Furthermore, particulars co-remove universals, since when all particulars are removed, their collection is also removed. he opposite does not hold: one could well consider a species, for instance, with a unique particular member (e.g. the sun and the moon, according to the examples given in Arist., Met. Ζ 15)11. In such cases, the unique member of the species exists but does not belong to any universal collection: hence the individual does not co-introduce the universal and the universal does not co-remove the particular. One may indeed remark that the collection composed by one single individual is still an entity diferent from the single individual member that belongs to it. To the best of my knowledge, however, the ancient commentators do not develop any argument of this kind. Furthermore, the collection with one single member would still not be ‘universal’ in the sense of ‘being composed by several members’12. he two rules of priority are also compatible with reading (b), i.e. the ‘intensional’ reading of the Peripatetic position. In this case, individuals are co-introduced by universals, since universals are deinable entities that exist only insofar as they are instantiated by some individual. When all individuals are removed, the universal deinable nature is also removed. he opposite does not hold, as is shown again by the example of a species with one single particular instantiation. he situation, however, is more complicated here. In fact, one could well consider a deinable entity corresponding to the sun (the nature ‘sun’) which exists only insofar as it is instantiated by a unique individual. his deinable nature would not be universal, but would nevertheless be diferent from the unique particular that instantiates it (the deinable nature would be the same even if it were 11
See on this Adamson, this volume. I consciously avoid talking of «classes» and of their members, but rather adopt the term «collection», which is more neutral and does not suggest any direct parallel between these ancient views and modern logic. 12
304 Riccardo Chiaradonna
instantiated by several particulars). As we shall see below, Alexander of Aphrodisias develops an argument of this kind and treats the deinable nature (e.g. the genus ‘animal’, the species ‘human being’ or ‘sun’) as something separate from its being universal (see Alex. Aphr., Quaest. I.11a, 22, 3-6 and I.11b, 23, 26-27 Bruns). 2. Boethus of Sidon: the extensional position Unfortunately, the commentaries on the Categories by Boethus and Alexander are lost. he situation is extremely diicult with Boethus since, unlike what happens with Alexander, none of his works are extant. In order to assess his views, we depend completely on later second or third-hand accounts furnished by Neoplatonist commentators13. It is actually very unlikely that Dexippus and Simplicius read Boethus directly. Probably they based their accounts on Iamblichus, who in turn had relied on Porphyry’s lost commentary Ad Gedalium for information about Boethus14. his should indeed recommend prudence. For example, Martin Tweedale has convincingly shown that Simplicius sometimes provides a misleading account of Alexander’s position: the same might well be the case with Boethus, but, unlike what happens with Alexander, we cannot check Dexippus and Simplicius’ outlines against Boethus’ own writings. Furthermore, the testimonia are oten obscure: for instance, it is very diicult to separate Simplicius’ report from his assessment of Boethus’ position. hat said, we should not simply give in to desperation, since what we can ind in Dexippus and Simplicius is enough to draw a suiciently clear and consistent outline of Boethus’ position15. 13
On Boethus, see Moraux 1973, pp. 143-79. More recently, Reinhardt 2007; Rashed 2007, who provides an in-depth discussion of Boethus in relation to Alexander; Rashed 2013a. Sharples 2008a focuses on Boethus’ position within the early reception of Aristotle’s Categories; on this, see also Chiaradonna 2009b. Several testimonia on Boethus have now been translated and commented upon in Sharples 2010. Griffin forthcoming provides an extensive discussion of Boethus’ interpretation of the Categories. 14 It is controversial whether Simplicius read Porphyry’s Ad Gedalium directly. Chase 2003, p. 109 note 194 and passim suggests that Simplicius only relied on Iamblichus. 15 he recently discovered commentary on Aristotle’s Categories preserved in the
305 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
As noted above, Dexippus’ reference to Boethus and Alexander is open to diferent interpretations. he most we can say is that the Peripatetic position about the priority of individuals was diferent from the Neoplatonist realism about universals held by Iamblichus and his followers. However, two diferent interpretations are possible within the same Peripatetic philosophical background, i.e. the extensional and the intensional. Our testimonia on Boethus strongly suggest he held an extensional view of the universals. First it is worth focusing on Simpl., In Cat., 78, 4-20 Kalbleisch. Here Simplicius famously expounds Boethus’ views on sensible substance16. As Simplicius reports, Boethus compared Aristotle’s theory of substance in the Categories, according to which ousia is a single category (μίαν […] κατηγορίαν), to the division of substance into form, matter and composite which Aristotle expounds «elsewhere» (ἐν ἄλλοις). Boethus’ conclusion is radical to say the least: while matter and composite substance satisfy the criteria of substantiality established in the Categories, form is in matter as «in something else» and is therefore cut of from substance. hus, form should be seen as belonging to non-substantial categories such as quality, or quantity, or some other. Signiicantly, Boethus comes to this conclusion by noting that Aristotle’s deinition of primary substance (τὸν τῆς πρώτης οὐσίας λόγον, Simpl., In Cat., 78, 10 Kalbleisch) in the Categories can only be applied to matter and composite substance, since the property of ‘not being said of any subject and not being in any subject’ belongs to them (In Cat., 78, 11-12 Kalbleisch, see Arist., Cat., 5, 2a11-13 and 3a8-9). From these remarks, Boethus infers that form is outside the category of substance. Boethus, then, equates ‘substance’ with ‘primary substance’ without any further qualiication; apparently, he does not focus on the status of Aristotle’s secondary substances (species and genera) that are ‘said of a subject’ without ‘being in a subject’ (Cat., 5, 2a37-b2). Hence, he does not consider the hypothesis according to which form may be substance since it is ‘said of a subject’ with respect to matter without being, in consequence of this, ‘in a subject’ in relation to matter. Accordingly, if Simplicius’ parArchimedes palimpsest (probably a section of Porphyry’s Ad Gedalium) provides some crucial new testimonia on Boethus, which lend further support to the present interpretation. Here I will leave out these passages. For further discussion, see Chiaradonna, Rashed, Sedley 2013. 16 On this passage, see now Reinhardt 2007; Sharples 2010, pp. 86 f.; Rashed 2013a, who focuses on Boethus’ notion of quality.
306 Riccardo Chiaradonna
aphrase is trustworthy, Boethus makes a selection within Aristotle’s criteria of substantiality in the Categories: he accepts Aristotle’s stricter notion of substance (as the particular bearer of properties) and passes over in silence the reasons that may lead us to regard genera and species as secondary substances. Indeed, Simplicius’ second or third-hand paraphrase could well be inaccurate17. Yet, further testimonia suggest similar conclusions and it is tempting to infer from the extant evidence that according to Boethus universals have no reality at all by themselves and are nothing but mere collections of particulars. Simpl., In Cat., 50, 2-9 Kalbleisch contains Boethus’ answer to the aporia according to which individual substances are ‘in a subject’ with reference to the place and time in which they are situated. First Boethus denies that particular substances are ‘in a subject’ in relation to a particular place and a particular time: the reason for this fact is that substances in motion change place and time lows continually. One may say, however, that particulars are in universal time (ἐν τῷ καθόλου χρόνῳ, In Cat., 50, 5-6 Kalbleisch). Boethus answers that he universal does not even exist [οὐδὲ εἶναι ἐν ὑποστάσει]18 according to Aristotle, and if it did exist, it would not be ‘something’ [οὐ τὶ εἶναι]; but Aristotle said ‘in something’ [ἔν τινι]. So what is in something cannot be in what is universal (Simpl., In Cat., 50, 6-9)19.
Again, an opinionated reading of the Categories is detectable in these lines. In order to counter the view that particulars are in universal time 17
Signiicantly, Simplicius’ paraphrase of Boethus is followed immediately by Porphyry’s response (p. 78, 20 f. Kalbleisch = Porph. 58F. Smith), which Simplicius read either directly (if he had access to Porphyry’s Ad Gedalium) or via Iamblichus. 18 he translation of ὑπόστασις is famously controversial. In what follows I will variously render this term as «reality», «existence» or «real existence». A clear-cut distinction between essence and existence is actually diicult to ind in the Greek commentators (as well as in all ancient philosophers). Neither should we assume that an extremely common term such as ὑπόστασις always possesses the technical Stoic meaning of «subsistence». See on this Burnyeat 2003, pp. 20 f. 19 Dexipp., In Cat., 22, 30 f. Busse provides a slightly diferent version of this argument and does not name Boethus. Luna 2001, pp. 279 f. compares the two versions extensively. She concludes that, their diferences notwithstanding, «[l]es éléments utilisés dans les deux textes sont donc les mêmes; ce qui change, ce sont leur disposition et leur valeur» (Luna 2011, p. 281).
307 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
as ‘in a subject’, Boethus argues that time as a universal cannot in any way be conceived of as a subject in the relation of ‘being in a subject’ (ἐν ὑποκειμένῳ εἶναι). From Boethus’ remark one may legitimately infer that nothing can be related to a universal subject according to the relation of esse in subiecto, since (i) what is universal has no reality (ὑπόστασις) and (ii) even if universals had some kind of reality, they would, in any case, not be ‘something determinate’ (οὐ τὶ εἶναι). he relation between (i) and (ii) is not completely clear to me. I would propose that Boethus aims to separate the status of what is universal from both the status of substances and that of qualities. Both substances and qualities are, in fact, real entities, whereas universals are not. However, he might have added (ii) as sort of ad hominen remark: even if we grant that universals are real, they cannot however in any way be regarded as subjects of inherence. His explanation is ultimately based on Cat., 2, 1a24-25, where Aristotle deines what is in a subject as that which «is in something, not as a part [ὃ ἔν τινι μὴ ὡς μέρος ἐνυπάρχον], and cannot exist separately from what it is in». Apparently, Boethus leaves out Aristotle’s remark on the notion of ‘part’ and develops the idea that what is ‘in a subject’ should exist ‘in something’ (ἔν τινι). Even if we grant that what is universal has some kind of existence, it cannot in any way be taken to be a τι; accordingly, nothing can exist ἔν τινι in relation to a universal subject. he parallel passage from Dexippus’ commentary (οὐδὲν τῶν κοινῶν οὔτε τόδε οὔτε τὶ ὑπάρχει, Dexipp., In Cat., 22, 32-33 Busse) suggests that Boethus used τι as a designation for Aristotles’ τόδε τι. In fact, both in the Categories and in the Metaphysics Aristotle denies that what is universal (secondary substances, according to the jargon of Aristotle’s Categories) has the status of a τόδε τι. Rather, Aristotle is inclined to conceive of universals as quasi-qualitative entities (ποιόν τι, Cat., 5, 3b17; τοιόνδε, Met., Ζ 13, 1039a2). hat said, it is worth noting that Aristotle does not suggest that universals cannot have the position of subjects in the relation of ‘being in a subject’ (ἐν ὑποκειμένῳ εἶναι). As he argues in Cat., 5, 3a1-6, nothing prevents non-substantial items from being ‘in a subject’ with regard to substantial species and genera. Probably Boethus gave full emphasis to Aristotle’s remarks on the quasi-qualitative status of universal items and (unlike Aristotle) came to regard universals as incapable of being subjects in the relation of ἐν ὑποκειμένῳ εἶναι. As noted above, Simplicius’ account of Boethus’ theory of substance suggests that Boethus simply took the ‘category of substance’ to be identical with Aristotle’s primary substance in the Categories and ruled
308 Riccardo Chiaradonna
out Aristotle’s secondary substances. In a similar way, Simplicius’ account of universal time suggests that Boethus used the (genuine Aristotelian) remark that a universal item is not a tode ti in order to argue that universals have no reality and that even if they did, they could not in any way be conceived of as subjects of inherence. Further passages conirm these provisional conclusions. Boethus’ view about the tode ti is referred to again in Simpl., In Cat., 104, 27 Kalbleisch (Simplicius’ discussion is paralleled in Dexipp., In Cat., 51, 15-22 Busse, but Dexippus’ account is cursory and Boethus is not named). Simplicius asks in which respect we shall say that the individual substance is a tode ti: in respect of the form, the matter or the composite? In his answer, he explains that the individual can be seen as a tode ti on account of all of these. He mentions Boethus when he explains why the individual can be called a tode ti on account of its form: «[…] in respect of the form, insofar as it is determinate and one in number, for Boethus too determines unity by means of “this”»20. he reference is cursory to say the least and Simplicius seems to mention Boethus’ view outside of its original context (signiicantly, Boethus’ name appears immediately ater a reference to Plato’s theory of matter in Ti. 50b: see In Cat., 104, 25 Kalbleisch). hus, Simplicius’ discussion in these lines probably cannot be used in order to explain the sense of Boethus’ original remark. hat said, we can nevertheless assume with some certainty that Boethus determined (ἀφορίζει) unity according to the tode ti. Prudence is necessary, but the parallel with the passages discussed above suggests that Boethus regarded the tode ti (i.e. the individual substance) as the only kind of reality provided with genuine unity, whereas on his account genera and species do not 20
I follow the translation by de Haas in de Haas, Fleet 2001, p. 48. he Greek text is καὶ γὰρ ὁ Βόηθος τὸ ἒν κατὰ τόδε ἀφορίζει and it seems to me necessary to supply τὸ before τόδε (κατὰ τόδε: this suggestion was already made by Kalbleisch 1907, p. 559; see below, 104, 30-31 Kalbleisch: τὸ δὲ σύνθετον […] ἐπιδέχεται τὸ τόδε). Sharples’ translation is diferent and closer to the received text: «for Boethus too deines in this respect [κατὰ τόδε] what is one» (Sharples 2010, p. 79). As I see it, however, this interpretation is less convincing, because Simplicius does not focus on the deinition of what is one, but on the deinition of what can be regarded as a tode ti. Simplicius irst points out that an individual substance can be seen as a tode ti on account of its form, since form makes the individual determinate and one in number. hen, in support of his point, Simplicius mentions Boethus’ view that being one is the same as being tode ti.
309 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
correspond to any determinate entity provided with unity (since, if the present interpretation is correct, Boethus regarded genera and species as mere collections of particulars). his is simply an hypothesis, but it is nevertheless interesting that the cursory reference to Boethus ap. Simpl., In Cat., 104, 25 Kalbleisch may be read according to the conclusions reached so far. he same holds for a passage from Syrianus’ Commentary on the Metaphysics (In Met., 105, 19 f. Kroll) where he critically discusses some erroneous interpretations of Plato’s Ideas. According to Syrianus, Boethus the Peripatetic «goes astray as a result of Aristotle’s teaching, identifying the Forms with generic items» (εἰς ταὐτὸν ἄγων τοῖς γενικοῖς τὰς ἰδέας, 106, 6-7 Kroll). Syrianus speciies further that the Stoic Cornutus is not far from this position. he reference is again cursory and not very perspicuous. In particular, the status of Boethus’ genika needs further scrutiny. Syrianus (In Met., 106, 7-13 Kroll) opposes genika and particulars and equates genika and universals. his passage may plausibly be read in connection to Simplicius’ discussion on the universal time ap. Simpl., In Cat., 50, 6-9 Kalbleisch. Presumably, Boethus conlated ideas and universal items in order to criticize and undermine Plato’s Ideas. hus, he probably argued that Ideas, as well as universal items, do not exist. he parallel between Boethus and the Stoic Cornutus is obviously interesting in this respect21. Signiicantly, according to Syrianus Boethus is led astray by Aristotle’s teaching: his position is set out as an interpretation of Aristotle and Syrianus does not point to any direct Stoic inluence on Boethus. It is noteworthy however that Syrianus regards Boethus’ distinctive reading of Aristotle as convergent with Stoicism. hus, even without postulating a direct inluence of the Stoic view, we can reasonably assume that Boethus developed an opinionated reading of the Categories in which universal items were conceived of as beret of any existence. Predictably enough, Boethus’ position was perceived as close to that of the Stoics. Here the dossier ‘Boethus and the Stoa’ cannot be discussed extensively. Certainly Boethus was very well aware of the Stoic theories. Simplicius (In Cat., 163, 6 Kalbleisch) says that Boethus devoted a whole book (ὅλον βιβλίον)22 to the relative, in which he critically dis-
21
On universals in Stoicism, see Bronowski, this volume. Presumably, this book was part of his Commentary on the Categories, whatever its literary form: see on this Griffin forthcoming. 22
310 Riccardo Chiaradonna
cussed the Stoic views (see Simpl., In Cat., 167, 22 f. Kalbleisch)23. Furthermore, some of his views are indeed similar to those of the Stoics: this is the case with his theory of the immanent form as an ‘accident’ of matter (ap. Simpl., In Cat., 78, 11-20 Kalbleisch), which has been connected to the Stoic theory of quality24, and with his theory of the universals, whose ainities with the Stoic theory did not escape Syrianus. Robert Sharples remarks that «Boethus’ position is closer to that of the Stoics than to Aristotle»25, hese conclusions need some qualiication, however, since Boethus’ position can also be seen as a systematic reading of Aristotle which gives full weight to some aspects of Aristotle’s thought and treats other aspects as secondary. Marwan Rashed has interestingly presented that of Boethus as one among several «possible Aristotelianisms». According to Rashed, Boethus develops his systematic Aristotelianism by giving full weight to the ontic priority of individuals established in the Categories. As a consequence of this fact, Boethus regards the status of the hylomorphic form as secondary. hus, no speciic Stoic inluence would be necessary to explain Boethus’ position, which would only be based on a selection of works and themes internal to Aristotle’s corpus. Other Aristotelian commentators in the irst century BCE, such as Andronicus, shared this attitude and their reading of Aristotle was mostly based on the Categories (as Rashed aptly remarks, their Aristotelianism was «Catégories-centrique»), whereas works such as the Physics and the Metaphysics played a minor role. As Rashed takes it, Alexander of Aphrodisias’ essentialist reading of Aristotle was a reaction against the reading of his ancient colleagues26. Rashed’s reading sheds new light on the development of the ancient Aristotelian tradition. Yet I would perhaps qualify his interpretation with some further remarks. In my view, it is crucial to note that Aristotle’s Categories do not suice to explain the genesis of Boethus’ reading of Aristotle27, Boethus’ rejection of the universals outside substance goes in fact far beyond Aristotle’s views on species and genera as ‘secondary substances’. Boethus radicalizes the secondary status of genera 23
See Sharples 2010, pp. 62 f.; Rashed 2013a. See Reinhardt 2007, pp. 526 f. 25 Sharples 2010, p. 87. 26 See Rashed 2007, pp. 1-31 and p. 42; Rashed 2004. 27 Here I am inclined to disagree with Rashed 2007, p. 42: «Boéthos et consorts prennent les Catégories pour seul guide du réel». 24
311 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
and species, to the extent that they are conceived of as beret of real existence. hus, according to Boethus Aristotle’s substance is simply identical with the primary substance in the Categories, whereas secondary substances are not substances at all. Probably Boethus does not even take the status of universal items to be the same as that of nonsubstantial qualities or quantities. Rather, he is likely to be assuming that universal items simply do not exist as distinct from individuals. As we shall see below, Alexander follows a diferent path and does his best to give full emphasis to the substantial status of secondary substances. Certainly, they are secondary, since they are not independent of individuals and could not exist without any instantiation. Yet in Alexander’s view genera and species are not mere collections of particulars, but deinable natures that exist in particulars. Boethus’ view about the unqualiied ontic priority of individual substances may well be read in connection with the philosophical climate of his time, which was determined by the Hellenistic schools and by Stoicism in particular. I also suspect that the selection of Aristotle’s esoteric works among the early commentators was heavily inluenced by late Hellenistic philosophical debates (this holds for Aristotle’s Categories and On the Heaven, the two ‘star treatises’ of the early commentators)28. hese remarks are by no means intended to reject Rashed’s systematic reading of Boethus. In my view, however, it is philosophically very interesting to situate the genesis of Boethus’ reading of Aristotle within the philosophical climate of his time. his may help to explain why the early commentators developed an opinionated reading of Aristotle, which could be seen (and indeed later was seen) as convergent with Stoicism. It is worth focusing on two further diicult testimonia from Simplicius. he irst passage is about the theory of speciic diferentia: Boethus, however, says that the diferentia is properly placed with the species, not with the genus [ὁ μέντοι Βόηθος πρὸς τὸ εἶδος κυρίως συντάττεσθαί φησιν τὴν διαφοράν, ἀλλ’ οὐ πρὸς τὸ γένος], because the diferentiae are oten substituted for the species [ἀντὶ τοῦ εἷδους παραλαμβάνονται] (Simpl., In Cat., 97, 28-30 Kalbleisch)29.
In his discussion, Simplicius irst reports the view of some exegetes who regard the diferentia as something which by nature separates 28 29
See Chiaradonna 2013; Chiaradonna 2011c. Parallel in Dexipp., In Cat., 46, 1-2, where Boethus is not named.
312 Riccardo Chiaradonna
items under the same genus (In Cat., 97, 25-26 Kalbleisch). his deinition is an ancient one: it occurs in Porphryry’s Isagoge and its ultimate source is the Topics (Z 3, 140a27-29)30. According to Simplicius, Boethus disagrees, since he claims that the diferentia should properly be placed with the species, not with the genus. Ater the lines quoted above, Simplicius makes some further remarks, but it is unclear whether he is still reporting Boethus’ view or critically discussing it (Simpl., In Cat., 97, 31-34 Kalbleisch)31: for this reason, I will not consider these lines in the present discussion. Simplicius’ remark against Boethus at In Cat., 97, 34-35 Kalbleisch (cf. Dexipp., In Cat., 48, 6-9 Busse) is however very interesting and can be used as a starting point in order to outline Boethus’ position. Simplicius says that the diferentia is diferent from the species (Dexippus remarks that the diferentia is diferent from the species as the part is diferent from the whole) and it is a kind of form (μορφή) of the genus, while the genus is like a subject (ὑποκείμενον). It has been suggested that Boethus echoes Met. Ζ 12, where Aristotle identiies the ultimate diferentia with the eidos32. his is not impossible, but I would be prudent about Boethus’ use of Met. Ζ, since Aristotle’s hylomorphism plays virtually no role in Boethus’ philosophy. As I see it, Boethus’ silence about the genus, and his equation between the species and the diferentia can well be read as relecting the extensional interpretation developed so far. If, in fact, we conceive of universals in an extensional way, i.e. as collections of individuals, any generic entity or nature will simply be suppressed. Accordingly, the genus cannot be like a subject that is determined by the diferentia: this explains Simplicius’ critical remark. In Boethus’ view, the genus simply does not exist as such (i.e. as a nature determined in an intensional way): this explains Boethus’ parallel between the genera and Plato’s Ideas. If this is the case, the diferentia must be placed with the species, because the species is identical with the diferentia. he species cannot in fact be composed of the genus and the diferentia, since the genus in itself simply does not exist. Unfortunately, we do not know how Boethus conceived of the differentia and its ontic status (we do not know, in particular, whether See. Porph., Isag., 11, 18-19 Busse and the excellent commentary ad loc. in Barnes 2003, p. 197, with further parallels. 31 See de Haas in de Haas, Fleet 2001, p. 74 note 115. 32 De Haas in de Haas, Fleet 2001, p. 74 note 114. 30
313 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
he regarded diferentiae as tropes, something which would indeed it very well with the interpretation developed so far); neither do we know what kind of relation Boethus established between the diferentia and the (in his view non-substantial) hylomorphic form. So, the present discussion cannot but be partial and speculative. It is however at least possible to propose some hypotheses about Boethus’ view, which try to combine the information drawn from the passages discussed above. According to Boethus, matter and individuals are the only existing substantial subjects, whereas diferentiae are mere non-substantial qualities (diferentiae cannot be substantial, since they cannot be regarded as subjects of inherence). Species are mere collections of particulars grouped according to their diferentiae and these diferentiae are somehow equivalent to the non-substantial ‘formal’ properties inhering in matter mentioned ap. Simpl., In Cat., 78, 19-20 Kalbleisch. hus, diferentiae make it possible to class individuals according to speciic collections. For an individual, belonging to a species means belonging to a speciic collection on account of the non-substantial qualities inhering in it. According to this theory, a genus would be nothing but the sum (or rather the logical product) of several speciic collections (see also Simpl., In Cat., 58, 29-59.4 Kalbleisch). Boethus’ overall attitude can aptly be characterized as ‘nominalist’ and, as noted above, his position goes beyond what Aristotle says in the Categories. In Met., Ζ 12, 1038a5-6 Aristotle famously provides the following alternative: either the genus absolutely does not exist apart (παρά) from the species, or – if it does exist – exists as matter. If Boethus ever considered this text, he must have opted for the irst horn of the alternative. In his view, the genus has in itself simply no kind of existence and cannot be seen as the subject of any possible ‘information’ of the part of the diferentia. If general concepts have no real correlate apart from particulars, one might well wonder just what their status is. Did Boethus regard general concepts as mere mental ictions? Again, all we can do is draw some hypotheses. Possibly in his discussion about universals Boethus made use of his semantic view that propositions are «about» things (περὶ […] πράγματος), but their meaning is composed of concepts or «thoughts» (νοήσεις, see Simpl., In Cat., 41, 14-19 and 41, 28-42, 2 Kalbleisch), since according to Boethus there are no ‘propositional objects’ which can be the meaning of statements. Boethus’ remarks are perhaps (and very interestingly) reminiscent of Plato’s distinction between saying something and saying something about something (Pl., Sph. 262e-263d), and may well be directed against the Stoic
314 Riccardo Chiaradonna
λεκτόν33. hus, we cannot directly refer these remarks to the status of general concepts. hat said, the diference between being τοῦ πράγματος and being περὶ πράγματος (Simpl., In Cat., 41, 18-19 Kalbleisch) can plausibly be applied to the meaning of statements such as «Socrates is man» or «Socrates is animal». Boethus could easily argue that the predicate in these judgements does not stand for any general entity. So general terms only mean mental concepts. his, however, does not entail that species and genera are mere igmenta, since their real correlate is given by the particular members of their extension. According to this overall view, general terms would have the status of common names: again, such a theory can aptly be characterized as ‘nominalist’. hese diiculties notwithstanding, the passages discussed above provide a suiciently consistent picture of Boethus’ position about universals. he same is not the case with Simpl., In Cat., 65, 19-24 Kalbleisch. Here Simplicius focuses on some objections against the alleged completeness of Aristotle’s list of categories. Among these objections, he mentions the one concerning the categorial status of the monad and the point. Ater mentioning Alexander’s solution (the monad and the point should be placed among the relative), Simplicius says: If, however, number is twofold – one incorporeal, the other corporeal – then, as Boethus too would say the monad will also be twofold: one which is substance, and is in intelligible number – Aristotle also thinks that this one exists – and one which is a relative or quantiied item. Later, however, Boethus says that perhaps it is better to call it a quantiied item, for as whiteness is to white, so the dyad is to two. If, therefore, the former are both quantiied, the latter are also quantiied (Simpl., In Cat., 65, 19-24 Kalbleisch)34.
Paul Moraux had already remarked that this passage is troublesome to say the least35. Boethus’ criticism of Plato’s Ideas and his view about Boethus was certainly familiar with Plato’s Sophist: see below. On Boethus’ criticism of the Stoic lekton, see Rashed 2013a. 34 εἰ δὲ διττὸς ὁ ἀριθμός, ὁ μὲν ἀσώματος, ὁ δὲ σωματικός, ἔσται, ὡς καὶ ὁ Βόηθος ἂν φαίη, καὶ ἡ μονὰς διττή, ἡ μὲν οὐσία, ἡ ἐν τῷ νοητῷ ἀριθμῷ (τοῦτο δὲ καὶ Ἀριστοτέλει δοκεῖ), ἡ δὲ πρός τι ἢ ποσόν. ὕστερον δέ φησιν ὁ Βόηθος μήποτε ἄμεινον εἶναι ποσὸν φάναι· ὡς γὰρ λευκότης ἔχει πρὸς λευκόν, οὕτως καὶ ἡ δυὰς πρὸς τὰ δύο· εἰ οὖν ἐκεῖνα ἄμφω ποιόν, καὶ ταῦτα ποσόν. Parallel in Dexipp., In Cat., 33, 23-27 Busse. On these passages, see the extensive commentary in Luna 2001, pp. 673-96. 35 See Moraux 1973, p. 155. 33
315 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
the unqualiied priority of particulars cannot easily be reconciled with a theory of ideal numbers such as that which Simplicius seems to attribute to Boethus in these lines. Moraux, however, regards Simplicius’ report as trustworthy and suggests that Boethus followed Speusippus on this issue, since Boethus was certainly interested in Speusippus and referred to his theory of polyonyms (ap. Simpl., In Cat., 36, 2830 Kalbleisch). Unfortunately, Simplicius’ words (ὡς καὶ Βόηθος ἂν φαίη, 65, 20 Kalbleisch) do not help to settle the issue and it remains uncertain whether his paraphrase can be trusted completely or not36. Here I will propose a tentative explanation of this controversial passage. Simplicius’ outline of Boethus’ theory of sensible substance opens with these words: Ὁ μέντοι Βόηθος ταῦτα μὲν παρέλκειν τὰ ζητήματα βούλεται· μὴ γὰρ εἷναι περὶ τῆς νοητῆς οὐσίας τὸν λόγον (Simpl., In Cat., 78, 4-5 Kalbleisch). he questions (zêtêmata) rejected by Boethus are those set out in Simplicius’ previous pages, where he focuses on Nicostratus’ and Plotinus’ criticisms against substance. To make a long story short, according to Simplicius Nicostratus and Plotinus claim that Aristotle’s theory of substance in the Categories is unsatisfying and incomplete, since Aristotle leaves out intelligible substance (Simpl., In Cat., 76, 13-17)37. Simplicius’ account misleadingly lends the impression that Boethus countered these objections raised by later exegetes, arguing that their criticism was redundant since Aristotle’s discussion of substance in the Categories simply does not focus on the intelligible ousia. Perhaps Boethus was addressing objections developed by an early anti-Aristotelian exegete and similar to those later raised by Nicostratus and Plotinus. Perhaps Simplicius (or Iamblichus) incorporated Boethus in his account in order to counter Nicostratus’ and Plotinus’ later objections. It is also possible that Boethus was reacting to an early Platonizing reading of the Categories: by his remark, he might be warning that one should not read Plato’s Ideas into Aristotle’s ousia. Be that as it may38, Boethus certainly mentioned Aristotle’s irst mover in his discussion of ποιεῖν and πάσχειν (Simpl., In Cat., 302, 17 Kalbleisch). Accordingly, if Boethus really claimed that one should not consider the νοητὴ οὐσία when interpreting Cat. 5, by this he did not intend to rule out intelligible beings from the interpretation 36
See the critical remarks against Moraux in Tarán 1981, p. 745 f. Griffin forthcoming provides a full discussion. 37 On Plotinus and Nicostratus, see Chiaradonna 2005. 38 For further discussion, see Chiaradonna 2009b.
316 Riccardo Chiaradonna
of Aristotle’s Categories, nor suggest that intelligible beings do not exist at all. Rather, he was probably claiming that a discussion about intelligible substances is redundant in the framework of Cat. 5 (whereas in his view talking of the unmoved mover was certainly not redundant in the discussion on ποιεῖν and πάσχειν). Accordingly, nothing rules out the possibility that Boethus might have referred to the theory of intelligible numbers where he thought this to be relevant to his reading of Aristotle. his is all the more likely, since Boethus was possibly reacting against the Pythagorizing reading of Aristotle’s Categories developed by Eudorus of Alexandria, a reading which is detectable in Ps.-Archytas’ treatise Περὶ τῶ καθόλου λόγω, as well in Philo and Plutarch. Perhaps Boethus’ remark about the irrelevance of the sensible substance for the interpretation of Cat. 5 was originally directed against Eudorus39. Given such premises, Boethus’ mention of the intelligible monad is not really surprising: he might well have referred to this theory when discussing the views of his rival Platonic-Pythagorean readers of Aristotle (and this could explain why he would seem to ascribe the theory of intelligible numbers to Aristotle: this would in fact be an allusion to the exegesis developed by his opponents)40. Moraux’s parallel with Speusippus is plausible too, for the early commentators were certainly willing to recall and possibly incorporate the views of Plato and the Ancient Academy. As noted above, Boethus mentions Speusippus’ polyonyms and refers to Plato (Simpl., In Cat., 159, 12 f.). Andronicus mentions Xenocrates when discussing the categorial bi-partition per se/relative and the theory of the soul41. his attitude is easily justiiable within the philosophical climate of the irst century BCE, which was still rather luid and marked by the renaissance of ancient dogmatic philosophies within a philosophical debate dominated by the Hellenistic schools. Perhaps Boethus and Andronicus’ appeal to the Academy was directed against the Stoics. Be that as it may, Boethus’ mention of the intelligible monad can plausibly be placed within this picture. hese remarks, however, still do not answer to the main question 39
See Chiaradonna 2009b; Griffin forthcoming. his, however, is not completely sure, since the words τοῦτο δὲ καὶ Ἀριστοτέλει δοκεῖ at 65, 21 Kalbleisch might well be a remark by Simplicius. According to Chase 2003, p. 147 note 734 Simplicius’ reference may be to Aristotle’s lost On the Good. 41 Ap. Simpl. In Cat., 63, 22-24 Kalbleisch; Them. In De An., 32, 19-31 Heinze. See Rashed 2004. 40
317 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
raised by the passage quoted above: given Boethus’ nominalist position about substance and universals, is it plausible that he developed a Platonizing theory of ideal numbers and that he ascribed this view to Aristotle? Certainty cannot be attained, and Simplicius’ passage is obscure. Actually Simplicius refers to two diferent solutions proposed by Boethus. According to the irst solution, Boethus distinguished between a substantial monad, which is in the realm of intelligible number, and a relative or quantiied monad (which should obviously be placed in the sensible world). According to a second solution set out «later», however, Boethus says that perhaps it is better to call «it» a quantiied item, for the dyad is to two as whiteness is to white. Accordingly, if both whiteness and white are qualiied, then both the dyad and the two are quantiied. he Greek text at 65, 14 Kalbleisch runs as follows: ὕστερον δέ φησιν ὁ Βόηθος μήποτε ἄμεινον εἶναι ποσὸν φάναι. he subect of einai poson can plausibly be identiied with the monad. If this is the case, according to Boethus’ second solution both the monad and the dyad are quantiied items. hus, given a couple of particulars, the dyad is the quantity which corresponds to the quantiied predicate ‘two’. his view is not incompatible with those on the status of substances and generic items and does not point to any metaphysics of ideal numbers. According to Simplicius, however, Boethus’ irst solution recognized the existence of intelligible numbers (among which we should place the substantial monad). If Simplicius does not misleadingly ascribe to Boethus the Platonist-Pythagorean view that he aimed to reject through his second solution (although this may well be the case, as noted above), then we are forced to admit that Boethus acknowledged the existence not only of the unmoved mover, but also of ideal numbers. While I would not endorse this reading without some hesitation, it is crucial to note that even in this case Boethus would not be conceiving of ideal numbers as causal principles, nor taking them to be generic of universal entities. Rather, essential numbers would have the status of intelligible individuals, and thus be diferent from Plato’s Forms (which Boethus regarded as non-substantial genika). We ind a similar situation in Alexander (ap. Simpl., In Cat., 82, 7-10 Kalbleisch), who – according to Iamblichus/Simplicius – claims that the intelligible and separate form (τὸ νοητὸν καὶ χωριστὸν εἶδος) is called individual substance (ἄτομον οὐσίαν). Simplicius explains that this view is probably characteristic of the Peripatus, since according to the members of this school common items have no independent existence (οὐδέ ἐστιν ὅλως καθ’ ἑαυτὰ ἐν ὑποστάσει), but rather only have
318 Riccardo Chiaradonna
their being in individuals. his passage is indeed somewhat surprising and might suggest that Alexander held some version of Plato’s theory of separate forms. his is certainly not the case, however, and Simplicius later explains (In Cat., 90, 21 f. Kalbleisch) that Alexander was referring to what he took to be a separate form, i.e. the irst mover42. Possibly Alexander was replying to Nicostratus, who regarded Aristotle’s discussion in the Categories as partial, since Aristotle leaves out intelligible substances. Against Nicostratus, Alexander was perhaps attempting to show that the accounts of substance in Cat. 5 and Met. Λ are compatible, since Aristotle’s deinition of primary substance in the Categories can also be referred to the unmoved mover, which is not a universal but an individual, and is not in subiecto. If Simplicius’ paraphrase of Boethus’ irst solution is trustworthy, the passage about the intelligible monad could be interpreted along similar lines, and Boethus’ view on the monad would in no way be opposed to his nominalist view of generic items. In fact, whether he really admitted an intelligible monad or not, nothing suggests that he conceived of it as a universal. his hypothesis might suggest further (indeed very speculative) conclusions. Alexander was probably inclined to equate the status of mathematical objects and that of universals43. In both cases, he developed an abstractionist view according to which these items are immanent in sensible particulars and our soul is able to separate them from matter, thus conceiving them ‘in themselves’. his view should carefully be distinguished from that according to which mathematical objects are mere mental constructions. In fact, both universals and mathematical objects are perfectly real entities that can be determined objectively. Our soul simply separates them from matter and conceives of in itself what de facto only exists insofar as it is instantiated by material objects. As noted above, Boethus’ view on universals is radically diferent from Alexader’s abstractionist essentialism and we can plausibly suppose that Alexander was reacting against his predecessor. According to Boethus, universals are mere collections of individuals, they are beret of existence and there is no entity that corresponds to 42
See on this Guyomarc’h 2008. On Alexander’s approach to Plato’s forms, see Lefebvre 2008. 43 See Mueller 1990, pp. 467-70 with the supplementary remarks in Rashed 2011, pp. 59-64, who convincingly rejects Mueller’s mentalistic interpretation of Alexander’s abstractionism.
319 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
(e.g.) the general concept ‘human being’ and is immanent in particular human beings. It is at least possible that Boethus regarded ‘human being’ as a mere mental concept without any direct general real correlate, whereas the expression ‘human being’ actually denotes the particular human beings classed according to their proper qualities. Given such premises, if Boethus was inclined to conceive of mathematical objects as real independent entities, he could not have regarded their status as parallel to that of the genika. Hence, it is not completely unlikely that he held some (perhaps Speusippean) theory according to which ideal numbers are individual and intelligible substances. If this is true, Boethus’ distinguished real individual and substantial numbers from those in the sensible world, which are mere quantiied and collective predicates of particular items. his would explain the relation between Boethus’ irst and second solution, without making the two incompatible. If this is the case, Alexander’s essentialism was toto caelo opposed to Boethus’ ontology, both on the status of universals and on that of mathematical objects. To sum up: either Simplicius’ paraphrase is misleading and Boethus’ irst solution does not express Boethus’ own view, but rather that of his Pythagorean opponents, or Simplicius’ paraphrase is correct, and Boethus’ irst solution provides a realist view about mathematical objects, which is compatible with Boethus’ nominalism about universals. he second solution expresses either Boethus’ own position (as opposed to that of the Pythagoreans), or his view about sensible and quantiied numbers (as opposed to substantial and intelligible numbers).
3. Alexander of Aphrodisias’ essentialism and his views on universals his ‘nominalist’ view on universals is repeatedly criticized by Alexander of Aphrodisias, whose own Peripatetic view is basically equivalent to the ‘intensional’ position set out above44. Even if Alexander does not mention Boethus by name in these contexts (indeed, Alexander rarely mentions the names of his adversaries), it is more than plausible that Boethus was his polemical target. Against Boethus’ nominalism, Alexander develops a kind of moderate realism about universals, 44
he literature on Alexander’s views on universals is abundant. I would only refer to Lloyd 1981; Tweedale 1984; Sharples 2005; Rashed 2007, pp. 254-60. Sorabji 2004, pp. 149-56 provides an excellent survey.
320 Riccardo Chiaradonna
which is part of his overall systematic essentialist reading of Aristotle’s logic, physics and ontology. Here I will only cursorily recall some aspects of Alexander’s position. Quaestio I.3 probably provides the clearest way to approach all aspects of Alexander’s sophisticated realism45. In this short work, Alexander aims to establish what kind of things are those referred to by deinitions. he Quaestio opens by outlining two opposite theories that Alexander rejects. According to the irst position (7, 20-24 Bruns), deinitions refer to particulars. Alexander rejects this view because particulars are what they are in conjunction with accidents; they are not always self-identical, but are subject to change; and in addition to that, particulars are the object of perception rather than deinition. According to the second position (7, 24-27 Bruns), deinitions refer to a common entity separated from particulars, an entity that is incorporeal and eternal. Alexander rejects this theory too. His remark is rather cursory and he simply asks how ‘biped’ could be something incorporeal and ‘mortal’ something eternal. his remark is actually not very convincing: for instance, one may well conceive of the separate form ‘biped’ as an incorporeal entity, which is the principle that explains why the quality ‘biped’ is present in corporeal things. Signiicantly, Alexander himself regards qualities inhering to sensible particulars as incorporeal (see De An., 18, 5-7 Bruns), since they do not include matter in their nature even if they exist only in conjunction with matter46. So his polemical remark against self-subsisting separate incorporeal forms could in principle also be addressed against his own views on qualities. However, Alexander’s remark can perhaps better be understood in connection to what he says against the nominalist position in the immediately preceding lines. According to Alexander, deinitions should refer to stable objects that only reason can grasp adequately. his prevents deinitions from referring to particulars that exist in conjunction with accidents and are beret of stability. hat said, one should not assume that there are deinable entities independent of particulars: such entities would in fact be beret of any connection with particulars. His remark about the status of ‘biped’ and ‘mortal’ can be read as an emphatic statement of this point. Deinitions must in some way be connected to sensible particulars: using notions such as that of ‘biped’ or ‘mortal’ in order to refer to entities separate from and 45 46
See now the commentated translation of this work in Rashed 2007, pp. 257 f. See on this Kupreeva 2003.
321 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
independent of particular biped and mortal living beings would make little (if any) sense. his issue comes up at 7, 27-28 Bruns, where Alexander says that deinitions refer to (a) common entities that exist in particulars, or (vel) (b) to those particulars insofar as they are determined by the common entities that are present in them (ἀλλ’ εἰσὶν οἱ ὁρισμοὶ τῶν ἐν τοῖς καθέκαστα κοινῶν, ἣ τῶν καθέκαστα κατὰ τὰ ἐν αὐτοῖς κοινά). In his view, (a) and (b) are not mutually exclusive hypotheses, but diferent ways of expressing the same fact. We can now clearly understand why Alexander rejects both the nominalist and the realist Platonic positions. Since deinitions refer to entities that are common and diferent from particulars, the nominalist view must be rejected. Particulars, however, cannot merely be cut of from the object of deinition: if this were the case, we could well deine the universal Human Being, but this deinition could in no way be applied to particular human beings. Alexander takes a sort of middle path between Boethus’ nominalism and a kind of Platonic realism47. According to Alexander, the fact that several individuals are ‘such and such’ is grounded on another more primitive fact, i.e. the existence of a common entity according to which (cf. κατά, 7, 28 Bruns) those particulars are ‘such and such’. As far as we can judge from the extant evidence, Boethus held a very diferent view and regarded the fact that several particulars are ‘such and such’ (in his jargon: that several particulars have certain diferences) as primitive: this primitive fact does not require any further explanation. Alexander’s objection, however, points to an interesting problem. A radically anti-essentialistic view should address the issue of how to establish a suicient criterion in order to select those aspects of particular beings which make it possible to rank them under the same species. In other words, a philosophical position that suppresses the existence of generic or speciic essences should nonetheless somehow account for our classiications of the natural world. Indeed, one may well argue that natural species are nothing but pragmatic arbitrary classiications with no ontic import. Alexander, however, would probably have regarded this conclusion as simply nonsensical (and all ancient non-sceptic philosophers would share such an attitude). his explains Alexander’s remark at 7, 21-22 Bruns that particulars 47
As Rashed 2007, p. 259 aptly remarks, «[l]es Aristotéliciens ne doivent pas combattre le platonisme en sombrant dans le nominalisme».
322 Riccardo Chiaradonna
are ‘such and such’ (τοιαῦτα) in conjunction with accidents. In his view, a deinition entails that we select its object and isolate it from the other features which inhere to particulars. Alexander, therefore, demands a suicient criterion for establishing this selection and his essentialism actually provides an answer to the problem (indeed, an answer that could easily be criticized as circular), whereas Boethus’ radical antirealist position is much more problematic from this perspective. Signiicantly, Simplicius reports that Porphyry raised a similar objection: according to Porphyry, Boethus envisaged enmattered form (what Aristotle himself conceived of as substance) as nothing but a quality or some other among the accidents (ap. In Cat., 78, 21-22 Kalbleisch = 58F. Smith). hus, he was not able to isolate essential features from qualitative aspects in the structure of sensible particulars. Porphyry’s objections against Boethus recall Alexander’s views and it is more than likely that Porphyry based his criticism on previous objections raised by Alexander48. his is not enough to demonstrate beyond all doubt that Boethus is polemically targeted at the beginning of Alexander’s Quaestio I.3 (although this is a plausible hypothesis); be that as it may, the philosophical parallel between Boethus’ position and Alexander’s nominalist polemical target remains interesting. In the remaining part of the Quaestio, Alexander focuses on the ontic status of immanent deinable entities. As he explains at 7, 32 f. Bruns, the deinition «rational mortal animal»49 can be taken in conjunction with the «material circumstances and diferences» accompanying its concrete existence: in this case, the deinable entity produces (ποιεῖ, 8, 2) Socrates, Callias and all other individuals. herefore, we should not suppose that particular beings and their deinable natures are mutually separated. Each deinable nature (e.g. ‘human being’) only exists insofar as it is instantiated by the particular material beings determined by it. If all particulars were suppressed, the deinable nature would be suppressed with them (see also Quaest. I.11b, 24, 11-15 and 19-22 Bruns). his, however, does not entail that particular beings are all that exists. Indeed, objects of deinition are immanent to particulars and exist in actuality only insofar as they determine particular beings. hat said, it is crucial to regard each object of deinition as an entity irreducible to particulars, an entity that we can grasp through our mind in isolation 48
See Chiaradonna, Rashed 2010, pp. 272 f. Here Alexander calls ‘deinition’ the deinable nature which is the real correlate of the deinition. 49
323 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
from the particulars which it is in. When grasped by our mind, the object of deinition becomes common (κοινὸν γίνοιτο, 8, 3-4 Bruns). his is a key aspect of Alexander’s abstractionist realism, according to which deinitions refer to real natures that exist in individuals. hese are natures that are not universal as such, but only insofar as our soul isolates them from matter and conceives of them by themselves (see De An., 85, 14-20 Bruns). If we come back to the parallel between Boethus and Alexander established by Dexippus, we can easily see how Alexander’s essentialist thesis about the ontic priority of individuals toto caelo difers from Boethus’ extensional theory. According to Alexander, what is common is a nature that is deinable and irreducible to particulars, a nature that exists «in each particular as a whole», the same in all (8, 9-10 Bruns). Alexander conceives of both the speciic (human being: see. Quaest. I.3) and the generic (animal: see Quaest. I.11 a and b) deinable natures in this way50. In both cases, he aims to rule out all possible extensional conclusions in the theory of universals. hus, universals are connected to formal natures that are deinable in themselves and are the proper object of rational knowledge. Alexander’s famous and controversial thesis according to which what we call a universal is an «accident» of a given «thing» (πρᾶγμα, Quaest. I.11a, 22, 3-6; I.11b, 23, 26-27; see I.3, 8, 12-13 Bruns) is part of this theory. As noted by M. Tweedale, the «thing» which the universal is an accident of should not be equated with a particular being, but with a deinable nature (animal or human being)51. Alexander’s terminology is not completely consistent, but a general theory is clearly at work in his writings. Formal natures can be determined and deined by themselves and are not necessarily universal as such. If, for example, there were only one human being, his deinable nature would not be universal (at least de facto), since it would be instantiated by only one particular being. Nonetheless, it would equally be possible to isolate the deinable nature human being from the unique human being determined by this nature (Quaest. I.3, 8, 13-16 Bruns). Hence it is an accident that the deinable nature is universal, while it 50
Here I ignore Alexander’s sophisticated and somewhat ambivalent ontology of the genus: see Rashed 2007, pp. 94-104. I only focus on what Rashed would call «la teneur formelle» of the genus. 51 See Tweedale 1984. Alexander’s view that what is universal is an accident of the deinable nature should not be conlated with the view that existence is an accident of the deinable nature: see Chiaradonna, Rashed 2010, p. 288.
324 Riccardo Chiaradonna
not accidental that this nature is intensionally determined as it is. As reported by Simpl., In Cat., 85, 13-14 Kalbleisch, Alexander applied this line of argument to some canonical examples of species instantiated by only one particular, such as the sun, the moon and the cosmos52. As noted above, at the beginning of Quaestio I.3 Alexander raises a quasi-Platonist criticism against the nominalist position: deinitions cannot refer to particulars, since particulars change and deinitions should refer to permanent objects. he concluding part of this short work explains how Alexander regards deinable natures as permanent objects without conceiving of them as separate quasi-Platonic forms. As he notes, common natures are incorruptible in virtue of the «eternity by succession» (ἐκ τῆς διαδοχῆς αἰδιότητι, 8, 23 Bruns) of the particulars in which they exist. hus, the logico-epistemological realist analysis of deinable natures is ultimately grounded in the Peripatetic hylomorphic analysis of generation. As noted by Marwan Rashed, the hylomorphic form provides objective content for the species and makes it diferent from any arbitrary classiication53. he close connection between universality, the eternity of the species and hylomorphic form emerges in Alexander’s On Providence (87, 5-91, 4 Ruland)54. Here Alexander relies on Aristotle’s GC Β 10 and explains that the eternal and universal species is the primary object of providence. Eternity and universality come to be taken as equivalent characters. As Rashed remarks, the eidos is unique in the chain of generation: its continual and eternal realization directly entails that it is universal55. A succinct comparison between Boethus’ and Alexander’s views may help to summarize our conclusions. According to Boethus, universals are mere collections of individuals, whereas according to Alexander universals are deinable entities that happen to be universals insofar as they are instantiated by several particulars. As far as we can judge, according to Boethus deinitions are simply based on the primitive fact that particulars are ‘such and such’, whereas according to Alexander the actual structure of sensible particulars depends on immanent deinable natures. Boethus’ general view makes it very diicult to isolate those essential aspects that allow us to rank several particulars under 52
Tweedale 1984, p. 293 shows that Simplicius does not understand Alexander’s point correctly. 53 See Rashed 2007, pp. 253 f. 54 his text is preserved in Arab. Translation in Rashed 2007, p. 253. 55 See Rashed 2007, p. 255.
325 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
the same species. Alexander’s position is instead completely grounded on a clear-cut distinction between essence and accidents. Finally, Boethus ascribes unqualiied priority to the notion of substance as subject, thus relegating the status of enmattered forms outside substance. Alexander, instead, accords unqualiied ontic priority to the essential form and the theory of eidos can be seen as the philosophical focus of Alexander’s reading of Aristotle. 4. he Neoplatonic criticism and the levelling of the diferent Aristotelianisms If the present discussion is correct, Dexippus certainly simpliies Boethus and Alexander’s views when he presents them as identical. he parallel established by Dexippus, however, can easily be appreciated from the perspective of the post-Iamblichean Neoplatonist theory of universals. Some preliminary remarks are necessary. Alexander’s essentialist reading of Aristotle paved the way for the later incorporation of Aristotle’s ontology within Neoplatonism. On the one hand, Plotinus’ critical discussion of Aristotle is largely shaped by Alexander. Much work has still to be done on these issues, but Alexander can safely be regarded as a ilter through which Plotinus understands Aristotle’s philosophy and criticizes some of Aristotle’s principal theories (in particular his hylomorphic account of nature). On the other hand, Porphyry’s harmonizing of Plato and Aristotle is heavily inluenced by Alexander’s essentialist reading, which Porphyry incorporates into his overall Platonist account of reality. his clearly emerges from the theory of the hylomorphic form and that of universals. Porphyry seems to follow Alexander closely and takes a somewhat simpliied version of Alexander’s essentialism as a valid account of physical reality, with the fundamental proviso that this account should be placed within a broader Platonist view, which includes real intelligible principles too. Porphyry’s general programme of harmonizing Plato and Aristotle is basically followed by all later Neoplatonists, but signiicant diferences and nuances are to be found between one philosopher and another within this general framework. Iamblichus (the source of the passages from Dexippus and Simplicius discussed in this contribution) systematically develops what might aptly be called a throughout Neoplatonisation of Aristotle. Simplicius (see In Cat., 2, 9-14 Kalbleisch) says that Iamblichus followed Porphyry closely, but, unlike Porphyry, applied his «intellective theory» (νοερὰ θεωρία) everywhere. his expres-
326 Riccardo Chiaradonna
sion refers to the metaphysical account of intelligible beings which had a key position in Iamblichus’ exegesis. In addition to that, Iamblichus took Aristotle’s Categories to be inspired by Archytas’ Pythagorean teaching. As far as we can judge, this attitude was signiicantly diferent from that of Porphyry, who extensively followed the Peripatetic views of Alexander. For example, Iamblichus interpreted Aristotle’s theory of substantial predication from the perspective of the Neoplatonist theory of derivation. Accordingly, he regarded substantial predication as the logical expression of the metaphysical relation in virtue of which physical realities partake in the separate ante rem forms (ap. Simpl., In Cat., 52, 9-18 Kalbleisch). Iamblichus pushed his reading of Aristotle along Platonic/Pythagorean lines so far that (as David/Elias, In Cat., 123, 2-3 Busse reports) he did not refrain from assuming that Aristotle was not opposed to Plato on the theory of Ideas56. he Iamblichean background is crucial to understanding Dexippus and Simplicius’ accounts of the Peripatetics, for the diference between the extensional and the intensional readings of Aristotle becomes minimal or irrelevant from the perspective of Iamblichus’ extreme Platonist realism. Dexippus’ sequence of questions (In Cat., 44, 31 f. Busse = Simpl., In Cat., 82, 1 f. Kalbleisch) clearly reveals the overall scope of his discussion. a) Why does Aristotle call the sensible substance «primary» in the Categories, whereas elsewhere the sensible substance is ranked second ater the incorporeal (Dexipp., In Cat., 44, 30-31 Busse = Simpl., In Cat., 82, 1-2 Kalbleisch)? b) Why is it that in the Physics Aristotle ranks common items as primary, whereas in the Categories he ranks particulars irst (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 3-4 Busse = Simpl., In Cat., 82, 14-15 Kalbleisch)? c) What could one reply to those who dispute this very point and claim that in fact universals are not prior in nature to particulars, but posterior to them (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 12-14 Busse = Simpl., In Cat., 82, 22-23 Kalbleisch)? Dexippus provides the following answers (the parallel with Simplicius is extremely close and it is virtually certain that both were paraphrasing Iamblichus). a1) In the Categories Aristotle calls the sensible substance «primary» because sensible realities are called substances in common parlance: here Aristotle’s purpose is not to speak about incorporeal substances. b1) Unlike what happens in the Categories, in the Physics Aristotle follows the 56
In these paragraphs I summarise what I have tried to show in a number of recent contributions. See esp. Chiaradonna, Rashed 2010, pp. 268 f. (on Plotinus and Alexander); Chiaradonna 2007c (on Porphyry and Iamblichus).
327 The Theory of Universals in the Aristotelian Commentators
natural order of things and not their order «in relation to us». According to the natural order, one «will give prior ranking to simple entities, causes, things which have their being in themselves, universal, immaterial entities, indivisibles and such like» (τὰ ἁπλᾶ, τὰ αἴτια, τὰ καθ᾽ αὑτὰ παρ᾽ αὑτῶν ἔχοντα τὸ εἶναι, τὰ καθόλου, τὰ ἄϋλα, τὰ ἀμέριστα καὶ τὰ τοιαῦτα προτάξει, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 8-10 Busse = Simpl., In Cat., 82, 19-20 Kalbleisch). c1) To those who regard individuals as prior in nature, we should reply that Aristotle takes common items as prior in his theory of sensibles as well (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 29-31 Busse). hus, Dexippus and Simplicius read their Neoplatonist theory of universal and intelligible beings into Aristotle and argue that this view is set out in the Physics57. Furthermore, they claim that universals are prior in the account of sensible beings as well: accordingly, Dexippus and Simplicius conlate universals and immanent essential natures completely. According to this view, the reality of an immanent nature is not grounded in its instantiation. Rather, immanent natures exist because they derive from separate universals and partake in them (see Iamblichus ap. Simpl., In Cat., 52, 9-18 Kalbleisch). his view is toto caelo diferent from both Boethus’ extensional reading of Aristotle and Alexander’s intensional one, since in both of them the metaphysical notion of participation plays no role at all. According to the Neoplatonist metaphysics of participation (which Iamblichus and his followers read into Aristotle), we cannot in any way regard particulars as primary according to the canonical rules of priority. In fact, Dexippus takes immanent common items to be primary because they complete the essence of particulars: ὁ γὰρ τὶς ἄνθρωπος καὶ ἄνθρωπός ἐστι (Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 22-24 Busse). he being of the common item will exted to all the things ranked under it (ἔχει τὸ κοινὸν τὴν οὐσιάν ἐν τῷ διατείνειν ἐφ’ ὅλα τὰ ὑπ’ αὐτὸ τεταγμένα, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 26 Busse). hus, if the common item is removed, the whole existence of the individual is removed as well. It is along these lines, according to Dexippus, that one must reply to the arguments of the associates of Alexander, Boethus and the other Peripatetics (τοῖς περὶ Ἀλέξανδρον καὶ Βόηθον τοῖς τε ἄλλοις Περιπατητικοῖς, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 28 Busse). Aristotle’s Metaphysics is crucial for any attempt to reject the According to Dillon 1990, p. 82 note 32 Dexippus refers to Arist., Ph., Α 1, 184a23; A 7, 189b31 and Δ 1, 200b24. De Haas in de Haas, Fleet 2001, p. 70 note 44 points out the parallel with Simpl., In Ph., 14, 30-20, 27; 208, 27-32 Diels. See now Menn 2010. 57
328 Riccardo Chiaradonna
Peripatetic theory of immanent universals: in interpreting this work one can show (pace Alexander and Boethus) that Aristotle gives priority to common items (τὰ κοινά) even when considering sensible things (καὶ ἐν τῆ τῶν αἰσθητῶν θεωρίᾳ, Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 29-31 Busse). Dexippus’ καὶ at 45, 30 Busse raises some problems. Why should one reject Boethus’ and Alexander’s views by showing the priority of common items even when considering sensible things? Two hypotheses are possible. According to the irst, Dexippus’ καὶ refers to the theses held by the Peripatetic commentators. Accordingly, Dexippus would be suggesting that Boethus and Alexander recognized the priority of common items in relation to intelligible beings, but not sensible ones. Against their view, Dexippus wishes to show that Aristotle gives prior ranking to common items even when considering sensible beings. his hypothesis is ingenious, but remains unlikely in my view58. Dexippus’ allusion would be exceedingly cryptic. Furthermore, Boethus and Alexander recognized the existence of intelligible substances but, as noted above, they certainly did not regard such substances as universal. Instead, Alexander overtly regards his separate form (i.e. the irst mover) as a kind of individual substance (ap. Simpl., In Cat., 82, 6-7 and 90, 31-32 Kalbleisch). As I see it, Dexippus’ καὶ can easily be explained in relation to what Dexippus says above, i.e. in his discussion of the immediately preceding questions. here he argues that Aristotle regarded universals as primary in nature when considering intelligible beings. According to Dexippus, this view can be found in the Physics. What about sensible things? According to the Peripatetic commentators, Aristotle conceived of sensible particulars as primary. his, however, is not the case according to Dexippus, and the Metaphysics shows that Aristotle regarded common items as primary even when considering sensible beings (and not only when considering intelligible beings, as Dexippus argues in the previous lines). hus, I take the καὶ at 45, 30 Busse to refer to Dexippus’ Neoplatonist philosophical agenda, which reads a hyper-realist theory of universals into Aristotle, with regard to both universalia ante rem (see Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 9-10 Busse) and universalia in re (see Dexipp., In Cat., 45, 22-24, 25-27 Busse). Riccardo Chiaradonna 58
A detailed defence of this hypothesis can be found in Griffin forthcoming. Grifin’s account of Boethus is astute and difers signiicantly from that of the present study.
Bibliography
Ackrill 1963: Aristotle: Categories and De interpretatione, trans. and notes by J.L. Ackrill, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1963. Ackrill 1997: J.L. Ackrill, In Defense of Platonic Division, in J.L. Ackrill, Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1997, pp. 93-109. Adam 1902: he Republic of Plato, ed. and notes by J. Adam, 2 vols., Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1902. Adamson 2008: P. Adamson, Plotinus on Astrology, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 34, 2008, pp. 265-91. Ademollo 2007: F. Ademollo, he Equals, the Equals hemselves, Equality, and the Equal Itself, «Documenti e studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 18, 2007, pp. 1–20. Ademollo 2011: F. Ademollo, he Cratylus of Plato: A Commentary, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2011. Albritton 1957: R. Albritton, Forms of Particular Substances in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «he Journal of Philosophy», 54, 1957, pp. 699-708. Allen J. 1994: J. Allen, Failure and Expertise in the Ancient Conception of an Art, in Scientiic Failure, ed. by T. Horowitz and A.I. Janis, Lanham, Rowman & Littleield 1994, pp. 81-108. Allen J. 2001: J. Allen, Inference from Signs. Ancient Debates about the Nature of Evidence, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2001. Allen R. 1959: R.E. Allen, Forms and Standards, «he Philosophical Quarterly», 9, 1959, pp. 164-7. Allen R. 1960: R.E. Allen, Participation and Predication in Plato’s Middle Dialogues, «he Philosophical Review», 69, 1960, pp. 147–64. Allen R. 1969: R.E. Allen, Individual Properties in Aristotle’s Categories, «Phronesis», 14, 1969, pp. 31-9.
472 Bibliography
Andrenacci, Palpacelli 2003: E. Andrenacci, L. Palpacelli, Una possible soluzione del rebus di Metaisica, I 10, 1058b26-29, «Rivista di ilosoia neoscolastica», 45, 2003, pp. 615-25. Annas 1974: J. Annas, Individuals in Aristotle’s Categories: Two Queries, «Phronesis», 19, 1974, pp. 146-52. Anscombe 1953: G.E.M. Anscombe, he Principle of Individuation, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», suppl. vol. 27, 1953, pp. 83-96. Armstrong 1978a: D.M. Armstrong, Universals and Scientiic Realism. Vol. 1: Nominalism and Realism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1978. Armstrong 1978b: D.M. Armstrong, Universals and Scientiic Realism. Vol. 2: A heory of Universals, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1978. Armstrong 1989: D.M. Armstrong, Universals. An Opinionated Introduction, Boulder (CO), Westview Press 1989. Armstrong 1997: D.M. Armstrong, A World of States of Afairs, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997. Asmis 1984: E. Asmis, Epicurus’ Scientiic Method, Ithaca (NY)-London, Cornell University Press 1984. Aubenque 1962: P. Aubenque, Le problème de l’être chez Aristote, Paris, PUF 1962. Auffret 2011: Th. Auffret, Aristote, Métaphysique Α1-2: Un texte “éminemment platonicien”?, «Elenchos», 22, 2011, pp. 263-85. Ayres 2002: L. Ayres, Not hree People: he Fundamental hemes of Gregory of Nyssa’s Trinitarian heology as Seen in To Ablabius: On Not hree Gods, «Modern heology», 18, 2002, pp. 445–74. Baltes, Lakmann 2005: M. Baltes, M.-L. Lakmann, Idea (dottrina delle idee), in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 1-23. Barnes 1979: J. Barnes, he Presocratic Philosophers, London, Routledge 1979. Barnes 1984: he Complete Works of Aristotle. he Revised Oxford Translation, ed. by J. Barnes, 2 vols., Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 1984.
473 Bibliography
Barnes 1988: J. Barnes, Epicurean Signs, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 1988, suppl. vol., pp. 91- 134. Barnes 1991: J. Barnes, Galen on Logic and herapy, in Galen’s Method of Healing, ed. by F. Kudlien and R.J. Durling, Leiden, Brill 1991, pp. 50-102. Barnes 2003: Porphyry: Introduction, trans. and comm. by J. Barnes, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2003. Barnes 2007: J. Barnes, Truth, etc., Oxford, Oxford University Press 2007. Barnes 2009: J. Barnes, Feliciano’s Translation of Dexippus, «International Journal of the Classical Tradition», 16, 2009, pp. 523-31. Barney 2001: R. Barney, Names and Nature in Plato’s Cratylus, New York-London, Routledge 2001. Barrett 1964: Euripides: Hippolytos, ed. by W.S. Barrett, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1964. Belardi 1975: W. Belardi, Il linguaggio nella ilosoia di Aristotele, Roma, Kappa 1975. Bénatouïl, El Murr 2010: Th. Bénatouïl, D. El Murr, L’Académie et les géomètres: usages et limites de la géométrie de Platon à Carnéade, «Philosophie antique», 10, 2010, pp. 41-80. Benson 1988: H.H. Benson, Universals as Sortals in the Categories, «Paciic Philosophical Quarterly», 59, 1988, pp. 282-306. Berti 2008: E. Berti, Socrate e la scienza dei contrari secondo Aristotele, «Elenchos», 29, 2008, pp. 303-15. Betegh 2006: G. Betegh, Epicurus’ Argument for Atomism, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 30, 2006, pp. 261-83. Bignone 2007: E. Bignone, L’Aristotele perduto e la formazione ilosoica di Epicuro, Milano, Bompiani 20073 (Firenze, La Nuova Italia 1936). Bluck 1957: R.S. Bluck, Forms as Standards, «Phronesis», 2, 1957, pp. 115-7. Bodéüs 2001: Aristote, Catégories, éd. par R. Bodéüs, Paris, Belles Lettres 2001. Bonazzi 2010: M. Bonazzi, I soisti, Roma, Carocci 2010. Bonitz 1849: H. Bonitz, Commentarius in Aristotelis Metaphysica, Bonn, Hildesheim 1849 (repr. Hildesheim-Zürich-New York, Olms Verlag 1992).
474 Bibliography
Boudon-Millot 2000: Galien. Oeuvres Tome II: Exhortation à l’étude de la médecine. Art médical, éd. par V. Boudon-Millot, Paris, Les Belles Lettres 2000. Boudon-Millot 2003: V. Boudon-Millot, Art, science et conjecture chez Galien, in Galien et la philosophie, éd. par J. Barnes et J. Jouanna, Genève, Fondation Hardt 2003, pp. 269-98 (Discussion at pp. 299-305). Boulogne 2009: Galien: Méthode de traitement, trad. par J. Boulogne, Paris, Gallimard 2009. Brancacci 1990: A. Brancacci, Oikeios logos. La ilosoia del linguaggio di Antistene, Napoli, Bibliopolis 1990. Brancacci 2002a: A. Brancacci, La determinazione dell’eidos nel Menone, «Wiener Studien», 115, 2002, pp. 59-78. Brancacci 2002b: A. Brancacci, Protagoras, l’orthoepeia et la justesse de noms, in Platon source de présocratiques, éd. par A. Brancacci et M. Dixsaut, Paris, Vrin 2002, pp. 169-90. Brisson 2002: L. Brisson, L’approche traditionnelle de Platon par H.F. Cherniss, in New Images of Plato. Dialogues on the Idea of the Good, ed. by G. Reale and S. Scolnicov, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2002, pp. 85-95. Brisson 2005: Porphyre: Sentences, travaux édités sous la responsabilité de L. Brisson, 2 vols., Paris, Vrin 2005. Brittain 2005: Ch. Brittain, Common Sense: Concepts, Deinition and Meaning in and out the Stoa, in Language and Learning, ed. by D. Frede and B. Inwood, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2005, pp. 164-209. Broackes 2009: J. Broackes, Autos kath’ hauton in he Clouds: Was Socrates himself a Defender of Separable Soul and Separate Forms?, «he Classical Quarterly», 59, 2009, pp. 46-59. Brunschwig 1979: J. Brunschwig, La forme, prédicat de la matière?, in Etudes sur la Metaphysique d’Aristote, éd. par P. Aubenque, Paris, Vrin 1979, pp. 131-58. Brunschwig 1988: J. Brunschwig, La théorie stoïcienne du genre suprême et l’ontologie platonicienne, in Matter and Metaphysics, ed. by J. Barnes and M. Mignucci, Napoli, Bibliopolis 1988, pp. 19-127. Brunschiwig 1995a: J. Brunschwig, L’immutabilité du tout, in J. Brunschwig, Etudes sur les philosophies hellénistiques, Paris, PUF 1995, pp. 15-42.
475 Bibliography
Brunschwig 1995b: J. Brunschwig, La théorie stoïcienne du nom propre, in J. Brunschwig, Etudes sur les philosophies hellénistiques, Paris, PUF 1995, pp. 115-40. Burge 1992: T. Burge, Frege on Knowing the hird Realm, in T. Burge, Truth, hought, Reason. Essays on Frege, Oxford-New York, Oxford University Press 2005, pp. 299–316. Burnyeat 1987: M.F. Burnyeat, he Inaugural Address: Wittgenstein and Augustine De Magistro, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», suppl. vol. 61, 1987, pp. 1-24. Burnyeat 1992: M.F. Burnyeat, Utopia and Fantasy. he Practicability of Plato’s Ideally Just City, in Psychoanalysis, Mind and Art, ed. by J. Hopkins and A. Savile, Oxford, Basil Blackwell 1992, pp. 175-92 (repr. in Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul, ed. by G. Fine, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1999, pp. 297-308). Burnyeat 2000: M.F. Burnyeat, Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul, in Mathematics and Necessity, ed. by T. Smiley, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2000, pp. 1–81. Burnyeat 2001: M.F. Burnyeat, A Map of Metaphysics Zeta, Pittsburgh (PA), Mathesis Publications 2001. Burnyeat 2003: M.F. Burnyeat, Apology 30b2-4: Socrates, Money, and the Grammar of γίγνεσθαι, «he Journal of Hellenic Studies», 123, 2003, pp. 1-25. Burnyeat 2005: M.F. Burnyeat On the Source of Burnet’s Construal of Apology 32b2-4: a Correction, «he Journal of Hellenic Studies», 125, 2005, pp. 139-42 Campbell 1990: K. Campbell, Abstract Particulars, Oxford, Basil Blackwell 1990. Cardullo 1993: R.L. Cardullo, Syrianus défenseur de Platon contre Aristote selon le témoignage d’Asclépius, in Contre Platon. Vol 1: Le platonisme dévoilé , éd. par M. Dixaut, Paris, Vrin 1993, pp. 197–214. Castelli 2003: L.M. Castelli, Individuation and Metaphysics Z15, «Documenti e Studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 14, 2003, pp. 1-26. Castelli 2008: L.M. Castelli, τὸ ἓν λέγεται πολλαχῶς. Questioni aristoteliche sui signiicati dell’uno, «Antiquorum Philosophia», 2, 2008, pp. 189-215.
476 Bibliography
Castelli 2010: L.M. Castelli Problems and Paradigms of Unity. Aristotle’s Accounts of the One, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2010. Caston 1998: V. Caston, Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality, «Philosophy and Phenomenological Research», 58, 1998, pp. 249-98. Caston 1999: V. Caston, Something and Nothing: the Stoics on Concepts and Universals, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 17, 1999, pp. 145-213. Cattaneo 1981: E. Cattaneo, Trois homélies pseudo-Chrysostomiennes sur la Pâque comme œuvre d’Apollinaire de Laodicée, Paris, Beauchesne 1981. Caveing 1997: M. Caveing, La constitution du type mathématique de l’idéalité dans la pensée grecque. Vol. 2: La igure et le nombre. Recherches sur les premières mathématiques des Grecs, Lille, Presses du Septentrion 1997. Centrone 2002a: B. Centrone, La critica aristotelica alla dottrina delle idee. L’argomento di Metaisica I, 10, 1058b26-1059a14, in Gigantomachia. Convergenze e divergenze tra Platone e Aristotele, a cura di M. Migliori, Brescia, Morecelliana 2002, pp. 191-203. Centrone 2002b: B. Centrone, Il concetto di holon nella confutazione della dottrina del sogno (heaet. 201d8-206e12) e i suoi rilessi nella dottrina aristotelica della deinizione, in Il Teeteto di Platone: struttura e problematiche, a cura di G. Casertano, Napoli, Lofredo 2002, pp. 139-55. Centrone 2005: B. Centrone, L’eidos come holon in Platone e i suoi rilessi in Aristotele, in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 103-14. Cerami 2003: C. Cerami, Il ruolo e la posizione di 7-9 all’interno del libro Z della Metaisica, «Documenti e studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 14, 2003, pp. 123-58. Chantraine 1961: P. Chantraine, Morphologie historique du grec, Paris, Librairie Klincksiek 1961. Chantraine 1979: P. Chantraine La formation des noms en grec ancien, Paris, Librairie Klincksiek 1979. Chappell 1973: V.C. Chappell, Aristotle on Matter, «he Journal of Philosophy», 70, 1973, pp. 679-96.
477 Bibliography
Charles 2002: D. Charles, Aristotle on Meaning and Essence, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2002. Charlton 1972: W. Charlton, Aristotle and the Principle of Individuation, «Phronesis», 17, 1972, pp. 238-49. Charlton 1994: W. Charlton, Aristotle on Identity, in Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, ed. by h. Scaltsas, D. Charles and M.L. Gill, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1994, pp. 41-53. Chase 2003: Simplicius: On Aristotle’s Categories 1-4, trans. and notes by M. Chase, London-Ithaca (NY), Duckworth-Cornell University Press 2003. Cherniss 1962: H. Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato and the Academy, New York, Russell & Russell INC 1962. Chiaradonna 1996: R. Chiaradonna, L’interpretazione della sostanza aristotelica in Poririo, «Elenchos», 17, 1996, pp. 55-94. Chiaradonna 1998: R. Chiaradonna, Essence et prédication chez Porphyre et Plotin, «Revue des Sciences philosophiques et théologiques», 82, 1998, pp. 577-606. Chiaradonna 2000: R. Chiaradonna, La teoria dell’individuo in Poririo e l’ ἰδίως ποιόν stoico, «Elenchos», 21, 2000, pp. 303-31. Chiaradonna 2002: R. Chiaradonna, Sostanza, movimento, analogia: Plotino critico di Aristotele, Napoli, Bibliopolis 2002. Chiaradonna 2004: R. Chiaradonna, Plotino e la teoria degli universali. Enn. VI 3 [44], 9, in Aristotele e i suoi esegeti neoplatonici, a cura di V. Celluprica e C. D’Ancona, Napoli, Bibliopolis 2004, pp. 1-35. Chiaradonna 2005: R. Chiaradonna, Plotino e la corrente antiaristotelica del platonismo imperiale: analogie e diferenze, in L’eredità platonica. Studi sul platonismo da Arcesilao a Proclo, a cura di M. Bonazzi e V. Celluprica, Napoli, Bibliopolis 2005, pp. 235-74. Chiaradonna 2007a: R. Chiaradonna, Porphyry’s Views on the Immanent Incorporeals, in Studies on Porphyry, ed. by G. Karamanolis and A. Sheppard, London, Institute of Classical Studies 2007, pp. 3549. Chiaradonna 2007b: R. Chiaradonna, Platonismo e teoria della conoscenza stoica tra II e III secolo d. C., in Platonic Stoicism – Stoic Platonism, ed. by M. Bonazzi and Chr. Helmig, Leuven, Leuven University Press 2007, pp. 209-41.
478 Bibliography
Chiaradonna 2007c: R. Chiaradonna, Porphyry and Iamblichus on Universals and Synonymous Predication, «Documenti e studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 18, 2007, pp. 123-40. Chiaradonna 2008: R. Chiaradonna, What is Porphyry’s Isagoge?, «Documenti e studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 19, 2008, pp. 1-30. Chiaradonna 2009a: R. Chiaradonna, Le traité de Galien Sur la démonstration et sa postérité tardo-antique, in Physics and Philosophy of Nature in Greek Neoplatonism, ed. by R. Chiaradonna and F. Trabattoni, Leiden, Brill 2009, pp. 43-77. Chiaradonna 2009b: R. Chiaradonna, Autour d’Eudore. Les débuts de l’exégèse des Catégories dans les Moyen Platonisme, in he Origins of the Platonic System. Platonisms of the Early Empire and their Philosophical Contexts, ed. by M. Bonazzi and J. Opsomer, Leuven, Peeters 2009, pp. 89-111. Chiaradonna 2011a: R. Chiaradonna, Plotino e la scienza dell’essere, in Plato, Aristotle or Both? Dialogues between Platonism and Aristotelianism in Antiquity, ed. by T. Bénatouïl, E. Mai and F. Trabattoni, Hildesheim, Olms 2011, pp. 117-37. Chiaradonna 2011b: R. Chiaradonna, he Universal Generalization Problem and the Epistemic Status of Ancient Medicine: Aristotle and Galen, in Logic and Knowledge, ed. by C. Cellucci, E. Grosholz and E. Ippoliti, Cambridge, Cambridge Scholars Publishing 2011, pp. 151-67. Chiaradonna 2011c: R. Chiaradonna, Interpretazione ilosoica e ricezione del corpus: Il caso di Aristotele (100 a.C.-250 d.C.), «Quaestio», 11, 2011, pp. 83-114. Chiaradonna 2013: R. Chiaradonna, Platonist Approaches to Aristotle: From Antiochus of Aschalon to Eudorus of Alexandria (and Beyond), in Plato, Aristotle and Pythagoras in the irst century BC, ed. by M. Schoield, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 2013, pp. 28-52. Chiaradonna forthcoming: R. Chiaradonna, Galen on What is Persuasive (πιθανόν) and What Approximates to Truth, in Philosophical hemes in Galen, ed. by P. Adamson and J. Wilberding, London, Institute of Classical Studies (forthcoming). Chiaradonna, Rashed 2010: R. Chiaradonna, M. Rashed, Before and Ater the Commentators: An Exercise in Periodization, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 38, 210, pp. 251-97.
479 Bibliography
Chiaradonna, Rashed, Sedley 2013: R. Chiaradonna, M. Rashed, D. Sedley, A Rediscovered Categories Commentary, with an Appendix by N. Tchernetska, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 44, 2013, pp. 129-94. Code 1984: A. Code, he Aporematic Approach to Primary Being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Z, in New Essays on Aristotle, ed. by F.J. Pelletier and J. King-Farlow, «he Canadian Journal of Philosophy», suppl. vol. 10, 1984, pp. 1-20. Code 1986: A. Code, Aristotle: Essence and Accident, in Philosophical Grounds of Rationality, ed. by R.E. Grandy and R. Warner, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1986, pp. 411–39. Cohen 1984: W. Cohen, Aristotle on Individuation, «he Canadian Journal of Philosophy», suppl. vol. 10, 1984, pp. 41-65. Cooper 1997: Plato: Complete Works, ed. by J. M. Cooper, Indianapolis (IN)-Cambridge (MA), Hackett 1997. Cornford 1937: F.M. Cornford, Plato’s Cosmology. he Timaeus of Plato, London, Routledge 1937. Cornford 1939: F.M. Cornford, Plato and Parmenides, London, Routledge 1939. Corradi 2006: M. Corradi, Protagora e l’ὀρθοέπεια nel Cratilo di Platone, in Esegesi letteraria e rilessione sulla lingua nella cultura greca, a cura di G. Arrighetti e M. Tulli, Pisa, Giardini Stampatori 2006, pp. 47-63. Cresswell 1975: M.J. Cresswell, What is Aristotle’s heory of Universals, «Australasian Journal of Philosophy», 53, 1975, pp. 238-47. Crivelli 2004: P. Crivelli, Aristotle on Truth, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2004. Crivelli 2012: P. Crivelli, Plato’s Account of Falsehood: A Study of the Sophist, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012. Cross 2000: R. Cross, Perichoresis, Deiication, and Christological Predication in John of Damascus, «Mediaeval Studies», 57, 2000, pp. 69-124. Cross 2002a: R. Cross, Individual Natures in the Christology of Leontius of Byzantium, «Journal of Early Christian Studies», 10, 2002, pp. 245-65. Cross 2002b: R. Cross, Universals in Gregory of Nyssa, «Vigiliae Christianae», 56, 2002, pp. 372-410.
480 Bibliography
Dalmais 1952: I.-H. Dalmais, La théorie des “logoi” des créatures chez saint Maxime le Confesseur, «Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques», 36, 1952, pp. 244–9. Dancy 1975: R.M. Dancy, On Some of Aristotle’s First houghts about Substances, «he Philosophical Review», 84, 1975, pp. 338-73. Dancy 1978: R. Dancy, On Some of Aristotle’s Second houghts about Substances, «he Philosophical Review», 87, 1978, pp. 372-413. Dancy 2004: R.M. Dancy, Plato’s Introduction of Forms, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2004. Daniélou 1953: J. Daniélou, Akolouthia chez Grégoire de Nysse, «Revue des sciences religieuses», 27, 1953, pp. 219-49. Decleva Caizzi 1996: F. Decleva Caizzi, Lo sfondo ontologico dell’Eutidemo di Platone, in Odoi dizesios. Le vie della ricerca. Studi in onore di Francesco Adorno, a cura di M.S. Funghi, Firenze, Olschki 1996, pp. 161-7. Decleva Caizzi 1999: F. Decleva Caizzi, Prodicus 3T (?), in Corpus dei papiri ilosoici greci e latini (CPF) I***, Firenze, Olschki 1999, pp. 656-62. de Haas, Fleet 2001: Simplicius: On Aristotle’s Categories 5-6, trans. and notes by F.A.J. de Haas and B. Fleet, London-Ithaca (NY), Duckworth-Cornell University Press 2001. Deichgräber 1930: K. Deichgräber, Die griechische Empirikerschule. Sammlung der Fragmente und Darstellung der Lehre, Berlin, Weidmannsche Buchhandlung 1930. Deichgräber 1957: K. Deichgräber, Galen als Erforscher des menschlichen Pulses: ein Beitrag zur Selbstdarstellung des Wissenschatlers (De dignotione pulsuum I 1), «Sitzungsberichte der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaten zu Berlin. Klasse für Sprachen, Literatur und Kunst», 3, 1957. De Libera 1996: A. De Libera, La querelle des universaux de Platon à la in du Moyen Âge, Paris, Seuil 1996. De Libera 1999: A. De Libera, Entre Aristote et Plotin: l’Isagoge de Porphyre et le problème des catégories, in Métaphysiques médiévales: études en honneur d’André de Muralt, éd. par C. Chiesa et L. Freuler, Faculté de héologie Lausanne, Geneva-Lausanne-Nechâtel, 1999, pp. 7-27.
481 Bibliography
Demos 1946: R. Demos, Types of Unity according to Plato and Aristotle, «Philosophical and Phenomenological Research», 6, 1946, pp. 53446. de Riedmatten 1948: H. de Riedmatten, Some Neglected Aspects of Apollinarist Christology, «Dominican Studies», 1, 1948, pp. 239-60. de Riedmatten 1956: H. de Riedmatten, La correspondance entre Basile de Césarée et Apollinaire de Laodicée, «he Journal of heological Studies», 7, 1956, pp. 199-210. de Rijk 2002: L. M. de Rijk, Aristotle: Semantics and Ontology, 2 vols., Leiden, Brill 2002. Deslauriers 1990: M. Deslauriers, Plato and Aristotle on Division and Deinition, «Ancient Philosophy», 10, 1990, pp. 203-19. Deslauriers 2007: M. Deslauriers, Aristotle on Deinition, Leiden, Brill 2007. de Strycker 1955: E. de Strycker, La notion aristotélicienne de separation dans son application aux Idées de Platon, in Autour d’Aristote. Recueil d’études de philosophie ancienne et médievale ofert à monseigneur Auguste Mansion, Louvain, Publications Universitaires de Louvain 1955, pp. 119-39. Devereux 1992: D.T. Devereux, Inherence and Primary Substance in Aristotle’s Categories, «Ancient Philosophy», 12, 1992, pp. 113-31. Devereux 1994: D.T. Devereux, Separation and Immanence in Plato’s heory of Forms, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 12, 1994, pp. 63–90 (repr. in Plato 1. Metaphysics and Epistemology, ed. by G. Fine, Oxford-New York, Oxford University Press 1999, pp. 192-214). de Vries 1969: G.J. de Vries, A Commentary on the Phaedrus of Plato, Amsterdam, Hakkert 1969. d’Hoine 2011: P. d’Hoine, Forms of symbebèkota in the Neoplatonic Commentaries on Plato and Aristotle, in Plato, Aristotle or Both? Dialogues between Platonism and Aristotelianism in Antiquity, ed. by T. Bénatouïl, E. Mai and F. Trabattoni, Hildesheim, Olms 2011, pp. 161-87. Di Lascio 2004: E.V. Di Lascio, hird Man. he Logic of the Sophisms at Arist. SE 22, 178b36-179a10, «Topoi», 23, 2004, pp. 33-59. Dillon 1990: Dexippus: On Aristotle’s Categories, trans. and notes by J. Dillon, London-Ithaca (NY), Duckworth-Cornell University Press 1990.
482 Bibliography
Dillon 1997: J. Dillon, Iamblichus’s Noera heôria of Aristotle’s Categories, «Syllecta Classica», 8, 1997, pp. 65-77. Dorion 2004: L.-A. Dorion, Socrate, Paris, PUF 2004. Dräseke 1902: J. Dräseke, Johannes Scotus Erigena und dessen Gewährsmänner in seinem Werke De divisione naturae libri V, Leipzig, Dieterich 1902. Driscoll 1981: J. Driscoll, J., ΕΙΔΗ in Aristotle’s Earlier and Later heories of Substance, in Studies in Aristotle, ed. by D. O’Meara, Washington DC., he Catholic University of America Press 1981, pp. 129-59. Duke et al. 1995: Platonis Opera. Tomus I, ed. E.A. Duke, W.F. Hicken, W.S.M. Nicoll, D.B. Robinson and J.C.G. Strachan, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1995. Dürlinger 1970: J. Dürlinger, Predication and Inherence in Aristotle’s Categories, «Phronesis», 15, 1970, pp. 179-203. Dyson 2009: H. Dyson, Prolepsis and Ennoia in the Early Stoa, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 2009. Ebbesen 1990: S. Ebbesen, Porphyry’s Legacy to Logic: a Reconstruction, in Aristotle Transformed: the Ancient Commentators and their Inluence, ed. by R. Sorabji, London, Duckworth 1990, pp. 141-71. Else 1936: G.F. Else, he Terminology of Ideas, «Harvard Studies in Classical Philology», 47, 1936, pp.17-55. Engberg-Pedersen 1979: T. Engberg-Pedersen, More on Aristotelian epagogê, «Phronesis», 24, 1979, pp. 301-17. Erismann 2008a: Chr. Erismann, he Trinity, Universals, and Particular Substances: Philoponus and Roscelin, «Traditio», 53, 2008, pp. 277305. Erismann 2008b: Chr. Erismann, L’individualité expliquée par les accidents. Remarques sur la destinée “chrétienne” de Porphyre, in Compléments de substance: études sur les propriétés accidentelles offertes à Alain de Libera, éd. par Chr. Erismann et A. Schniewind, Paris, Vrin 2008, pp. 51-66. Ferrari, Griffith 2000: Plato: he Republic, trans. by T. Griith and notes by G.R.F. Ferrari, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2000. Fine G. 1980: G. Fine, he One over Many, «he Philosophical Review», 89, 1980, pp. 197-240.
483 Bibliography
Fine G. 1984: G. Fine, Separation, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 2, 1984, pp. 31–87. Fine G. 1985: G. Fine, Separation: A Reply to Morrison, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 3, 1985, pp. 159-65. Fine G. 1986: G. Fine, Immanence, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», suppl. vol. 4, 1986, pp. 71-97. Fine G. 1993: G. Fine, On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s heory of Forms, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1993. Fine K. 1994: K. Fine, A Puzzle Concerning Matter and Form, in Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, ed. by h. Scaltsas, D. Charles and M.L. Gill, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1994, pp. 13-40. Fleet 2002: Simplicius: On Aristotle’s Categories 7-8, trans. by B. Fleet, London, Duckworth 2002. Fortuna 2001: S. Fortuna, Il metodo della diagnosi in Galeno (De locis afectis VIII, 1-452 K.), «Elenchos», 22, 2001, pp. 281-304. Fortuna, Orilia 2000: S. Fortuna, F. Orilia, Diagnosi, abduzione e metafora del testo: aspetti storici e metodologici, in Interpretazione e diagnosi. Scienze umane e medicina, a cura di G. Galli, Roma, Istituti Editoriali e Poligraici 2000, pp. 101-21. Fowler 1987: D.H. Fowler, he Mathematics of Plato’s Academy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987. Frede D. 2012: D. Frede, he Endoxon Mystique: What Endoxa Are and What hey Are Not, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 43, 2012, pp. 185-215. Frede D., Inwood 2005: Language and Learning, ed. by D. Frede and B. Inwood, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2005. Frede M. 1967: M. Frede, Prädikation und Existenzaussage: Platons Gebrauch von ‘… ist …’ und ‘… ist nicht …’ im Sophistes, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht 1967. Frede M. 1974: M. Frede 1974, Die Stoische Logik, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht 1974. Frede M. 1978: M. Frede, Individuen bei Aristoteles, «Antike und Abendland», 24, 1978, pp. 16-39 (repr. as Frede M. 1987a). Frede M. 1981: M. Frede, On Galen’s Epistemology, in Galen: Problems and Prospects, ed. by V. Nutton, London, Wellcome Institute for the
484 Bibliography
History of Medicine 1981, pp. 65-86 (repr. in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987, pp. 27898). Frede M. 1982: M. Frede, he Method of the So-Called Methodical School of Medicine, in Science and Speculation, ed. by J. Barnes, J. Brunschwig, M. Burneat and M. Schoield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1982, pp. 1-23 (repr. in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987, pp. 261-78). Frede M. 1985: M. Frede, Introduction, in Galen: hree Treatises on the Nature of Science, trans. by R. Walzer and M. Frede, Indianapolis (IN), Hackett 1985, pp. ix-xxxvi. Frede M. 1987a: M. Frede, Individuals in Aristotle, in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987, pp. 49-71 (originally published as Frede M. 1978). Frede M. 1987b: M. Frede, Substance in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987, pp. 72-80. Frede M. 1987c: M. Frede, he Ancient Empiricists, in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1987, pp. 24360. Frede M. 1990: M. Frede, An Empiricist View of Knowledge: Memorism, in Epistemology, ed. by S. Everson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1990, pp. 225-50. Frede M. 1992: M. Frede, he Sophist on False Statements, in he Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. by R. Kraut, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1992, pp. 397–424. Frede M. 1994a: M. Frede, he Stoic Notion of a lekton, in Language, ed. by S. Everson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1994, pp. 109-28. Frede M. 1994b: M. Frede, he Stoic Notion of a Grammatical Case, «Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies», 39, 1994, pp. 13-24. Frede M. 1997: M. Frede, Der Begrif des Individuums bei den Kirchenvätern, «Jahrbuch für Antike und Christentum», 40, 1997, pp. 38-54. Frede M. 1999: M. Frede, Epilogue, in he Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. by K. Algra, J. Barnes, J. Mansfeld and M. Schoield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1999, pp. 771-97.
485 Bibliography
Frede M. 2011: M. Frede, An Anti-Aristotelian Point of Method in three Rationalist Doctors, in Episteme, etc. Essays in honour of Jonathan Barnes, ed. by B. Morison and K. Ierodiakonou, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2011, pp. 115-37. Frede M., Patzig 1988: M. Frede, G. Patzig, Aristoteles, Metaphysik Ζ, Text, Übersetzung und Kommentar, 2 B.de., München, Beck 1988. Fronterotta 2005a: F. Fronterotta, Corruttibile e incorruttibile. L’argomento di Metaphysica Iota 10 nella critica di Aristotele alla teoria platonica delle idee, in Il libro Iota (X) della Metaisica di Aristotele, a cura di B. Centrone, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005. Fronterotta 2005b: F. Fronterotta, Natura e statuto dell’eidos: Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione accademica, in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 171-89. Gagarin 2002: M. Gagarin, Antiphon the Athenian. Oratory, Law, and Justice in the Age of the Sophists, Austin, University of Texas Press 2002. Gagarin 2008: M. Gagarin, Protagoras et l’art de la parole, «Philosophie antique», 8, 2008, pp. 23-32. Gallop 1975: Plato: Phaedo, trans. and notes by D. Gallop, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1975. Galluzzo 2004: G. Galluzzo, Il signiicato di Metaph. Z 13: una risposta a M.L. Gill, «Elenchos», 25, 2004, pp. 11-40. Galluzzo, Mariani 2006: G. Galluzzo, M. Mariani, Aristotle’s Metaphysics Book Zeta: he Contemporary Debate, Pisa, Edizioni della Normale 2006. García-Ballester 1994: L. García-Ballester, Galen as a Clinician: his Methods in Diagnosis, in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt, II.37.2, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1994, pp. 1636-71. Geach 1956: P.T. Geach, he hird Man Again, «he Philosophical Review», 65, 1956, 72–82. Gerson 2004: L. Gerson, Platonism and the Invention of the Problem of Universals, «Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie», 86, 2004, pp. 233-56. Giannantoni 1994: G. Giannantoni, Socrate nella Metaisica di Aristotele, in Aristotele. Perché la metaisica, a cura di A. Bausola e G. Reale, Milano, Vita e Pensiero 1994, pp. 431-49.
486 Bibliography
Gill 1989: M.L. Gill, Aristotle on Substance. he Paradox of Unity, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 1989. Gill 1994: M.L. Gill, Individuals and Individuation in Aristotle, in Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, ed. by h. Scaltsas, D. Charles and M.L. Gill, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1994, pp. 55-71. Gill 2001: M.L. Gill, Aristotle’s Attack on Universals, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 20, 2001, pp. 235-60. Gill, Ryan 1996: Plato: Parmenides, trans. and notes by M.L. Gill and P. Ryan, Indianapolis (IN), Hackett 1996. Gillespie 1912: C.M. Gillespie, he Use of Εἶδος and Ἰδέα in Hippocrates, «he Classical Quarterly», 6, 1912, pp. 179–203. Glidden 1985: D. Glidden, Epicurean Prolepsis, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 3, 1985, pp. 175-217. Goldschmidt 1972: V. Goldschmidt, ÔΥπάρχειν et ὑφεστάναι dans la philosophie stoïcienne, «Revue des études grecques», 85, 1972, pp. 331-44. Gonzalez 1998: F. Gonzalez, Dialectic and Dialogue. Plato’s Practice of Philosophical Inquiry, Evanston (IL), Northwestern. University Press 1998. Gonzalez 2003: F. Gonzalez, Perché non esiste una “teoria platonica delle idee”, in Platone e la tradizione platonica: Studi di ilosoia antica, a cura di M. Bonazzi e F. Trabattoni, Milano, Cisalpino 2003, pp. 3167. Goodman, Quine 1947: N. Goodman, W.V.O. Quine, Steps Towards a Constructive Nominalism, «he Journal of Symbolic Logic», 12, 1947, pp. 105-22. Granger 1980: H. Granger, A Defence of the Traditional Position Concerning Aristotle’s Non-substantial Particulars, «he Canadian Journal of Philosophy», 10, 1980, pp. 593-606. Granger 1984: H. Granger, Aristotle on Genus and Diferentia, «Journal of the History of Philosophy», 22, 1984, pp. 1-23. Griffin 2012a: M.J. Griffin, What Does Aristotle Categorize?, in he Peripatetic School hrough Alexander of Aphrodisias, ed. by M. Edwards and P. Adamson, «Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies», 55, 2012, pp. 69-118.
487 Bibliography
Griffin 2012b: M.J. Griffin, What Has Aristotelian Dialectic to Ofer a Neoplatonist? A Possible Sample of Iamblichus at Simplicius On the Categories 12,10-13,12, «he International Journal of the Platonic Tradition», 6, 2012, pp. 173-85. Griffin 2013: M.J. Griffin, Which ‘Athenodorus’ Commented on Aristotle’s Categories?, «he Classical Quarterly», 62, 2013, pp. 199-208. Griffin forthcoming: M.J. Griffin, he Reception of Aristotle’s Categories, c.80 BC to AD 220, D.Phil. dissertation, Oxford 2009 (Oxford University Press, forthcoming). Grillmeier 1986: A. Grillmeier, Jesus der Christus im Glauben der Kirche, Bd. 2/1-3, Freiburg-Basel-Wien, Herder 1986-. Griswold 1981: Ch. Griswold, he Ideas and the Criticism of Poetry in Plato’s Republic, Book 10, «Journal of the History of Philosophy», 19, 1981, pp. 135-50. Guthrie 1971: W. Guthrie, he Sophists, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1971. Guyomarc’h 2008: G. Guyomarc’h, Le visage du divin: la forme pure selon Alexandre d’Aphrodise, «Les études philosophiques», 86, 2008, pp. 323-41. Hackforth 1952: Plato’s Phaedrus, trans. and notes by R. Hackforth, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1952. Hadot 1968: P. Hadot, Porphyre et Victorinus, 2 vols., Paris, Institut d’Études Augustiniennes 1968. Hadot 1969: P. Hadot, Vorgeschichte des Begrifes ‘Existenz’: ÔΥπάρχειν bei den Stoikern, «Archiv für Begrifsgeschichte», 13, 1969, pp. 11527. Hadot 1980: P. Hadot, Sur les divers sens du mot pragma dans la tradition philosophique grecque, in Concepts et categories dans la pensée antique, éd. par P. Aubenque, Paris, Vrin 1980, pp. 309-19. Hall 1974: T.S. Hall, Idiosincrasy: Greek Medical Ideas of Uniqueness, «Sudhofs Archiv», 58, 1974, pp. 283-302. Halper 1989: E.C. Halper, One and Many in Aristotle’s Metaphysics: he Central Books, Columbus (OH), Ohio State University Press 1989. Halper 2009: E.C. Halper, One and Many in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Book Alpha-Delta, Las Vegas, Parmenides Publications 2009.
488 Bibliography
Hamlyn 1976: D. Hamlyn, Aristotelian epagogê, «Phronesis», 21, 1976, pp. 167-80. Hahm 1977: D.E. Hahm, he Origins of Stoic Cosmology, Columbus (OH), Ohio State University Press 1977. Hankinson 1988: R.J. Hankinson, Introduction. Science and Certainty: he Central Issues, in Method, Medicine, and Metaphysics: Studies in the Philosophy of Ancient Science, ed. by R.J. Hankinson, «Apeiron», 21, 1988, pp. 1-16. Hankinson 1991: Galen: On the herapeutic Method. Books I and II, trans. and comm. by R.J. Hankinson, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1991. Hankinson 1997: R.J. Hankinson, Natural Criteria and the Transparency of Judgement: Antiochus, Philo and Galen on Epistemological Justiication, in Assent and Argument. Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, ed. by B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld, Leiden, Brill 1997, pp. 161213. Hankinson 2004: R.J. Hankinson, Art and Experience: Greek Philosophy and the Status of Medicine, «Quaestio», 4, 2004, pp. 3-24. Hankinson 2008a: he Cambridge Companion to Galen, ed. by R.J. Hankinson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2008. Hankinson 2008b: R.J. Hankinson, he Man and His Work, in he Cambridge Companion to Galen, ed. by R.J. Hankinson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2008, pp. 1-33. Harte 2002: V. Harte, Plato on Parts and Wholes: the Metaphysics of Structure, Oxford-New York, Oxford University Press 2002. Harte 2008: V. Harte, Plato’s Metaphysics, in he Oxford Handbook of Plato, ed. by G. Fine, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2008, pp. 191216. Harte 2009: V. Harte, What’s a Particular and what Makes it so? Some houghts, mainly about Aristotle, in Particulars in Greek Philosophy, ed. by R.W. Sharples, Leiden, Brill 2009, pp. 97-125. Havrda 2011: M. Havrda, Galenus Christianus? he Doctrine of Demonstration in Stromata VIII and the Question of its Source, «Vigiliae Christianae», 75, 2011, pp. 343-75. Heinaman 1981: R. Heinaman, Non-substantial Individuals in the Categories, «Phronesis», 26, 1981, pp. 295–307.
489 Bibliography
Helmig 2010: Chr. Helmig, Proclus’ Criticism of Aristotle’s heory of Abstraction and Concept Formation in Analytica Posteriora II 19, in Interpreting Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics in Late Antiquity and Beyond, ed. by F.A.J. de Haas, M. Leunissen and M. Martijn, Leiden, Brill 2010, pp. 27-54. Helmig 2012: Chr. Helmig, Forms and Concepts: Concept Formation in the Platonic Tradition, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 2012. Hintikka 1980: J. Hintikka, Aristotelian Induction, «Revue internationale de philosophie», 34, 1980, pp. 422-40. Hirsch 1997: E. Hirsch, Dividing Reality, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1997. Hoffmann 1987: Ph. Hoffmann, Catégories et langage selon Simplicius – la question du skopos du traité aristotélicien des Catégories, in Simplicius: sa vie, son seuvre, sa survie, éd. par I. Hadot, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1987. Hoffman, Rosenkrantz 2005: J. Hoffman, J.S. Rosenkrantz, Platonist heories of Universals, in he Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, ed. by M.J. Loux and D. Zimmerman, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2005, pp. 46-73. Hübner 1974: R.M. Hübner, Die Einheit des Leibes Christi bei Gregor von Nyssa. Untersuchungen zum Ursprung der ‘physischen’ Erlösungslehre, Leiden, Brill 1974. Hussey 2004: E. Hussey, On Generation and Corruption I,8, in Aristotle: On Generation and Corruption, Book I: Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. by F.A.J. de Haas and J. Mansfeld, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2004, pp. 243-66. Hutchinson 1988: D.S. Hutchinson, Doctrines of the Mean and the Debate concerning Skills in Fourth-Century Medicine, Rhetoric, and Ethics, in Method, Medicine, and Metaphysics: Studies in the Philosophy of Ancient Science, ed. by R.J. Hankinson, «Apeiron», 21, 1988, pp. 17-52. Ierodiakonou 1995: K. Ierodiakonou, Alexander of Aphrodisias on Medicine as a Stochastic Art, in Ancient Medicine in its Socio-Cultural Context, ed. by Ph.J. van der Eijk, H.F.J. Horstamshof and P.H. Schrijvers, 2, Amsterdam-Atlanta (GA), Rodopi 1995, pp. 473-86. Inwood 1981: B. Inwood, he Origin of Epicurus’ Concept of Void, «Classical Philology», 26, 1981, pp. 273-85.
490 Bibliography
Irwin 1988: T. Irwin, Aristotle’s First Principles, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1988. Isnardi Parente 1981: M. Isnardi Parente, Le Peri ideôn d’Aristote: Platon ou Xénocrate?, «Phronesis», 26, 1981, pp. 135-52. Isnardi Parente 2005: M. Isnardi Parente, Il dibattito sugli EIDH nell’Accademia antica, in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 161-70. Jackson 1881-6: H. Jackson, Plato’s Later heory of Ideas, «he Journal of Philology», 10, 11, 13, 14, 15, 1881-1886. Jackson 1882: H. Jackson, On Plato’s Republic VI 509d f., «he Journal of Philology», 10, 1882, pp. 132-50. Jaeger 1957: W. Jaeger, Aristotle’s Use of Medicine as a Model of Method in his Ethics, «he Journal of Hellenic Studies», 77, 1957, pp. 54-61. Jeauneau 1982: E. Jeauneau, Jean l’Erigène et les Ambigua ad Iohannem de Maxime le Confesseur, in Maximus Confessor, éd. par F. Heinzer et Chr. Schönborn, Fribourg, Editions Universitaires Fribourg Suisse 1982, pp. 343–64. Johnston, Horsley 2011: Galen: Method of Medicine, 3 vols., ed. with trans. and notes by I. Johnston and G.H.R. Horsley, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press 2011. Jones 1972: B. Jones, Individuals in Aristotle’s Categories, «Phronesis», 17, 1972, pp. 107-23. Jouanna 1990: Hippocrate II.1: De l’ancienne médecine, éd. par J. Jouanna, Paris, Les Belles Lettres 1990. Kahn 1973a: Ch.H. Kahn, he Verb “Be” in Ancient Greek, Dordrecht, Reidel 1973. Kahn 1973b: Ch.H. Kahn, Language and Ontology in the Cratylus, in Exegesis and Argument, ed. by E. Lee, A. Mourelatos and R. Rorty, Assen, Van Gorcum 1973, pp. 152-76. Kahn 1981: Ch.H. Kahn, Some Philosophical Uses of “To Be” in Plato, «Phronesis», 26, 1981, pp. 105–34. Kahn 1996: Ch.H. Kahn, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1996. Kalbfleisch 1907: Simplicii in Aristotelis Categorias commentarium, ed. C. Kalbleisch, Berlin, Reimer 1907.
491 Bibliography
Karamanolis 2006: G. Karamanolis, Plato and Aristotle in Agreement? Platonists on Aristotle from Antiochus to Porphyry, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2006. Karamanolis 2009: G. Karamanolis, Plotinus on Quality and Immanent Form, in Physics and Philosophy of Nature in Greek Neoplatonism, ed. by R. Chiaradonna and F. Trabattoni, Leiden, Brill 2009, pp. 79-100. Kechagia 2010: E. Kechagia, Rethinking a Professional Rivalry: Early Epicureans Against the Stoa, «he Classical Quarterly», 60, 2010, pp. 132-55. Kenny 2004: A. Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy. Vol. 1: Ancient Philosophy, Oxford-New York, Oxford University Press 2004. Keyt 1971: D. Keyt, he Mad Cratsman of the Timaeus, «he Philosophical Review», 80, 1971, pp. 230-5. Klima 1993: G. Klima, he Changing Role of Entia Rationis in Medieval Semantics and Ontology: A Comparison Study with Reconstruction, «Synthese», 96, 1993, pp. 25-58. Klima 1999: G. Klima, Ockham’s Semantics and Metaphysics of the Categories, in he Cambridge Companion to Ockham, ed. by V. Spade, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1999, pp. 118-42. Knorr 1975: W.R. Knorr, he Evolution of the Euclidean Elements, Dordrecht, Reidel 1975. Koch 1900: H. Koch, Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita in seinen Beziehungen zum Neuplatonismus und Mysterienwesen, Mainz, Verlag von Franz Kirchheim 1900. Krämer 1973: H.J. Krämer, Aristoteles und die akademische Eidoslehre. Zur Geschichte des Universalienproblems in Platonismus, «Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie», 55, 1973, pp. 118-90. Krausmüller 2006: D. Krausmüller, Divine Self-Invention. Leontius of Jerusalem’s Reinterpretation of the Patristic Model of the Christian God, «he Journal of heological Studies», 57, 2006, pp. 526-45. Kretzmann 1974: N. Kretzmann, Aristotle on Spoken Sounds Signiicant by Convention, in Ancient Logic and its Modern Interpretations, ed. by J. Corcoran, Dordrecht, Reidel 1974, pp. 3-21. Kung 1981: J. Kung, Aristotle on heses, Suches, and the hird Man Argument, «Phronesis», 26, 1981, pp. 207-47.
492 Bibliography
Kühner, Gerth 1904: R. Kühner, B. Gerth, Ausführliche Grammatik der Griechischen Sprache: Satzlehre, 2 vols., Hannover-Leipzig, Hahn 19043. Kupreeva 2003: I. Kupreeva, Qualities and Bodies: Alexander against the Stoics, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 25, 2003, p. 297-344. Kupreeva 2010: I. Kupreeva, Alexander of Aphrodisias on Form, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 38, 2010, pp. 211-49. Lacey 1959: A.R. Lacey, Plato’s Sophist and the Forms, «he Classical Quarterly», 9, 1959, pp. 43–52. Lang 2001: U. Lang, John Philoponus and the Controversies over Chalcedon in the Sixth Century, Leuven, Peeters 2001. Larchet 1996: J.-C. Larchet, La divinisation de l’homme selon Saint Maxime le Confesseur, Paris, Editions du Cerf 1996. Lear 1980: J. Lear, Aristotle and Logical heory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1980. Lear 1982: J. Lear, Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics, «he Philosophical Review», 101, 1982, pp. 161-92. Lebon 1951: J. Lebon, La christologie du monophysisme syrien in Das Konzil von Chalkedon, hrsg. v. A. Grillmeier und H. Bacht, 3 B.de., Würzburg, Echter Verlag 1951, 1, pp. 425-580. Lefebvre 2008: D. Lefebvre, Le commentaire d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise à Métaphysique, Α, 9, 990 a 34-b8. Sur le nombre et l’objet des idées, «Les études philosophiques», 86, 2008, pp. 305-22. Leroux 2002: Platon: La République, trad. et notes par G. Leroux, Flammarion, Paris 2002. Lewis 1986: D. Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford, Blackwell 1986. Lewis 1991: F. Lewis, Substance and Predication in Aristotle, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1991. Lloyd 1955: A.C. Lloyd, Aristotelian Logic and Neoplatonic Logic, «Phronesis», 1, 1955, pp. 58-79; 146-60. Lloyd 1970: A.C. Lloyd, Aristotle’s Principle of Individuation, «Mind», 79, 1970, pp. 519-29. Lloyd 1981: A.C. Lloyd, Form and Universal in Aristotle, Liverpool, Cairns 1981.
493 Bibliography
Lloyd 1990: A.C. Lloyd, he Anatomy of Neoplatonism, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1990. Long 1986: A.A. Long, Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Berkeley (CA), University of California Press, 1986². Loriaux 1969–75: Le Phédon de Platon, trad. et comm. par R. Loriaux, 2 vols., Namur-Gembloux, Presses universitaires de Namur-Duculot 1969-75. Loux 1979: M.J. Loux, Form, Species, and Predication in Metaphysics Ζ, Η, and Θ, «Mind», 88, 1979, pp. 1-23. Loux 1991: M.J. Loux, Primary Ousia. An Essay on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Z and H, Ithaca (NY)-London, Cornell University Press 1991. Loux 2006a: M.J. Loux, Metaphysics, London-New York, Routledge 20063. Loux 2006b: M.J. Loux, Aristotle’s Constituent Ontology, «Oxford Studies in Metaphysics», 2, 2006, pp. 207-50. Loux 2007: M.J. Loux, Perspectives on the Problem of Universals, «Documenti e studi sulla tradizione ilosoica medievale», 18, 2007, pp. 601-22. Loux 2009: M.J. Loux, Aristotle on Universals, in A Companion to Aristotle, ed. by G. Anagnostopoulos, Oxford, Wiley-Blackwell 2009, pp. 18696. Luna 2001: Simplicius, Commentaire sur les Catégories d’Aristote. Chapitres 2-4, trad. par Ph. Hofmann et comm. par C. Luna, Paris, Les Belles Lettres 2001. Mabbott 1926: J.D. Mabbott, Aristotle and the ΧΩΡΙΣΜΟΣ of Plato, «he Classical Quarterly», 20, 1926, pp. 72-9. Machuca 2008: D. Machuca, Sextus Empiricus: His Outlook, Works, and Legacy, «Freiburger Zeitschrit für Philosophie und heologie», 55, 2008, pp. 28-63. Magee 1998: Anicii Manlii Severini Boethii De divisione liber, ed. and comm. by J. Magee, Leiden, Brill 1998. Mair 1918: A.W. Mair, General Relative Clauses in Greek, «he Classical Review», 32, 1918, pp. 169-70. Malcolm 1993: J. Malcolm, On the Endangered Species of the Metaphysics, «Ancient Philosophy», 13, 1993, pp. 79-93.
494 Bibliography
Malcolm 1996: J. Malcolm, On the Duality of Eidos in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie», 78, 1996, pp. 1-10. Mann 2000: W.R. Mann, he Discovery of hings, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 2000. Mansfeld 1994: J. Mansfeld, Prolegomena: Questions to be Settled before the Study of an Author or a Text, Leiden, Brill 1994. Mansfeld 2008: J. Mansfeld, Aristotle on Socrates’ Contribution to Philosophy, in Anthropine sophia. Studi di ilologia e storiograia ilosoica in memoria di Gabriele Giannantoni, a cura di F. Alesse, F. Aronadio, M.C. Dalino, L. Simeoni ed E. Spinelli, Napoli 2008, pp. 337-49. Mariani 1997: M. Mariani, Aristotele e la diferenza, in Logica e Teologia. Studi in onore di Vittorio Sainati, a cura di A. Fabris, G. Fioravanti e E. Moriconi, Pisa, ETS 1997, pp. 3-21. Mariani 2003: M. Mariani, Frege: identità e reiicazione dei modi di determinazione, in La ilosoia di Gottlob Frege, a cura di N. Vassallo, Milano, Franco Angeli 2003, pp. 129-44. Mariani 2005: M. Mariani, Aristotele e il «Terzo Uomo», in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 191-209. Martijn 2010: M. Martijn, Proclus on Nature. Philosophy of Nature and its Methods in Proclus’ Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Leiden, Brill 2010. Mattern 2008: S.P. Mattern, Galen and the Rhetoric of Healing, Baltimore (MD), he John Hopkins University Press 2008. Matthen 1983: M. Matthen, Greek Ontology and the “Is” of Truth, «Phronesis», 28, 1983, pp. 113-35. Matthews 1982: G.B. Matthews, Accidental Unities, in Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy Presented to G.E.L. Owen, ed. by M. Schoield and M.C. Nussbaum, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1982, pp. 223-40. Matthews 1989: G.B. Matthews, he Enigma of Categories 1a20 f. and Why it Matters, «Apeiron», 12, 1989, pp. 91-104. Matthews, Cohen 1968: G.B. Matthews, S.M. Cohen, he One and the Many, «Review of Metaphysics», 21, 1968, pp. 630-55.
495 Bibliography
McCabe 1994: M.M. McCabe, Plato’s Individuals, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 1994. McGuckin 2004: J. McGuckin, Saint Cyril of Alexandria and the Christological Controversy, Crestwood (NY), St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press 2004. Meinwald 1991: C. Meinwald, Plato’s Parmenides, Oxford-New York, Oxford University Press 1991. Meinwald 1992: C. Meinwald, Good-Bye to the hird Man, in he Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. by R. Kraut, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1992, pp. 365–96. Menn 2010: S. Menn, Simplicius on the heaetetus (In Physica 17.38-18.23 Diels), «Phronesis», 55, 2010, pp. 255-70. Mignucci 1986: M. Mignucci, Aristotle’s Deinitions of Relatives in Cat. 7, «Phronesis», 31, 1986, pp. 101–26. Mignucci 2000: M. Mignucci, Parts, Quantiication and Aristotelian Predication, «he Monist», 83, 2000, pp. 3-21. Minio-Paluello 1949: Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber De Interpretatione, ed. L. Minio-Paluello, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1949. Modrak 1979: D.K. Modrak, Forms, Types, and Tokens in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «Journal of the History of Philosophy» 17, 1979, pp. 371-81. Modrak 1985: D.K. Modrak, Forms and Compounds, in How hings are. Studies in the Predication and the History of Philosophy, ed. by J. Bogen and J. McGuire, Dordrecht, Reidel 1985, pp. 85-9. Moore, Stout, Hicks 1923: G.E. Moore, G.F. Stout, G.D. Hicks, Are the Characteristics of Particular hings Universal or Particular?, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», suppl. vol. 3, 1923, pp. 95128. Moore, Wilson 1893: Select Writings and Letters of Gregory, Bishop of Nyssa, ed. and trans. by W. Moore and H.-A. Wilson. Nicene and PostNicene Fathers, s. 2, 5, New York-Oxford-London, Parker & Co. 1893. Moraux 1973: P. Moraux, Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen. Bd. 1: Die Renaissance des Aristotelismus im 1. Jahrhundert v. Chr., Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1973. Moraux 1984: P. Moraux, Der Aristotelismus bei den Grìechen von Andronikos bis Alexander von Aphrodisias. Bd. 2: Der Aristotelismus im I. und II. Jh. n. Chr., Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1984.
496 Bibliography
Morrison 1985a: D. Morrison, Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 3, 1985, pp. 125-57. Morrison 1985b: D. Morrison, Separation: A Reply to Fine, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 3, 1985, pp. 167-73. Mourelatos 2006: A. Mourelatos, he Concept of the Universal in some later Pre-Platonic Cosmologists, in A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. by M.L. Gill and P. Pellegrin, Oxford, Blackwell 2006, pp. 56-75. Müller 1895: I. von Müller, Über Galens Werk vom Wissenschatlichen Beweis, «Abh. Bayer. Ak. d. Wiss. München», 20, 1895, pp. 403-78. Mueller 1981: I. Mueller, Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid’s Elements, Cambridge (MA)-London, MIT Press 1981. Mueller 1990: I. Mueller, Aristotle’s Doctrine of Abstraction in the Commentators, in Aristotle Transformed. he Ancient Commentators and heir Inluence, ed. by R. Sorabji, London-Ithaca (NY), Duckworth-Cornell University Press 1990, pp. 463-80. Natorp 1921: P. Natorp, Platos Ideenlehere. Eine Einführung in den Idealismus, Meiner, Leipzig 19212. Nehamas 1975: A. Nehamas, Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World, in A. Nehamas, Virtues of Authenticity, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 1999, pp. 138–58. Nehamas 1999: A. Nehamas, Virtues of Authenticity, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 1999. Nussbaum 1986: M. Nussbaum, he Fragility of Goodness, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1986. Oliver 1996: A. Oliver, he Metaphysics of Properties, «Mind», 105, 1996, pp. 1-80. Owen 1957: G.E.L. Owen, A Proof in the Peri ideôn, «he Journal of Hellenic Studies», 77, 1957 pp. 103-10 (repr. in Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, ed. by R.E. Allen, London, Routledge 1965, pp. 293-312 and in G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, London-New York, Duckworth 1986, pp. 165-79). Owen 1965: G.E.L. Owen, Inherence, «Phronesis», 10, 1965, pp. 97-105.
497 Bibliography
Owen 1966a: G.E.L. Owen, Plato and Parmenides on the Timeless Present, in G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, London-New York, Duckworth 1986, pp. 27–44. Owen 1966b: G.E.L. Owen, he Platonism of Aristotle, «Proceedings of the British Academy», 51, 1966, pp. 125-50 (repr. in G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, LondonNew York, Duckworth 1986, pp. 200-20). Owen 1968: G.E.L. Owen, Dialectic and Eristic in the Treatment of Forms, in G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, London-New York, Duckworth 1986, pp. 221–38. Owen 1978-9: G.E.L. Owen, Particular and General, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», n.s. 79, 1978-79, pp. 1-21. Pacius 1597: Aristotelis Stagiritae Peripateticorum Principis Organum, ed. I. Pacius, Francofurti 15972. Page 1985: C. Page, Predicating Forms of Matter in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «Review of Metaphysics», 39, 1985, pp. 57-82. Palmer 2007: J. Palmer, review of S.C. Rickless, Plato’s Forms in Transition: A Reading of the Parmenides, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2007, «Notre Dame Philosophical Review», 20.11.2007 (May 2013; last accessed September 2013). Paparazzo 2011: E. Paparazzo, Why Five Worlds? Plato’s Timaeus 55CD, «Apeiron», 44, 2011, pp. 147-62. Parenti 1994: A. Parenti, Su alcuni composti greci con αὐτο-, in Studi in onore di Carlo Alberto Mastrelli, a cura di G. Del Lungo Camiciotti, F. Granucci, M.P. Marchese e R. Stefanelli, Padova, Edizione Unipress 1994, pp. 187–200. Parry 1979: R.D. Parry, he Unique World of the Timaeus, «Journal of the History of Philosophy», 17, 1979, pp. 1-10. Parry 1991: R.D. Parry, he Intelligible World-Animal in Plato’s Timaeus, «Journal of the History of Philosophy», 29, 1991, pp. 13-32. Patterson 1981: R. Patterson, he Unique Worlds of the Timaeus, «Phoenix», 35, 1981, pp. 105-19. Penner 1987: T. Penner, he Ascent from Nominalism. Some Existence Arguments in Plato’s Middle Dialogues, Dordrecht, Reidel 1987.
498 Bibliography
Perrin 1984: Plutarch’s Lives. Vol. 3: Pericles and Fabius Maximus, Nicias and Crassus, ed. with trans. and notes by B. Perrin, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press 1984. Pradeau 2005: J.-F. Pradeau, Le forme e le realtà intelligibili. L’uso platonico del termine EIDOS, in Eidos-Idea. Platone, Aristotele e la tradizione platonica, a cura di F. Fronterotta e W. Leszl, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2005, pp. 75-89. Prior 1985: W.J. Prior, Unity and Development in Plato’s Metaphysics, London-Sydney, Croom Helm 1985. Quine 1948: W.V.O. Quine, On What here Is, «Review of Metaphysics», 2, 1948, pp. 21-38 (repr. in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press 1953). Quine 1960: W. V. O. Quine, Word and Object, Cambridge (MA), MIT Press 1960. Quine 1987: W.V.O. Quine, Quiddities: An Intermittent Philosophical Dictionary, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press 1987. Rashed 2004: M. Rashed, Priorité de l’εἶδος ou du γένος entre Andronicos et Alexandre. Vestiges arabes et grecs inédits, «Arabic Sciences and Philosophy», 14, 2004, pp. 9-63. Rashed 2005: Aristote: De la génération et la corruption, éd. par M. Rashed etc., Paris, Les Belles Lettres 2005. Rashed 2007: M. Rashed, Essentialisme: Alexandre d’Aphrodise entre logique, physique et cosmologie, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 2007. Rashed 2011: M. Rashed, Alexandre d’Aphrodise. Commentaire perdu à la Physique d’Aristote (Livres IV- VIII): les scholies byzantines, BerlinNew York, De Gruyter 2011. Rashed 2013a: M. Rashed, Boethus’ Aristotelian Ontology, in Plato, Aristotle and Pythagoras in the irst century BC, ed. by M. Schoield, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 2013, pp. 53-77. Rashed 2013b: M. Rashed, Platon et les mathématiques, in Lectures de Platon, éd par A. Castel-Bouchouchi, M. Dixsaut et G. Kevorkian, Paris, Ellipses, pp. 215-31. Raven 1923: Ch.E. Raven, Apollinarianism. An Essay on the Christology of the Early Church, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1923. Regis 1976: E. Regis, Aristotle’s ‘Principle of Individuation’, «Phronesis», 21, 1976, pp. 157-66.
499 Bibliography
Reinhardt 2007: T. Reinhardt, Andronicus of Rhodes and Boethus of Sidon on Aristotle’s Categories, in Greek and Roman Philosophy 100 BC-200 AD, ed. by R.W. Sharples and R. Sorabji, London, Institute of Classical Studies 2007, pp. 513-29. Reinhardt 2011: T. Reinhardt, Galen on Unsayable Properties, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 40, 2011, pp. 297-317. Remes 2005: P. Remes, Plotinus on the Unity and Identity of Changing Particulars, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 28, 2005, pp. 273-301. Rescher, Marmura 1965: N. Rescher, M.E. Marmura, he Refutation by Alexander of Aphrodisias of Galen’s Treatise on the heory of Motion, Islamabad, Islamic Research Institute 1965. Richard 1944: M. Richard, Léonce de Jérusalem et Léonce de Byzance, «Mèlanges de science religieuse», 1, 1944, pp. 35-88. Robin 1908: L. Robin, La théorie platonicienne des idées et des nombres d’après Aristote, Paris, Alcan 1908. van Roey, Allen 1994: Monophysite Texts of the Sixth Century, ed. by A. van Roey and P. Allen, Leuven, Peeters 1994. Ross 1924: Aristotle’s Metaphysics, ed. and comm. by W.D. Ross, 2 vols., Oxford, Clarendon Press 1924. Ross 1949: Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics, ed. and comm. by W.D. Ross, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1949. Ross 1951: W.D. Ross, Plato’s heory of Ideas, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1951. Ross 1958: Aristotelis Topica et Sophistici Elenchi, ed. W.D. Ross, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1958. Rowe 1993: Plato: Phaedo, ed. and notes by Chr.J. Rowe, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1993. Rowe 1995: Plato: Statesman, trans. and notes by Chr.J. Rowe, Warminster, Aris & Phillips 1995. Runia, Share 2008: Proclus: Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Volume II. Book 2: Proclus on the Causes of the Cosmos and its Creation, trans. and notes by D.T. Runia and M. Share, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2008. Russell 1903: B. Russell, he Principles of Mathematics. Vol. 1, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1903.
500 Bibliography
Russell 1912: B. Russell, he World of Universals, in B. Russell, he Problems of Philosophy, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1912, pp. 91-100. Russell 1946: B. Russell, History of Western Philosophy, London, Allen & Unwin 1946. Ryle 1939: G. Ryle, Plato’s Parmenides II, «Mind», 38, 1939, pp. 302-25. Sacksteder 1986: W. Sacksteder, Some Words Aristotle Never Uses: Attributes, Essences and Universals, «New Scholasticism», 60, 1986, pp. 427-53. Sainati 1968: V. Sainati, Storia dell’Organon aristotelico I, Firenze, Le Monnier 1968 (repr. Pisa, ETS 2011). Sandbach 1971: F.H. Sandbach, Ennoia and Prolepsis in the Stoic heory of Knowledge, in Problems in Stoicism, ed. by A.A. Long, London, Athlone Press 1971, pp. 22-37. Sassi 2005: M.M. Sassi, he Science of Man in Ancient Greece, Chicago, University of Chicago Press 2005. Scaltsas 1980-1: Th. Scaltsas, Numerical versus Qualitative Identity of Properties in Aristotle’s Categories, «Filosoia», 10-11, 1980-81, pp. 328-45. Schaff, Wace 1895: Basil. Letters and Select Works, ed. by Ph. Schaf and H. Wace, Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, s. 2, 8, Edinburgh, Clark 1895. Schiefsky 2005: Hippocrates: On Ancient Medicine, trans. and comm. by M. Schiefsky, Leiden-Boston, Brill 2005. Scott 2006: D. Scott, Plato’s Meno, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2006. Sedley 1973: D. Sedley, Epicurus, On Nature, Book XXVIII, «Cronache ercolanesi», 3, 1973, pp. 5-83. Sedley 1980: D. Sedley, he Protagonists, in Doubt and Dogmatism. Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, ed. by M. Schoield, M. Burnyeat and J. Barnes, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1980, pp. 1-19. Sedley 1982: D. Sedley, Two Conceptions of Vacuum, «Phronesis», 27, 1982, pp. 175-93. Sedley 1985: D. Sedley, he Stoic heory of Universals, «he Southern Journal of Philosophy», suppl. vol. 23, 1985, pp. 87-92.
501 Bibliography
Sedley 1989: D. Sedley, Epicurus on the Common Sensibles, in he Criteron of Truth, ed. by P. Huby and G. Neal, Liverpool, Liverpool University Press 1989, pp. 123-34. Sedley 1998: D. Sedley, Platonic Causes, «Phronesis», 43, 1998, pp. 11432. Sedley 2003: D. Sedley, Plato’s Cratylus, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2003. Sedley 2005: D. Sedley, Stoic Metaphysics at Rome, in Metaphysics, Soul and Ethics in Ancient hought, ed. by R. Salles, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2005, pp. 117-42. Sedley 2006a: D. Sedley, Plato on Language, in A Companion to Plato, ed. by H. Benson, Oxford, Blackwell 2006, pp. 214-27. Sedley 2006b: D. Sedley, Form-Particular Resemblance in Plato’s Phaedo, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», 106, 2006, pp. 311-27. Sedley 2007: D. Sedley, Creationism and its Critics in Antiquity, Berkeley (CA)-Los Angeles (CA)-London, University of California Press 2007. Sedley 2013: D. Sedley, Plato’s heory of Change at Phaedo 70-1, in Presocratics and Plato: A Festschrit at Delphi in Honor of Charles H. Kahn, ed. by R. Patterson, V. Karasmanis and A. Hermann, Las Vegas (NV)-Zurich-Athens, Parmenides Publishing 2013, pp. 181-97. Sellars 1955: W. Sellars, Vlastos and the hird Man, «he Philosophical Review», 64, 1955, pp. 405-37. Share 1994: Arethas of Caesarea’s Scholia on Porphyry’s Isagoge and Aristotle’s Categories, ed. by M. Share, Athens-Paris-Brussels, Ousia 1994. Sharma 2006: R. Sharma, On Republic 596a, «Apeiron», 39, 2006, pp. 27-32. Sharples 1992: Alexander of Aphrodisias: Quaestiones 1.1-2.15, trans. and notes by R.W. Sharples, London, Duckworth 1992. Sharples 1996: R. Sharples, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics: An Introduction to Hellenistic Philosophy, London, Routledge 1996. Sharples 2005: R.W. Sharples, Alexander of Aphrodisias on Universals: Two Problematic Texts, «Phronesis», 50, 2005, pp. 43-55. Sharples 2008a: R.W. Sharples, Habent Sua Fata Libelli: Aristotle’s Categories in the First Century BC, «Acta Antiqua Hungarica», 48, 2008, pp. 273-87.
502 Bibliography
Sharples 2008b: Alexander Aphrodisiensis: De anima libri mantissa, ed. and comm. by R.W. Sharples, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 2008. Sharples 2010: R. Sharples, Peripatetic Philosophy, 200 BC to AD 200: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2010. Simons 1994: P. Simons, Particulars in Particular Clothing: hree Trope heories of Substance, «Philosophy and Phenomenological Research», 54, 1994, pp. 553-75. Sirkel 2011: R. Sirkel, Alexander of Aphrodisias’s Account of Universals and its Problems, «Journal of the History of Philosophy», 49, pp. 297314. Slings 2003: Platonis Rempublicam ed. S.R. Slings, Oxford, Clarendon Press 2003. Smith 1917: J.A. Smith, General Relative Clauses in Greek, «he Classical Review», 31, 1917, pp. 69-71. Sonnenschein 1918: E.A. Sonnenschein, he Indicative in Relative Clauses, «he Classical Review», 32, 1918, pp. 68-9. Sorabji 2004: R. Sorabji, he Philosophy of the Commentators 200-600 AD. A Sourcebook. Vol. 3: Logic and Metaphysics, London, Duckworth 2004. Spellman 1995: L. Spellman, Substance and Separation in Aristotle, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1995. Stavru 2008: A. Stavru, Aporia o deinizione? Il ti esti negli scritti socratici di Senofonte, in Socratica 2005, a cura di L. Rossetti e A. Stavru, Bari, Levante Editori 2008, pp. 131-58. Stead 1977: Chr. Stead, Divine Substance, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1977. Steel 2009: C. Steel, he Divine Earth: Proclus On Timaeus 40bc, in Physics and Philosophy of Nature in Greek Neoplatonism, ed. by R. Chiaradonna and F. Trabattoni, Leiden, Brill 2009, pp. 259-82. Stout 1921-2: G.F. Stout, he Nature of Universals and Propositions, «Proceedings of the British Academy», 10, 1921-22 (repr. in he Problem of Universals, ed. by C. Landesman, New York, Basic Books 1971, pp. 154–66). Strange 1992: Porphyry: On Aristotle’s Categories, trans. and notes by S.K. Strange, London, Duckworth 1992.
503 Bibliography
Strobel 2007: B. Strobel, “Dieses” und “So etwas”. Zur ontologischen Klassiication platonischer Formen, Göttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprect 2007. Szabó 2005: Z. Szabó, Nominalism, in he Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, ed. by M.J. Loux and D. Zimmerman, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2005, pp. 11-45. Tarán 1981: L. Tarán, Review of P. Moraux, Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen. Bd. 1: Die Renaissance des Aristotelismus im 1. Jahrhundert v. Chr., Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1973, «Gnomon», 83, 1981, pp. 721-50. Tarrant 1974: H.A.S. Tarrant, Speusippus’ Ontological Classiication, «Phronesis», 19, 1974, pp. 130-45. Taylor 1928: A.E. Taylor, A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1928. Taylor 1934: A.E. Taylor, Forms and Numbers: A Study in Platonic Metaphysics, «Mind», 35, 1926, pp. 419-40 and 36, 1927 pp. 12-33 (repr. in A.E. Taylor, Philosophical Studies, London, Macmillan 1934, pp. 91-150). Taylor 1960: A.E. Taylor, Plato. he Man and His Work, London, Methenn 1960. Tecusan 2004: M. Tecusan, he Fragments of the Methodists: Methodism outside Soranus. Vol 1: Text and Translation, Leiden, Brill 2004. Toepliz 1929-31: O. Toeplitz, Das Verhältnis von Mathematik und Ideenlehre bei Plato, «Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Mathematik», 1, 1929-31, pp. 3-33. Törönen 2007: M. Törönen, Union and Distinction in the hought of St Maximus the Confessor, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2007. Trabattoni 1998: F. Trabattoni, Platone, Roma, Carocci 1998. Twardowski 1894: K. Twardowski, Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellung: eine psychologische Untersuchung, Wien, Hölder 1894 (repr. Munchen-Wien, Philosophia 1982). Tweedale 1984: M.M. Tweedale, Alexander of Aphrodisias’ Views on Universals, «Phronesis», 29, 1984, pp. 279-303. Tweedale 1987: M.M. Tweedale, Aristotle’s Universals, «Australasian Journal of Philosophy», 65, 1987, pp. 412-26. Tweedale 1988: M.M. Tweedale, Aristotle’s Realism, «he Canadian Journal of Philosophy», 18, 1988, pp. 501-26.
504 Bibliography
Untersteiner 1996: M. Untersteiner, I soisti, Milano, Bruno Mondadori 19962. van den Berg 2007: R.M. van den Berg, Proclus’ Commentary on the Cratylus in Context: Ancient heories of Language and Naming, Leiden, Brill 2007. van der Eijk 1996: Ph.J. van der Eijk, Diocles and the Hippocratic Writings on the Method of Dietetics and the Limits of Causal Explanation, in Hippokratische Medizin und antike Philosophie, hrsg. v. R. Wittern und P. Pellegrin, Hildesheim, Olms 1996, pp. 229-57 (repr. in Ph.J. van der Eijk, Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2005, pp. 74-100). van der Eijk 1997: Ph.J. van der Eijk, Galen’s Use of the Concept of “Qualiied Experience” in his Dietetic and Pharmacological Works, in Galen on Pharmacology, ed. by A. Debru, Leiden, Brill 1997, pp. 3557 (repr. in Ph.J. van der Eijk, Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2005, p. 279–98). van der Eijk 2008: Ph.J. van der Eijk, herapeutics, in he Cambridge Companion to Galen, ed. by R.J. Hankinson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2008, pp. 283-303. van Inwagen 2004: P. van Inwagen, A heory of Properties, «Oxford Studies in Metaphysics», 1, 2004, pp. 107-38. van Winden 1990: J.C.M van Winden, Notiz über ΔΥΝΑΜΙΣ bei Gregor von Nyssa, in ΕΡΜΗΝΕΥΜΑΤΑ: Festschrit Für Hadwig Hörner Zum Sechzigsten, hrsg. v. H. Eisenberger, Heidelberg, Winter 1990, p. 147– 50 (repr. in J.C.M van Winden, Arché: A Collection of Patristic Studies, ed. by J. den Boet and D.T. Runia, Leiden, Brill 1997, pp. 146-50). Vegetti 1994: M. Vegetti, L’immagine del medico e lo statuto epistemologico della medicina in Galeno, in Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt, II.37.2, Berlin-New York, De Gruyter 1994, pp. 1672– 717 (repr. in M. Vegetti, Dialoghi con gli antichi, a cura di S. Gastaldi, F. Calabi, S. Campese e F. Ferrari, Sankt Augustin, Academia Verlag 2007, pp. 227-78). Vlastos 1954: G. Vlastos, he hird Man Argument in the Parmenides, «he Philosophical Review», 58, 1954, pp. 319-49. Vlastos 1955: G. Vlastos, Addenda to the hird Man Argument: A Reply to Professor Sellars, «he Philosophical Review», 64, 1955, pp. 438-48. Vlastos 1956: G. Vlastos, Postscript To he hird Man: A Reply To Mr. Geach, «he Philosophical Review», 65, 1956, pp. 83-94.
505 Bibliography
Vlastos 1970: G. Vlastos, An Ambiguity in the Sophist, in G. Vlastos, Platonic Studies, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 19812, pp. 270–322. Vlastos 1971a: G. Vlastos, he Unity of the Virtues in the Protagoras, in G. Vlastos, Platonic Studies, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 19812, pp. 221–69. Vlastos 1971b: G. Vlastos, he “Two-Level Paradoxes” in Aristotle, in G. Vlastos, Platonic Studies, Princeton (NJ), Princeton University Press 19812, pp. 323–34. Vlastos 1991: G. Vlastos, Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1991. von Balthasar 1961: H.U. von Balthasar, Kosmische Liturgie: Das Weltbild Maximus’ des Bekenners, Einsiedeln, Johannes-Verlag 1961. von Staden 1989: H. von Staden, Herophilus. he Art of Medicine in Early Alexandria, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1989. Vuillemin 2001: J. Vuillemin, Mathématiques pythagoriciennes et platoniciennes, Paris, Albert Blanchard 2001. Warren 2006: J. Warren, Psychic Disharmony: Philoponus and Epicurus on Plato’s Phaedo, in «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 30, 2006, pp. 235-60. Waterlow 1982: S. Waterlow, he hird Man’s Contribution to Plato’s Paradigmatism, «Mind», 91, 1982, pp. 339-57. Wedberg 1955: A. Wedberg, Plato’s Philosophy of Mathematics, Stockholm, Almqvist & Wiksell 1955. Wedin 1993: M.V. Wedin, Nonsubstantial Individuals, «Phronesis», 38, 1993, pp. 137-65. Wedin 2000: M.V. Wedin, Aristotle’s heory of Substance. he Categories and Metaphysics Zeta, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2000. Weiss 1965: G. Weiss, Studia Anastasiana I, Studien zum Leben, zu den Schriten und zur heologie des Patriarchen Anastasius I von Antiochien (559-598), München, Institut für Byzantinistik und neugriechische Philologie der Universität, 1965. Wessel 2004: S. Wessel, Cyril of Alexandria and the Nestorian Controversy. he Making of a Saint and of a Heretic, Oxford, Oxford University Press 2004. Whitaker 1996: C.W.A. Whitaker, Aristotle’s De Interpretatione. Contradiction and Dialectic, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1996.
506 Bibliography
White 1971a: N.P. White, A Note on Ἔκθεσις, «Phronesis», 16, 1971, p. 164-8. White 1971b: N.P. White, Aristotle on Sameness and Oneness, «he Philosophical Review», 80, 1971, p. 177-97. White 1992: N.P. White, Plato’s Metaphysical Epistemology, in he Cambridge Companion to Plato, ed. by R. Kraut, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1992, pp. 277–310. Whiting 1986: J. E. Whiting, Form and Individuation in Aristotle, «History of Philosophy Quarterly», 3, 1986, pp. 359-77. Wilberding 2005: J. Wilberding, “Creeping Spatiality”: the Location of Nous in Plotinus’ Universe, «Phronesis», 50», 2005, pp. 315-34. Wilberding 2006: J. Wilberding, Plotinus’ Cosmology: A Study of Ennead II.1 (40), Oxford, Oxford University Press 2006. Williams D.C. 1953: D.C. Williams, On the Elements of Being, I, «Review of Metaphysics», 7, 1953, pp. 3-18. Woods 1967: M.J. Woods, Problems in Metaphysics Z, Chapter 13, in Aristotle, ed. by J.M.E. Moravscik, New York, Doubleday 1967. Woods 1974-5: M.J. Woods, Substance and Essence in Aristotle, «Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society», 25, 1974-5, pp. 167-80. Woods 1991a: M.J. Woods, Universal and Particular Forms in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, «Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy», 9, 1991, pp. 41-56. Woods 1991b: M.J. Woods, Particular Forms Revisited, «Phronesis», 36, 1991, pp. 75-87. Yang 2005: M.-H. Yang, he Relationship between Hypothesis and Images in the Mathematical Subsection of the Divided Line in Plato’s Republic, «Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review», 44, 2005, pp. 285-312. Zachhuber 2000: J. Zachhuber, Human Nature in Gregory of Nyssa. Philosophical Background and heological Signiicance, Leiden, Brill 2000. Zachhuber 2001: J. Zachhuber, Basil of Caesarea and the hreeHypostases-Tradition. Reconsidering the Origins of Cappadocian heology, «Zeitschrit für antikes Christentum», 5, 2001, pp. 65-85. Zachhuber 2003: J. Zachhuber, Nochmals: Der “38. Brief“ des Basilius von Cäsarea als Werk des Gregor von Nyssa, «Zeitschrit für antikes Christentum», 7, 2003, pp. 73-90.
507 Bibliography
Zachhuber 2005a: J. Zachhuber, Once again: Gregory of Nyssa on Universals, «he Journal of heological Studies», 56, 2005, pp. 75-98. Zachhuber 2005b: J. Zachhuber, Das Universalienproblem bei den griechischen Kirchenvätern und im frühen Mittelalter. Vorläuige Überlegungen zu einer wenig erforschten Traditionslinie im ersten Millenium, «Millennium. Jahrbuch zu Kultur und Geschichte des ersten Jahrtausends n.Chr.», 2, 2005, pp. 137-74. Zachhuber 2010a: J. Zachhuber, Phyrama, in he Brill Dictionary of Gregory of Nyssa, ed. by L.F. Mateo-Seco and G. Maspero, Leiden, Brill 2010, pp. 612-4. Zachhuber 2010b: J. Zachhuber, Physis, in he Brill Dictionary of Gregory of Nyssa, ed. by L.F. Mateo-Seco and G. Maspero, Leiden, Brill 2010, pp. 615-20. Zeyl 2000: Plato: Timaeus, trans. and notes by D.J. Zeyl, Indianapolis (IN)-Cambridge (MA), Hackett 2000. Zimmermann 1991: Al-Farabi’s Commentary and Short Treatise on Aristotle’s De Interpretatione, trans. and comm. by F. Zimmermann, Oxford, Clarendon Press 1991 (1981).
Finito di stampare nel mese di ottobre 2013 presso le Industrie Grafiche della Pacini Editore S.p.A. Via A. Gherardesca • 56121 Ospedaletto • Pisa Telefono 050 313011 • Telefax 050 3130300 Internet: http://www.pacinieditore.it
View more...
Comments