Ateneo Law Intro to Law
Short Description
Reviewer...
Description
INTRODUCTION TO
LAW REVIEWER (FIRST AND SECOND DAY)
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
FIRST DAY THE TRIAL (Der Process) Take note that Franz Kafka is one of the greatest scholars in the philosophical movement known as existentialism existentialism and that his work deals with themes such as absurdity and hopelessness. It might be easier to regard his works with that in mind because some of his works will seem weird and oddly contradictory if viewed as a normal piece of literature. This is Franz Kafka's posthumous work, wherein a man called Josef K. (hereinafter called K.), a senior bank clerk, is arrested for an unidentified unidentified crime. The men who come to arrest him do not specify under whose authority they are acting. It is a diatribe on the legal process and philosophical ruminations on justice and how it is handled in light of a judicial process like the courts. This is the plot, in a nutshell, from Wikipedia: On his thirtieth birthday, a senior bank clerk, Josef K., who lives in lodgings, is unexpectedly arrested by two unidentified agents for an unspecified crime. The agents do not name the authority for which they are acting. He is not taken away, however, but left at home to await instructions from the Committee of Affairs. K. later visits the court and stands in the witness box pleading his case. He then returns home. K. later goes to visit the magistrate again, but instead is forced to have a meeting with an attendant's wife. Looking at the Magistrate's books, he discovers a cache of pornography. K. returns home to find Fräulein Montag, a lodger from another room, moving in with Fräulein Bürstner. He suspects that this is to prevent him from pursuing his affair with the latter woman. Yet another lodger, Captain Lanz, appears to be in league with Montag. Later, in a store room at his own bank, K. discovers the two agents, who arrested him, being whipped by a flogger for asking K. for bribes, as a result of complaints K. previously made about them to the Magistrate. K. tries to argue with the flogger, saying that the men need not be whipped, but the flogger cannot be swayed. The next day he returns to the store room and is shocked to find everything as he had found it the day before, including the Whipper and the two agents. K. is visited by his uncle, who is a friend of a lawyer. The lawyer was with the Clerk of the Court. The uncle seems distressed by K.'s predicament. At first sympathetic, he becomes concerned K. is underestimating the seriousness of the case. The uncle introduces K. to an advocate, who is attended by Leni, a nurse, who K.'s uncle suspects is the advocate's mistress. K. has a sexual encounter with Leni, whilst his
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 2 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
uncle is talking with the Advocate and the Chief Clerk of the Court, much to his uncle's anger, and to the detriment of his case. K. visits the advocate and finds him to be a capricious and unhelpful character. K. returns to his bank but finds that his colleagues are trying to undermine him. K. is advised by one of his bank clients to visit Titorelli, a court painter, for advice. Titorelli has no official connections, yet seems to have a deep understanding of the process. K. learns that, to Titorelli's knowledge, not a single defendant has ever been acquitted. He sets out what K.'s options are, but the consequences of all of them are unpleasant: they consist of different delay tactics to stretch out his case as long as possible before the inevitable "Guilty" verdict. Titorelli instructs K. that there's not much he can do since he doesn't know of what crime he has been accused. K. decides to take control of matters himself and visits his advocate with the intention of dismissing him. At the advocate's office he meets a downtrodden individual, Block, a client who offers K. some insight from a client's perspective. Block's case has continued for five years and he appears to have been virtually enslaved by his dependence on the advocate's meaningless and circular advice. The advocate mocks Block in front of K. for his dog-like subservience. This experience further poisons K.'s opinion of his advocate, and K. is bemused as to why his advocate would think that seeing such a client, in such a state, could change his mind. (This chapter was left unfinished by the author.) K. is asked to tour an Italian client around local places of cultural interest, but the Italian client short of time asks K. to tour him around only the cathedral, setting a time to meet there. When the client doesn't show up, K. explores the cathedral which is empty except for an old woman and a church official. K. decides to leave, as a priest K. notices seems to be preparing to give a sermon from a small second pulpit, lest it begin and K. be compelled to stay for its entirety. Instead of giving a sermon, the priest calls out K.'s name, although K. has never known the priest. The priest works for the court, and tells K. a fable, (which has been published separately as Before the Law) that is meant to explain his situation, but instead causes confusion, and implies that K.'s fate is hopeless. Before the Law begins as a parable, then continues with several pages of interpretation between the Priest and K. The gravity of the priest's words prepares the reader for an unpleasant ending. On the last day of K.'s thirtieth year, two men arrive to execute him. He offers little resistance, suggesting that he has realised this as being inevitable for some time. They lead him to a quarry where he is expected to kill himself, but he cannot. The two men then execute him. His last words describe his own death: "Like a dog!"
The two excerpts: "Before the Law" and "Dialogue between a Priest and K." are found in The Trial by Kafka. The first is a parable, and the second is a dialogue between two different ideas. Take note that the first excerpt is found within the second. “The Problem of our Laws” is a short story, also by Kafka.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 3 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Before the Law: The parable discussed in this excerpt concerns a doorkeeper and one who wants to pass through it. The doorkeeper is only the first of a series of doorkeepers, but warns the man who seeks to pass that he is only the first and there are many beyond him, each more terrible than the last. The man asks if he can ever be allowed in and the doorkeeper says that its possible but not right now. So instead of leaving, the man sits by the door and every so often asks to be let in, only to be rejected by the doorkeeper. The man ponders this question: If the law is meant to be accessible to everyone, why must it be so difficult to get access to it? Through the rest of his years, he sits and waits to be let in by the doorkeeper, doing everything he can to gain access, including sacrificing his belongings to bribe him and asking the fleas on the fur collar of the doorkeeper to let him pass, to no avail. The doorkeeper accepts the bribes only because he did not want the man to think that he (the man) failed to do anything. The man waits at the door until his senses start to fail him. While his eyes start to fail, he begins to see the "radiance that streams from the gateway of the Law." Just before he expires, asks the doorkeeper why, if everyone strives to reach the Law, no one else has tried to enter. The doorman, seeing that the end was near for the man, said this: "No one else could ever be admitted here, since this gate was made only for you. I am now going to shut it." Dialogue Between the Priest and K: The chapter begins with K. being tasked to show an important Italian businessman around, who doesn't show up. He then starts to look around their meeting place, a cathedral. Just as he is about to leave, a priest calls out to him by name, although K. doesn't know him at all. It turns out he is a court employee. He tells K. about the parable of "Before the Law" (discussed above). The dialogue excerpt is about the two of them discussing the interpretation of the parable. The priest (up in the pulpit) talks about his case and how he thinks it's going badly and that K will be proven guilty. K laments that it is a mistake and that he is not guilty, so how is someone who is guilty be found guilty. The priest says that is how the guilty speak, but makes no presumptions of guilt against K. K says that everyone involved in the proceedings has something against him, and influence the others who aren't involved. The priest says that verdicts do not appear suddenly but are arrived at gradually. K says he needs help but the priest says he's looking for help in the wrong places, and says that he shouldn't look for help in a woman. K
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 4 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
argues that women are powerful and that the people in the court are women chasers. The priest becomes frustrated with K. The priest comes down from the pulpit and K says that he finds the priest very friendly and because of this he can speak openly to him more than he could with anyone from the court. The priest tells him not to fool himself, and then starts discussing the parable of "Before the Law." Afterwards, K believes that the doorkeeper cheated the man, but the priest told him not to believe his opinion before checking it. K says that its quite obvious that the man was cheated, and that the doorkeeper gave him the information that would help the man when the man would have no more use of it. The priest said that the doorkeeper had a duty and that the man had not asked before that. K continued by saying that if the door was intended for the man then the doorkeeper should have let him in. The priest says that the doorkeeper explains two things about access to the law: first, that he can't allow him to enter NOW but maybe later on, and second, that the door was meant for him alone. If one of the statements contradicted the other, then the doorman cheated, but according to the priest, they didn't. The priest goes on to discuss the many features of the doorman, in that he is incorruptible, precise, duty-conscious, simple-minded and a little arrogant, but that he is also friendly by nature and even humors the many questions and requests of the man which do not contradict his duty. Not every doorkeeper would have withstood the many years with the man. The priest concludes that there are many ways by which the doorkeeper's actions may be interpreted.
! !
K asks the priest if he thinks the man was cheated, and the priest states that he does not make any opinion about the doorkeeper; he only points out that there are many interpretations. The text cannot be altered, and people's differing opinions are only expressions of despair over it. The priest says that there are interpretations that say that the doorkeeper was cheated, because he only knew the outside of the law but not the inside of it. His ideas of what the law are are supposedly childish, and while he treats the man as a subordinate, he is also subordinate to the other doorkeepers inside, all of whom are more terrible to behold than himself. The free man is superior to one who is subservient to another. The man being made to wait was free to leave and go anywhere except inside the gate guarded by the doorkeeper; he only chose to stay and wait outside. The doorkeeper had no such freedom. Guarding the gate meant for the man alone meant that the doorkeeper could not leave but wait for the whole of the man's life to see if he became worthy to pass through it. In this way, the doorkeeper was subservient to the man, and could only be released from his duty at the close of the man's life.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 5 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
K sees the point of the priest and says that maybe the two versions of who cheated who are not incompatible. The priest says that this is another opinion expressed about the parable. The priest says that you don't need to accept everything as true, you only have it accept it as being necessary. They arrive in piece at the end of their discussions, both at differing sides of the argument. K becomes tired thinking about the different interpretations of the story and thinks that the fairly simplistic story at the beginning lost its shape. K believes its time for him to leave the cathedral but claims to be lost in the dark. Before the priest leaves, K calls back to him to wait. K asks if the priest wants anything from him, but the priest says no. K says that he was so friendly to him earlier, but now abandons him as if he were nothing to the priest. "First, you need to understand who I am," said the priest. "You're the prison chaplain," said K., and went closer to the priest, it was not so important for him to go straight back to the bank as he had made out, he could very well stay where he was. "So that means I belong to the court," said the priest. "So why would I want anything from you? The court doesn't want anything from you. It accepts you when you come and it lets you go when you leave."
The Problems of Our Laws
!
This excerpt discusses the problems of law to the common man (meaning, one not versed in law such as barristers/lawyers). K. talks about how difficult it is to grasp the laws when they're created and guarded by the elite, and how difficult it is to be ruled by laws one does not know or understand. Laws are ancient, their interpretation has been the work of centuries and such interpretation has been so well regarded that they've become like the law itself. Such interpretation can only be done with restriction, only by and for the nobles. He talks about how nobles stand above the law and it is because of such a position that the law has been entrusted to them. There is "wisdom in it, but also hardship" for the ones who are not afforded the opportunity to grasp the law. The fact of the existence of such law is in itself a presumption because they are presumed to exist, and the reason why is only allegedly told to those who hold it -- the nobles. It becomes funny because maybe the laws they are trying so hard to understand may not exist at all. He states that there is a small movement that believes that the Law is whatever the nobles do, and that popular opinion cannot factor in its interpretation or creation because listening to their good points cannot offset the heavy drawbacks that will come in when listening to them.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 6 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
He puts stock in the belief that time will come when the world realizes that the law is incomplete without societal input and the law will belong, finally, to the people and the nobility will vanish. This is nothing against the nobility and is more of a remark of selfhatred of the ordinary people for not being "deserving enough" to be entrusted with the law. And therefore a paradox exists because only in the rejection of the nobility can this kind of vision come true, but no one is strong enough to unite as a force before them. "The sole visible and indubitable law that is imposed upon us is the nobility, and must we ourselves deprive ourselves of that one law?"
Law:
(law) v. Ius (justice) Dr. Jur Eric Engle
Lex
WHAT IS LAW:
-
-
o
-
An exclusive answer is not what is meant to be achieved but rather a number of definitions that will be consistent with one another. Thus, natural law, positive law, law as prescription and law as description will be distinguished to arrive at a definition. Distinguishing between law and justice will allow focus on command and right. Engle states that unlike Kenley, he regards law as a “conflicting set of conditional statements and consequent imperatives rather than as hierarchically harmonious set of norms.” A number of norms that are the same ultimately form a unity of norms. This unity of norms can be traced back to a single basic norm that is the basis for all the number of norms that emanate from it. These types of norms are usually known as moral norms. For example: Not to lie, not to cheat and keeping a promise are all the same kind of moral norms that are derived from the basic norm of truthfulness. What is important to know here is that many moral norms are usually just derivations of a basic general norm (from the general norm to particular norms derived from it). Normative reference to law is necessary for law to have more significance than something done by force. The teeth behind law isn’t only physical violence but more of a moral obligation/sanction.
METHODOLOGY: 1. Legal Science - To be able to answer what law is it must be the object of scientific inquiry. But as any of the natural sciences, legal science is not exact. It is nomothetic meaning it presents principles which are laws in the strict sense.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 7 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
o
-
-
-
Nomotheses cannot be derogated from and must react exactly as they do. Example: If water is heated it eventually boils and evaporates, as a natural science they must act exactly as they do. In human science however, legal science included, it is different. It cannot be said that because of a certain event the same outcome will be obtained every time. This is because the object concerns human beings, and human beings have volition (will). Humans have the capacity to act and interact with the environment. Human science cannot have non-derrogable laws but can only have general trends and tendencies. This doesn’t mean that there is no human science because it is still possible to make statements regarding human tendencies and trends and be able to make general predictions. These predictions however, are not exact but only approximates. The differing possibilities and limitations of human sciences should be recognized.
2. The Empirical Method - One test to determine whether a position is scientifically known is when a prediction can be based upon it. So if a certain fact is known, then a prediction may be based upon it. - If a fact is unknown it is possible that it will be known in the future although at present it is unknown. An unknown fact may also just be unknowable. An unknown fact cannot be the basis of science but it may give rise to speculation and hypothesis. - Ideas may be true, false, unknown and possibly also unknowable ever. - Through empirical testing, knowable facts can be verified. Through empirical testing, the observation that if X act happens Y result occurs and thus from future instances it can be inferred that the happening will recur. - Empirical verification can also be done in human sciences although it is less exact as compared to natural science. - A theory can be verified if there is a correspondence between material reality and the predicted outcome. So in terms of legal science, we need to determine what the predicted outcomes in law are. - For law we see predictions of legislators or a judge as to what will happen if a certain act occurs. But these predictions are not always accurate and what happens is even beyond the possible outcomes and those written in law books.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 8 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
3. Scholarly Law versus Practical Law - The absence of the correlation between law in the books and life can be solved in two methods. - First is the idealist approach. Here it is argued that material reality is an imperfect reflection of ideas and that failure of persons to conform to the law and the law to punish them imply that the law and justice or the person and justice is not a correct relation. This approach however is empirically incapable of verification. Being incapable of science the paper rejects this method. - Second response is to look at law critically. First, Scholarly law are those in books which include statements of judges and a description of what is ruled on by judges in a certain set of facts. Second is Practical law (law in the streets) or what in fact happens. When law in the books and law in the streets correlate or actually happen, then that could mean either a very just regime or a tyrannical one. When they do not correlate and are way out of balance then a revolution occurs and a new ruling class takes control. LAWS ARE CONDITIONALS AND IMPERATIVES
-
-
-
-
-
Reading the law in books, all laws are stated as a conditional that when actuated will trigger imperatives. For example, if you steal something then you will be punished. If the conditional is fulfilled then the imperative reward or punishment happens. The degree of correspondence between these conditionals and their outcome is not always accurate but it is a measure of the efficacy of the law and the government enforcing it. A direct correspondence between the conditional and imperative is impossible because of free will. Also, the laws of legal systems are almost always imperfectly enforced and thus legal science is not nomothetical . To consider legal science as nomothetical would be that every law will be enforced everywhere, at all times without exception and that humans behave exactly alike, which is clearly not the case. But despite the impreciseness with which legal science acts, it is generally enforced and so, generalized predictions can be made as to the probability of an event following another. Legal science is dialectical. The law is dialectical in that it mediates between right and o right. Both or all sides of the controversy have some good. And so the job of the law is to mediate between the rights of two sides, to adjust or accommodate and to sacrifice as little as possible of what is right on both sides. Dialectic in the Aristotelian sense, in that it is the object of o discourse. Meaning that different legal opinions are compared to get a better sense of which governs human behavior.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 9 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Example: When a judge is presented with the plaintiff and defendant, two sides are presented which are completely opposite. The decision of the judge is the dialectical synthesis of these competing positions. Dialectic in the Marxist sense, wherein law is an element of a o superstructure of a particular mode of production, which justifies and defends a particular mode of production at a particular point in history. Scholarly law (law in the books) is understood as authoritative statements of legislators and judges consisting of conditional and imperatives. However, not all imperative commands are a result of conditionals found in scholarly law. It is possible, however, for the legislative to issue a purely o imperative statement or a conditional statement that triggers no imperatives. Conditional statements can also consist of rules, exceptions to the rule and exceptions to the exceptions. This process of exceptions could continue indefinitely. Conditional statements of the law could be procedural rules of positive law or substantive rules, which could reflect principles of natural law and/or natural justice. Substantive rules of law are from procedural elements of o positive law or substantive aspects of natural law, natural justice or a combination. The conditional statements of substantive law are made of o procedural rules, general principles of law and/or fundamental rights. !
-
-
-
META-RULES 1. General Principles: - General principles of law are a source of meta-rules which is a concept of civillianist law. It is a source of international law, and also of persuasive authority in domestic law in civil law jurisdictions but not in common law jurisdictions. - General principles of law are reflected in principles of equity, embodied as maxims of law.
2. Fundamental Rights and Rules of Procedure: - Unlike civil law jurisdiction, common law countries have adopted constitutionally binding charters of rights and have given their highest courts the power to review the constitutionality of ordinary laws. - Constitutional charters are reflections of fundamental rights and freedoms found in natural law and natural justice. - These common law charters of rights and freedoms operate similarly as the civilian’s general principles of law.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 10 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
-
Fundamental rights (especially in the United States) are generally limited to individual freedoms (worded as negative freedoms –“freedom from” as compared to positive freedoms: “the right to”). They contain collective freedoms as well. General principles of law/fundamental rights can thus be seen as conceptually the same. It is seen as: Binding or non-binding o Independent sources of law or reflections of natural o law/natural justice Collective or individual o Negative (“freedoms from”) or positive (“rights to”) o However these rules are constituted, general principles of law and concepts of fundamental rights and freedoms are rules that determine how to form other rules. Fundamental rights are essentially substantive and are a more limited concept than general principles of law, which are both substantive and procedural. But both fundamental rights and general principles of law are generally binding rules and for that they are similar. Because of similarity they may be invoked in theory but less in practice because of generality and ambiguity. Fundamental rights and fundamental freedoms: First generation rights: freedoms asserted by the rising o middle class and proto-industrialists were in the negative— “freedom from” as compared to positive “rights to” 1848 socialist revolutions inaugurated positive “rights to”. o The rising working classes asserted a right to minimum standards like hours, wages, etc. – thus the “rights to” expressed not only fundamental constitutional rights but were also strengthened by secondary legislative administrative law. What these freedoms and rights have in common is that they reorder the principle of distributive justice. The bourgeois revolution began the era of distribution based “supposedly” on merit. While the socialist revolutions introduced a principle of distribution according to need. The evolution from negative freedoms to positive rights to all classes shows the historical dialectical character of the elaboration of rights. General principles, fundamental rights, fundamental freedoms and rules of procedure are all example of meta-rules – rules about making rules.
LAW AND JUSTICE: 1. “Law” as description and “law” as prescription - Some assert that there is a connection between law and justice and thus a bad law that serves no justice is not a law at all. This is true in that one is justified in breaking an unjust
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 11 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
law since there is no crime in breaking a law that is criminal in itself. However it is not true in the sense of law as conditional predictive statements. The prescriptive power of law (normative character) arises o from the idea that law reflects morality. But the description of a conditional or command of law is o merely positive law. Thus, an unjust law may have no moral prescriptive force but have a practical descriptive validity.
2. Legal Science is not strictly nomothetical - The dual character of law as prescription and law as description can also be seen from the fact that legal science is not strictly nomothetical since the ruler and ruled have the capacity to act. - Because legal science is not nomothetic we account for the variance between what is prescribed (scholarly law) and what actually happens (practical law) as the difference between prescription and description. - The dual character of law as prescription and description can be seen from the empirical method and shows that the validity of a law is not dependant on its moral character (although most laws have some element of morality, its enforcement is not dependent on this moral character). Thus, those who break unjust law do so at their own o risk, because as a law it still must be followed even if we feel it is unjust.
3. Law as Prediction - Law is a description of what is and prescription is what law should be. Yet, law is also a prediction of what can happen in the real world. - The law is not always unjust, and a tyrant can create bad laws but having state power, they must be followed. However, these immoral laws will eventually be broken by majority of the people and eventually become unenforceable (good example is the people power revolution against martial law). In this sense, natural law is self-enforcing. o 4. Positive Law and Natural Justice - A connection between law and justice is not necessary since a law can be just and when it is, it partakes the nature of natural justice. A law may partake of natural justice without having the needed force to make it effective. Thus a just state must exhibit a tempered union of natural law (force) and natural justice (morality). Two types of unjust states: o
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 12 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
!
!
Powerless states that lack the capacity to enforce what appear to be just laws. States that are powerful but enforce unjust laws.
5. Distributive and Corrective Justice - Distributive justice determines the general principle according to which public goods are to be distributed: merit, need, equality or inequality. - Different states have different principles of distribution. This just goes to show that the system of distribution is positive and conventional rather than natural and inevitable. - Corrective (transactional) justice sees to it that private exchanges are fair and equal. That parties to a contract are not cheated, the victim of o another’s negligence are compensated. Corrective justice, however, may not be translated into o practice. Natural justice is not inevitably translated into natural law.
6. Ex ante legislation and ex post judgment (temporal view) - Ex ante means prior to the act being adjudicated. - Ex post means a decision made after the act. - Laws are enacted almost always ex ante and judicial decisions are ex post , although these decisions may have ex ante effects to future litigants. Genocide was ex post as there were no treaties o proscribing it until after WW2. - One of the achievements of the bourgeois revolutions was to replace arbitrary tyrannical ruling with decisions based on merit. - The arbitrary character of aristocratic rule was replaced by the elimination of ex post facto laws. Ex post facto laws are laws that make an act a crime, o which was not a crime when it was committed. Example: Person X was smoking in a car while driving. The next day a law is passed prohibiting smoking while driving a car. Person X is then arrested for the act of smoking prior to the enactment of a law. No crime should be made after the fact (nul crimen sin o lege ). - One of the features of bourgeois liberal government and of socialist government is the specialization of organs of state. - The role of a legislator is to establish ex ante rules. The pronouncements of legislators are general (although o not as general as fundamental rights or general principles of law). The role of the judiciary on the other hand is to create o decisions ex post , relying upon rules promulgated by
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 13 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
the legislator ex ante (thus, decrees of courts are a lot more specific then those made by the legislator).
7. Collective Judgments: - Another achievement of the bourgeois revolutions was the replacement of collective judgment with a strict principle of individual accountability instead of being based on social classes, etc. Thus, crimes done by family members or ascendants o could not be penalized against the descendants. Also, crimes committed by a person belonging to a certain class could not be penalized against all of the members of that class. CONCLUSION :
-
-
-
The fundamental element of law does not consist of a hierarchically ordered set of norms. Instead, they are potentially conflicting conditional statements with contingent enforcement imperatives. This however is only scholarly law or law in the books. o To be considered practical law they must be enforced. o Natural law is nothing more or less than the law of the strongest while positive law are the arbitrary statements of a legislator. While differing societies have different standards of justice, those differences are functions of their mode of production. Within a given mode of production, moral standards of society are generally accepted and are intersubjective. They reflect the moral judgment and capacity of judgment of the society depending upon the society’s state of economic development.
SECOND DAY Bramble Bush Precedent •
An official doing over again under similar circumstances substantially what has been done by him or his predecessors before
Foundation of precedent Official analogue of what in society: folkways/institutions and of what is in the individual: habit •
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 14 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Precedent is the dignified name for the practice of the officer/office The author thinks that unless there were such practice it would be hard to know there was an office/officer If written records exist and are carefully and continuously consulted, the possibility of change creeping into the practices unannounced is greatly lessened. •
•
Law application of precedent: The courts might keep records and keep them and pay little attention to them But the lawyer searches the records for convenient cases to support his point, presses upon the court what is has already done before, capitalizes the human drive toward repetition by finding, making explicit, by urging the prior cases To continue past practices is to provide a new official in his inexperience of his predecessors. If he is idle - have their action brought to his o attention and profit by their industry If he is ignorant - can learn from them and profit by o the knowledge of those who have gone before him If he is foolish - profit by their wisdom o If he is biased/corrupt - public check on his biases o and corruption, limits the frame in which he can indulge them unchallenged The knowledge that he will continue what they have done gives a basis from which men may predict the action of the courts, a basis to which they can adjust their expectations and their affairs in advance. To know the law is helpful even when the law is bad. In our system, there has grownup: 1. Habit of following precedent 2. Legal norm that precedent is to be followed Main form of precedent The canon that each case must be decided as one o instanced under the general rule, other canons are only to support this canon, •
•
•
•
• •
•
ORTHODOX DOCTRINE OF PREDECENT (strict view) Applied to unwelcome precedents Honorable technique for whittling precedents away. It is a surgeon’s knife Every case lays down a rule, the rule of the case • •
•
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 15 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
o
o
o
o
Ratio Decidendi = prima facie the rule of the case since it is the ground upon which the court chose to rest its decision BUT a later court can reexamine the case and invoke the canon that no judge has the power to decide what is not before him, through examination of facts or of the procedural issue, narrow the picture of what was actually before the court and hold that the ruling made requires to be understood as thus restricted Extreme form result: confining the case to its particular facts Effect: case overruled
Loose view of precedent The court has decided and decided authoritatively, any point or all points on which it chose to rest its case to pass Rule of court laid down = the court has held Extreme form results In thinking and arguing exclusively from the language o that is found in past opinions and in citing and working with that language wholly without reference to the facts of the case called language forth Capitalizing welcome precedents •
• •
•
Strict view Hard to use for lawyers, but its okay for the judge because he has the knife in his hand, he can free himself •
NOTE: Precedents do not produce certainty. There must still be persuasion and judgment.
State v. Rachel Pendergrass 2DW & V., NC. 365 [1837] Facts: The defendant kept a school for small children. On one occasion, a little girl of six or seven years of age was whipped (with a switch) by defendant after a milder treatment had failed. Some of the marks from the whip went away after a few days but two marks were proved on her arm and neck, which also disappeared after a few days. The lower court ruled in favor of the State and found defendant guilty of abuse. Issue:
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 16 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Whether or not defendant is guilty of child abuse or if it was part of the legal chastisement of pupils. Ratio/Held: The Court in this case found defendant not guilty and reversed the prior judgment. The law grants to schoolmasters and teachers the discretion to correct their pupils, analogous to that of their parents. It is the duty of parents to command obedience to control stubbornness and reform bad habits but to do this, he must have the power to administer moderate correction when just and necessary. The welfare of the child is the main purpose for which pain is permitted to be inflicted. However, when the punishment can seriously endanger life, limb or health or disfigure the child or cause permanent injury, then the purpose of correction is not achieved and this shouldn’t be allowed. But if it causes only temporary pain and no permanent ill, then it is permissible. In this case no permanent injury was done to the child and the only appearances that could warrant the belief of threatened permanent injury were the bruises (on the arm and neck) but they were too equivocal to justify.
State v. Black 60 N.C. 262 [1864] Facts: The defendant Jesse Black was charged with assault against his wife Tamsey Black. According to the evidence, they lived separately from each other and one day as Jesse was passing by the house where his wife resided, Tamsey made an ill remark about a Sal Daly and Jesse Black (“have you patched Sal Daly’s bonnet?”). They exchanged angry words and Jesse accused her of having connections with a negro. Then the Jesse grabbed her hair and pulled her down the floor. He didn’t hit her but during trial she said that she was hurt and her throat was injured and sore although he did not choke her (at the trial she was completely recovered). After she got up from the floor she continued to abuse him. The defense argued that Jesse could not be convicted of battery on his wife unless a permanent injury is inflicted or uses excessive violence or cruelty.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 17 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Issue: Whether or not Jesse Black can be convicted for abuse against his wife. Held/Ratio: The Court in this case held that he was not liable for abuse against his wife. The Court stated that a husband, being responsible for the household, can do such acts and enforce a certain degree of force as is necessary to control the unruly temper of his wife. Until a degree of cruelty, or excess passion is inflicted, the Court will not invade the domestic forum. Such an intervention would put the parties as a public exhibition, widen the breach, make reconciliation almost impossible, and encourage insubordination. The fact that they live separately is a non-issue since they are still married. Only when there is a divorce where the state recognizes their separation can this be considered abuse. But a private agreement to live separately doesn’t affect the fact that the husband is still responsible for her acts.
Antonin Scalia: The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules
Antonin Scalia stands by what Aristotle said that: Rightly constituted laws should be the final sovereign; and personal rule, whether it be exercised by a single person or a body of persons, should be sovereign only in those matters on which law is unable, owing to the difficulty of framing general rules for all contingencies, to make an exact pronouncement. It is this dichotomy between "general rule of law" and "personal discretion to do justice" that I wish to explore. He started by discussing the advantages of common-law system, that is, the discretion-conferring approach. It follows that perfect justice can only be achieved if courts are unconstrained by such imperfect generalizations. Scalia gave some substantial competing values which often contradicts the search for perfection. First of which is equal treatment. Parents know that children will accept quite readily all
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 18 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
sorts of arbitrary substantive dispositions -- no television in the afternoon, or no television in the evening, or even no television at all. But try to let one brother or sister watch television when the others do not and you will feel the fury of the fundamental sense of justice unleashed. Second is predictability. Even in simpler times uncertainty has been regarded as incompatible with the Rule of Law. Rudimentary justice requires that those subject to the law must have the means of knowing what it prescribes. It is said that one of Emperor Nero's nasty practices was to post his edicts high on the columns so that they would be harder to read and easier to transgress. As laws have become more numerous, and as people have become increasingly ready to punish their adversaries in the courts, we can less and less afford protracted uncertainty regarding what the law may mean. Predictability, or as Llewellyn put it, "reckonability," is a needful characteristic of any law worthy of the name. There are times when even a bad rule is better than no rule at all. Common-law approach is said to be as ‘the course of judicial restraint, “making” as little law as possible in order to decide the case at hand’. However, Scalia have come to doubt whether this is true because in writing for the majority of the Court, he adopts a general rule, and say, "This is the basis of our decision," he not only constrain lower courts, he constrain myself as well. In the real world of appellate judging, it displays more judicial restraint to adopt such a course than to announce that, "on balance," we think the law was violated here -- leaving ourselves free to say in the next case that, "on balance," it was not. It is a commonplace that the one effective check upon arbitrary judges is criticism by the bar and the academy. But it is [very difficult] to demonstrate the inconsistency of two opinions based upon a "totality of the circumstances" test only by announcing rules do we hedge ourselves in. Judges are sometimes called upon to be courageous, because they must sometimes stand up to what is generally supreme in a democracy: the popular will. Their most significant roles, in our system, are to protect the individual criminal defendant against the occasional excesses of that popular will, and to preserve the checks and balances within our constitutional system that are precisely designed to inhibit swift and complete accomplishment of that popular will. The chances that frail men and women will stand up to their unpleasant duty are greatly increased if they can
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 19 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
stand behind the solid shield of a firm, clear principle enunciated in earlier cases. It is very difficult to say that a particular convicted felon who is the object of widespread hatred must go free because, on balance, we think that excluding the defense attorney from the line-up process in this case may have prevented a fair trial. It is easier to say that our cases plainly hold that, absent exigent circumstances, such exclusion is a per se denial of due process.
The Queen v. Dudley and Stephens 14 Q.B.D 273 (1884) Facts: Four men (Dudley, Stephens, Brooks and Parker) were out in the ocean in an English yacht while there was a storm. When the yacht was damaged, they all escaped in an open boat. They had no supply of food and water except for two tins of turnips and a small turtle they caught. Stephen and Dudley decided, without the consent of Brooks, that they would kill and eat Parker since he is the youngest and weakest of them all. They fed upon Parker’s body for four days and on the fourth day they were rescued. Upon returning to land, Dudley and Stephens were arrested and brought to trial. Procedure: The jury issued a special verdict. They found that there was no greater necessity to kill Parker, than there was to kill any of the others. However, the jury was unable to decide whether the killing of Parker was indeed a felony. Issue: Are Dudley and Stephens guilty of murder for killing Richard Parker? Held: Yes. Where a private person, acting on his own judgment, takes the life of another, he is guilty of murder, unless his act can be justified by self-defense. The defendants were not protecting themselves against any act of Parker.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 20 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Ratio: The defendants were subject to terrible temptation and sufferings that may break down the bodily power of the strongest man and try his conscience, but nevertheless the defendants put a weak, innocent boy to death in order to preserve their own lives. They denied the boy any possible chance of survival. The record shows that the defendants were rescued four days after the killing of the boy, but they were not to know that they would not be rescued within hours or the next day, giving all four a decent chance to survive. If they were rescued the next day, the killing would have been unnecessary and profitless. The counsel for the defendants urges that they killed out of necessity; however, necessity of a private nature pertains to self-defense, which allows a man to take another's life in his own defense. Parker was not a threat to the defendants' lives; in fact, he was weak and could not offer any resistance. While it may have been necessary to kill Parker for their own survival, it is not an excusable or justifiable killing. This would mean that if a man was poor and without clothes, he would be permitted to steal another man's money and clothes in order to save himself. The only justifiable homicide of a private nature is the defense against the force of a man's person, house, or goods. This necessity must be inevitable. While the court in this case did not deem the acts of the defendants devilish, they still constitute murder.
Law and Morality By Altman A Common Saying Natural law is a corpus of moral truths that we can all discover. It is a name for the point of intersection between law and morals. Distinguish this from positive law, which refers to any system of laws created by humans, only with validity over a particular territory and its inhabitants. Judgment at Nuremberg Two distinct lines of argument against the prosecution and conviction of Nuremberg defendants:
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 21 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
1) Trial should follow the rule of law. A trial is a proceeding purporting to conform to the rule of law, summary execution has no such pretense. No valid legal rules were in effect that outlawed “crimes against humanity.” So the principle of “no crime without a law was violated. The Nuremberg Charter did outlaw crimes against humanity, but was adopted after the crimes took place, thus violating principles against the retroactive application of law. International treaties didn’t make individuals criminally liable, and there were no specific punishments. Prior to the Charter, international treaties didn’t criminalize conspiracy, especially to the extent of the Charter making every conspirator responsible for every act carried out. The tribunal was not an impartial one, since the judges came from countries Germany had just fought. New rules were not equally enforced against other acts (Hiroshima, Nagasaki) that could also be seen as war crimes. How do you define “war of aggression?” There would be a morass of historical and moral questions. So, considering all of this, it was a political trial where the victors used their superior power. 2) A sovereign power cannot be legally limited by any superior power. There is no global sovereign who enforces international treaties, so “international law” can’t really be authoritative and binding. Under German law as it existed during the Nazi regime, the defendants had not acted illegally. Acts of state are acts of the sovereign. These acts cannot be illegal, because the sovereign decides what is legal and illegal. Complying with commands that come from the sovereign cannot be a crime. •
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Justification of the trial: Several international treaties, including some to which Germany was a party, renounced aggressive war. So this declared what the international community had previously agreed were crime. The charge of crimes against humanity were part and parcel of the Nazi plan to wage aggressive war and commit war crimes by exterminating Jews, Gypsies, etc. Doesn’t matter where the judges are from, as long as they are independent and willing to listen to both sides, and to render a judgment based on law and evidence. (this is evidenced by fact that three defendants were acquitted, and some not guilty on all counts) Only the most culpable got death sentences. •
•
•
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 22 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
•
•
Important to make public for historical purposes all of the atrocities committed by the Nazis. No one could doubt after all of the evidence that it was a horrifying campaign of aggression and genocide. Sovereign states are obligated under international law. The rule of law must be extended to the international community.
Nature Law Theory According to Hugo de Groot (Grotius) in 17 th century (1583-1645), natural law would be the same even if God did not exist. Certain things are intrinsically wrong, whether or not God decrees them. On the other hand, Sir William Blackstone (1723-80) believes that English law derives its authority from natural law. Blackstone wrote his books on common law shortly before the United States Constitution was written. Many terms and phrases used by the framers were derived from Blackstone's works. The revolution against the British can be said to be based on natural law – look to the Declaration of Independence. “…they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights.” St. Thomas Aquinas Aquinas gave four categories: 1. Eternal law (divine reason known only to God) - principles of action God implanted in things to enable each to perform its function in the universe. 2. Natural law (participation of eternal law in rational creatures) – knowable by our natural powers of reason, guiding us toward what is good for humans. 3. Divine law (revealed in the scriptures) – the ultimate good, human salvation, not achievable in this life. 4. Hman law (supported by reason, enacted for common good) – Aquinas’s term for positive law, rules framed by the legal community for the common good of its members. Aquinas said a law that does not conform to natural or divine law is not a law at all. Is this argument a convincing one? Aquinas is confident because he knows 1) God exists; 2) God has ordained that those in charge of political communities frame laws serving the common good; and 3) the natural reasoning powers of humans lead all reasonable persons to agree on basic principles. Opponents would argue 1) there is no God; 2) even if there is, God’s existence is not something we can know, but only believe in; 3) even if we can know God exists, we don’t really know what he
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 23 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
intends from political leaders; and 4) reasonable people can disagree over fundamental ideas of good and bad. Lon L. Fuller Fuller is noted legal philosopher, who wrote The Morality of Law in 1964, discussing the connection between law and morality. His debate with H.L.A. Hart in the Harvard Law Review (Vol. 71) was of significant importance for framing the modern conflict between legal positivism and natural law. Like traditional natural law theorists, Fuller wrote of there being a threshold that must be met, or a test that must be passed, before something could be called “law.” But the test that Fuller applies is one of function and procedure and not just moral content. This is Fuller’s “inner morality of law.” It consists of a system of rules that must be met, or substantially met, if a system is to be called “law.” (A system that meets some could be considered “partly legal” and display a greater respect for principles of legality than a system that doesn’t meet the requirements at all.) (P1) the rules must be expressed in general terms; (P2) the rules must be publicly promulgated; (P3) the rules must be prospective in effect, and not retroactive; (P4) the rules must be expressed in understandable terms; (P5) the rules must be consistent with one another, and not contradictory; (P6) the rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected parties, or have the possibility of compliance;(P7) the rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them, or constancy; and (P8) the rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording. Legal Positivism Legal positivism is the view that the validity of any law can be traced to an objectively verifiable source. This rejects natural law view that law exists in some way separate from human enactment. A common factor among legal positivists is that the law as laid down should be kept separate for the purpose of study and analysis from what the law ought to be. They share the view that the most effective way to analyze and understand the law is to suspend moral judgment and establish its source. Jeremy Bentham became known as one of the most influential of the utilitarians, through his own work and that of his students. He argued the right act or policy he called "the greatest happiness principle," often referred to as the principle of utility. The greatest happiness of the greatest number is the foundation of morals and legislation." Utilitarianism is the idea that the moral worth of an action is solely determined by its contribution to overall utility, that is, its contribution to happiness or pleasure as summed among all persons. His critique of Blackstone was that the unwritten REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 24 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
common law was intrinsically vague and uncertain, and cannot provide a reliable, public standard that can reasonably be expected to guide behavior. Legal codes would diminish the power of judges to interpret the law, and remove much of the need for lawyers.
John Austin Austin was a noted British jurist and published extensively concerning the philosophy of law and jurisprudence. He was a disciple of Bentham. Laws are general commands laid down by superiors to guide the actions of those under them. These constitute positive law and impose legal obligations. This compares to laws laid down by men that are not as political superiors or in pursuit of legal rights. (Laws by analogy like laws of fashion, and by metaphor, like laws of gravity.) Those who act contrary to the rules may be punished at the hands of the political rulers. In his view, this political leader is the sovereign, defined solely in terms of power, not in terms of moral qualification. Question of what the law is and what it should be are always separate. There is no connection between legal and moral obligation. Concepts of law and legal obligation are purely “power concepts.” Austin rejects the idea of an “international law” since there is no global sovereign to issue and enforce commands. So international laws are a kind of positive morality for the international community. This will be used at Nuremberg. That brings us back to the big question – is a rule valid if it is contrary to natural law or morality? Austin thinks yes, but that doesn’t mean there aren’t situations where you might choose to disobey an immoral law. But natural law types might say that moral progress will be achieved by the rejection of unjust laws and the refusal to obey them. Would this cause social disorder and confusion? Austin would think so. Bentham pursued the idea of a single, complete law. Austin built his system on a classification of rights, but not a “complete law.” A lot of his focus applies to criminal more than civil law. Austin was also not as concerned as Bentham in checking the power of judges and lawyers. Law as command requires that there must always be a sanction that follows failure to obey a command. “smallest chance of incurring the smallest evil.”
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 25 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
H.L.A. Hart Hart is known for applying techniques of analytical and linguistic philosophy to the study of law. This is based on a logical view of concepts, as well as a focus on what words actually mean in a language. So he tried to illuminate the meaning of legal concepts, the way we deploy them, and the way we think about law and the legal system. He argues that we need to look to context – words and rules can have a number of clear meanings. His 1961 work The Concept of Law is a classic. Hart starts with human frailties, or the “minimum content of natural law”: 1. Human vulnerability – we are all susceptible to physical attacks. 2. Approximate equality – even the strongest must sleep at times. 3. Limited altruism – we are, in general, selfish. 4. Limited resources – We need food, clothing, shelter and they are limited. 5. Limited understanding and strength of will – we cannot be relied upon to cooperate with our fellow men. These require the enactment of rules to protect persons and property, and to ensure that promises are kept. Legal rules are divided into primary and secondary rules. Primary rules involve the use of violence, theft, deception, things that humans must repress to coexist in society. These impose obligations. Secondary rules are of three types: 1. Rules of change – rules that help society adapt to changing conditions by making it possible to eliminate old rules and enact new ones. These rules confer power on individuals or groups to enact legislation in accordance with certain procedures. 2. Rules of adjudication – confer authority on individuals to pass judgment mainly in cases of breaches of primary rules. This is mainly punishing the wrongdoer or making them pay damages. 3. Rules of recognition – helps people recognize the rules under which they will be held accountable. This is duty-imposing: it requires those who exercise public power (judges) to follow certain rules that are the accepted standards. Judges don’t have to like the rules, just follow them. Then, rules are either internal or external. External involves outward behavior, people acting a certain way. While internal involves the attitudes people take, like seeing deviation from the REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 26 of 27
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
rules as something to be criticized. Hart thinks the internal part is critical – there has to be social pressure to conform to rules, the rules must help maintain some aspect of society regarded as important and valuable, and sometimes requires people to act contrary to their own self interest. Hart makes lots of reference to the “money or your life” gunman. You are obliged to obey, because of the choice, but you don’t have an obligation, because no rule imposes an obligation to obey. If governments can create obligations by enacting laws, that’s different from the gunman, because he can’t create an obligation, moral, legal or otherwise.
REGINA IUSTITIAE SORORITY
Page 27 of 27
View more...
Comments