An Introduction to the Policy Process - BIRKLAND

January 30, 2017 | Author: cleber1lopes | Category: N/A
Share Embed Donate


Short Description

Download An Introduction to the Policy Process - BIRKLAND...

Description

An Introduction to the

Policy Process

This page intentionlly left blank

An Introduction to the

Policy Process Theories, Concepts, and Models of Public Policy Making Third Edition

Thomas A. Birkland ROUTLEDGE

Routledge Taylor & Francis Group

LONDAN AND NEW YORK

First published 2011 by M.E. Sharpe Published 2015 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 2011 Taylor & Francis. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Notices No responsibility is assumed by the publisher for any injury and/or damage to persons or property as a matter of products liability, negligence or otherwise, or from any use of operation of any methods, products, instructions or ideas contained in the material herein. Practitioners and researchers must always rely on their own experience and knowledge in evaluating and using any information, methods, compounds, or experiments described herein. In using such information or methods they should be mindful of their own safety and the safety of others, including parties for whom they have a professional responsibility. Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Birkland, Thomas A. An introduction to the policy process : theories, concepts, and models of public policy making / by Thomas A. Birkland. — 3rd ed. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-7656-2532-8 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Policy sciences. 2. Political planning—United States. I. Title. H97.B57 2010 320.6—dc22 2010016536

ISBN 13: 9780765625328 (pbk)

To Jim Klonoski and to Molly, Oskar, and Isaak

This page intentionlly left blank

Contents

List of Tables and Figures Preface to the Third Edition ╇ 1. ╇ 2. ╇ 3. ╇ 4. ╇ 5. ╇ 6. ╇ 7. ╇ 8. ╇ 9. 10.

ix xi

Introducing the Policy Process Elements of the Policy-Making System The Historical and Structural Contexts of Public Policy Making Official Actors and Their Roles in Public Policy Unofficial Actors and Their Roles in Public Policy Agenda Setting, Power, and Interest Groups Policies and Policy Types Policy Design, Policy Tools, and Decisions Policy Implementation, Failure, and Learning Science and Theory in the Study of Public Policy

References Index About the Author

3 25 58 92 130 168 202 228 263 287 311 325 340

vii

This page intentionlly left blank

List of Tables and Figures

Tables 1.1 1.2 1.3 1.4 3.1 3.2 3.3 4.1 4.2 6.1 7.1 7.2 7.3 8.1 8.2 8.3 8.4 9.1 10.1

Defining “Public Policy” A Public Policy Morphology Selected Disciplines That Study Public Policy Anecdotes and Evidence Article 1, Section 8 of the Constitution Elements of American Political Stability Separation (and Sharing) of Powers Measuring Legislative Activity: Bills, Amendments, Joint Resolutions, and Concurrent Resolutions in the 105th and 110th Congresses Committees in the 110th Congress Types of Causal Theories with Examples Levels of Policy Codification Actors, Stability, and Visibility of Various Policy Types Wilson’s Cost-Benefit Policy Typology Elements of Policy Design Types of Policy Tools or Instruments Characteristics of Policy Instruments Rational Comprehensive Decision Making and Bounded Rationality Explanations for Policy Failure Anecdotes and Evidence

8 14 15 17 64 76 82 95 101 193 204 211 216 231 248 251 257 274 294

Figures 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4

The Stages Model of the Policy Process A Systems Model of Politics and Policy United States Population, 1960–2007 Annual Rate of Population Growth, United States, 1960–2007 ix

26 27 29 30

x

List 2.5 2.6 2.7 2.8 2.9

of

Tables

and

Figures

Portion of U.S. Population by Age Groups 30 Proportion of Population by Select Ethnic or Racial Group 31 Labor Force Participation, Men and Women, 1975–2008 32 Median Family Income, by Household Type, 1949–2007 33 Proportionate Answers to “Most Important Problem” 37 Question, 1964–2004 2.10 Answer to the “Right Track” Poll Question 39 2.11 Proportion of Voting Age Population Participating in Elections, 1932–2008 40 2.12 Presidential Approval Ratings, Harry Truman through George W. Bush 41 2.13 Presidential and Congressional Approval Ratings, 1990–2008 42 2.14 U.S. Gross Domestic Product, Constant (2000) Dollars, 1930–2007 43 2.15 Federal Budget Deficits and Surpluses, Constant (year 2000) 45 Dollars, 1940–2014 2.16 Federal Budget Deficits and Debt as Percent of Gross 45 Domestic Product, 1940–2014 2.17 Monthly Unemployment Rate, January 1948–November 2009 47 2.18 Income Distribution in the United States, 1967–2006 48 2.19 Comparative Income Distribution (Gini Index), OECD 48 States and Overall European Union 4.1 The Legislative and Regulatory Process 99 4.2 Overall Federal Outlays, 1940–2014, Current and Constant Dollars 113 4.3 Federal Government Outlays as Percentage of GDP, 1940–2014 113 4.4 Federal Government Outlays Per Capita, Constant Dollars, 1940–2014 114 4.5 Total Number of State and Local Government Employees, 1992–2006 114 4.6 Number of Federal Civilian Employees, 1981–2010 115 4.7 Comparative Growth of Federal Budget and Federal 115 Employment, 1981–2010 5.1 Election Turnout, President and House of Representatives 132 5.2 Number of U.S. Newspapers, 1940–2008 146 5.3 Newspaper Circulation, Daily and Sunday, 1940–2008 146 5.4 Number of Daily Viewers of Evening Network TV News, 1980–2006 147 5.5 Trends in Home Internet Adoption, 2000–2009 152 5.6 Most Commonly Visited Types of Internet News Sites, February 2008 153 6.1 Levels of the Agenda 171 6.2 News Coverage of Terrorism, by New York Times “Desk,” 1990–2002 182 6.3 Media and Congressional Attention to Terrorism, 1990–2002 183 10.1 Kingdon’s Streams Metaphor 298 10.2 The Advocacy Coalition Framework 299 10.3 A Framework for Institutional Analysis 304

Preface to the Third Edition

Why I Wrote This Book It has long been said that one never really gets to know a subject until one has to teach it. If this is true, it’s doubly true that one really learns a subject when one writes a book about it. This is not to say, certainly, that this book represents all there is to know about public policy. Rather, I have written this book to be a starting point in what I hope you will find to be an interesting and fruitful lifetime of thinking about and engaging in public policy making. Most public policy texts tend to deemphasize theories of public policy in favor of more topic-centered discussions. A standard textbook in public policy contains one or two chapters on basic theoretical or structural aspects of policy making, and then devotes the remaining chapters (between half and seven-eighths of the typical book) to particular policy areas, such as “health policy” or “criminal justice policy” or “national security policy.” One of my goals in writing this book was to fill in the gap between the end of the theoretical section and the case studies that are staples in these textbooks. Striking the right balance between the theoretical and the substantive or “practical” is a challenge throughout the social sciences, and I hope this book helps teachers balance these two important aspects of the public policy curriculum. To that end, I have included many examples in the book, based on my research or on interesting things I’ve learned about from my colleagues, in the newspapers, or en route to learning about something else. Such serendipitous discoveries make the study of public policy fresh and fascinating, and I hope I’ve conveyed some of that excitement in this book. Another motivation for this book was my interest in providing a primer in public policy for advanced undergraduates or graduate students in courses and programs that are not primarily about public policy, but in which an understanding of public policy is particularly useful. I taught in and codirected such a program at the University at Albany. The university’s Biodiversity and Conservation policy program, which is housed in the Biological Sciences department, is a Masters of Science program that includes a great deal of conservation biology and public xi

xii

Preface

to the

Third Edition

policy, including a required course in politics and policy and a course in the policy of biodiversity and environmental conservation. For many this course is initially quite daunting, as most students have a background in biology or other sciences but little exposure to public policy ideas. In particular, the “messiness” and indeterminacy of the policy process is often troubling to students with a science background. My goal in writing this book is to provide an overview of the policy process that acknowledges this messiness while showing how policy scholars have developed ways that we can think more systematically about this seemingly chaotic process. I also hope people who are returning to policy studies or are seeking to teach themselves about the process will find this book useful. Returning students, and those who are pursuing graduate studies after some years of professional experience, will find that policy studies grow and change quite quickly. This book is intended to help students, whether they are studying in a formal educational institution or on their own, to become current with some important ideas in the study of policy. I urge all readers to think of this book as a beginning or a supplement, and certainly not the final word on public policy. The reference section of this book contains short descriptions of many of the materials cited here, and I hope you have the chance to read the materials that interest you and to continue your engagement with this material. I’ve attempted to write this book in a somewhat more conversational style than most textbooks. My goal is to provide a readable text and a useful reference that can be used to supplement or clarify concepts learned in classes, textbooks, and in daily contact with the policy process, including personal experience, the news media, and direct participation in policy making. The book includes an extensive glossary of terms used in policy studies to better serve as such a reference, and the aforementioned annotated references serve as a guide to some of the classic works in the field of public policy. What’s Ahead This book starts with an overview of the idea of policy studies as both an academic discipline and an “applied” science. I review my thinking on what makes policy studies an appropriate endeavor for scientific study, even when the subject of study seems to be so irrational and even when we are the subject of the discipline itself! Chapter 2 is new to this edition, and offers an overview of key social, economic, and demographic trends that influence and will influence policy making for some time to come. I include this because in both the first and second editions I described the nature and substance of the environment in which policy is made. One aspect of the environment is the various trends that are reviewed in this new chapter. Most students of political science and of public policy have a broad sense of the ideas

Preface

to the

Third Edition

and trends reflected in the graphs contained in chapter 2, but I think there will be some surprises and interesting insights as well. Chapter 3 focuses on the historical and structural features of American politics that influence public policy; this chapter contrasts with chapter 2 in that it describes a more stable set of external variables. This division between dynamic and changing environmental variables reflects Paul Sabatier’s thinking in his Advocacy Coalition Framework in the policy process. This discussion is particularly important, as most political scientists and policy scholars acknowledge the importance of the structure and rules under which the game, if you will, of politics is played. Students are often taught—or at least are allowed to conclude—that the rules and structure are neutral, and that anyone who wants to play the game can get involved in politics and “make a difference” in their community. I argue, following the lead of key students of politics, that the founders of our constitutional order purposefully designed our system to favor commercial interests and property holders and to make it hard for mass publics to mobilize and seek a share of the wealth. For those interested in policy change, the structure is troubling, for it suggests that mass movements and participatory democracy are not likely to carry the day in policy debates. But, as highlighted throughout this book, there are circumstances under which policy can change, and sometimes policy changes quite rapidly. Indeed, one of the most fascinating aspects of politics comes in understanding when, against the odds, policy change based on mass mobilization is possible. And, of course, not all change is welcome, and liberals and conservatives alike have engaged in attempts—often aided by the structure of our system—to slow down policy change. I draw no normative conclusion here—we can simply observe that the system is resistant to change, as current debates over health care reform demonstrate, to the frustration of some and the relief of others. The various institutions and people that make public policy are described in chapters 4 and 5. Chapter 4 describes the official or institutional actors in the process—the legislative, executive, and judiciary. Chapter 5 continues this discussion with the unofficial actors, such as interest groups and media, and then outlines the ways in which we think about how all the actors come together—in “iron triangles,” subgovernments, and issue networks—to debate and negotiate policy alternatives. Groups, power, and agenda setting are reviewed in chapter 6. This is discussed at some length, as agenda setting is perhaps the most important stage of the policy process. It is at this stage that groups exercise political power to achieve their goals, either by promoting change or blocking it. The use of power in politics is subtle and complex, particularly in our political system. Understanding of what power is, how it is acquired, and how it is used to prevent issues from gaining attention is a key to understanding why any political system does some things while not doing others, even in the face of obvious needs or logic that would seem to compel a “superior” course of action. Chapter 7 then describes several different ways one can categorize the substance

xiii

xiv

Preface

to the

Third Edition

of policies, and how the various actors make decisions on which policies to pursue. Like so much in public policy studies, these descriptions of policy types are not final—they are sometimes illogical and often make the process of categorizing policies more confusing than the value of the analytic payoff. But the policy types I review in chapter 7 are, I believe, primarily useful as a way of stimulating thinking about what governments do, and what we ask governments to do. The type of policy in question often influences the design of policies intended to address policy problems. Thus, chapter 8 considers issues of policy design and the nature of the various policy tools or instruments that we can use to mitigate or solve society’s problems. Closely related to policy design and tool choice is policy implementation and arguments of failure, which I discuss in chapter 9. Policy implementation is a wellstudied aspect of the policy process, which considers the oft-forgotten work that must come after the excitement of policy enactment has passed. Implementation—putting a program into effect—is often as difficult and contentious as policy design and enactment, and in some cases is more difficult to manage. Because of the difficulties inherent in policy design and implementation, many people will claim that policies have failed to meet their goals. In chapter 9, I examine policy failure by outlining the various ways in which any policy can be said to be a failure. The complexity of policy making, with interconnectedness of policy impacts but disjointed policy design, makes real or claimed failure almost inevitable based on how one defines failure. Chapter 10 puts all these elements of policy making together by considering modern theories of the policy process. In this edition, I have focused more on the idea of policy science as social science in this chapter, moving some of the material that formerly appeared in chapter 1 to here. I think this helps ground the discussion of theory. By exploring theories and thinking of the policy process as a “system,” the inputs to and outputs from the political system are summarized and discussed in terms of their relationship to the political system, or what is often called “the black box” in systems models. The second half of the chapter discusses different and complementary ways of looking inside the black box; most of these models of policy making are at the forefront of current policy theory. Public Policy in the Early Twenty-First Century When this book was first written, the Clinton administration was coming to an end. Eight years of relatively robust economic growth was continuing, the Internet boom seemed, to some, an unlimited engine of growth and innovation, and Americans felt reasonably secure at home and abroad. The end of the Cold War gave Americans the luxury to once again turn inward, for the first time since the dark days just before World War II. This is not to say that the nation had no problems; indeed, continued increases in health care costs, concerns over the long-term solvency of social security,

Preface

to the

Third Edition

and middle-class worries about college tuition, the quality of public schools, and the availability of good jobs continued to challenge Americans. But these domestic issues dominated, for the most part, foreign policy. There were certainly important foreign policy issues in those years, what with the new post–Cold War world, wars in the Balkans, the genocide in Rwanda, and the emergence of China and India as world economic and political powers. But, as usual, Americans were most concerned about the state of the economy and the future of the nation. In many ways, times now are no different from what they were in 2000—the economy remains by far the most important issue on the agenda. But Americans are also deeply concerned about health care, the environment, education, and climate change—indeed, the gamut of issues that one could study as a student of public policy. More to the point, the issues in the United States invite the active interest and participation of many people, including the readers of this book. The context in which you might participate in policy making is undeniably challenging. To be sure, America was not isolationist in the 1990s, and the first Bush administration and then the Clinton administration, both in the glow of the apparent success of the Gulf War and still in the shadow of the failures of the Vietnam era, attempted to find a way to use American economic, cultural, and military power. Depending on one’s perspective, these powers can be used to promote American values of democracy, liberty, free markets, and individualism to all people in the world; the images of the physical as well as the psychological collapse of the Berlin wall symbolize this triumph of American—indeed, Western—values over the drab, collectivist tendencies of communism. Others may be alarmed that America, without a counterweight in the world, has unfettered power to shape the world, not in its image—which stresses liberty and human rights—but in its interests, which often collide with the values on which the nation was founded. Thus, the nation’s dependence on Middle Eastern oil has resulted in the United States supporting intolerant and repressive regimes that do not share American values of religious tolerance and democracy. Many of these issues were on Americans’ minds when those who voted did so in 2000. In one of the closest elections in history, and in one of those odd quirks of our system, where the winner of the most votes still loses in the electoral college, power peacefully, as it has for over 200 years, shifted from one person and one party to another. Domestic policy seemed to dominate discussion in the early days of the Bush administration. Talk of tax cuts, of stimulating the economy, of dealing with the bursting of the “Internet bubble” dominated much public discussion. All this, of course, changed on one day in September 2001. For weeks and months after September 11 it seemed to all of us that everything had changed. Americans were less concerned about domestic politics. We were confronted with the possibility of catastrophic terrorism of the sort that could kill millions of people. As we have learned since September 11, this threat had always existed, but the September 11 attacks were surely the most dramatic and shock-

xv

xvi

Preface

to the

Third Edition

ing example of this sort of terrorism. Concerns were raised about the possibility of nuclear, biological, and chemical terrorism. These worries were fanned by the terrorist (or at least, terroristic) mailings of anthrax to members of Congress and the news media; while apparently unrelated to the September 11 attacks, these incidents illustrated the threats we faced. And we were reminded of the specter of terrorism by the attempted bombing of an airplane as it landed in Detroit in late 2009. Of course, for many Americans, what was once called “the global war on terrorism” is still front and center in their lives; thousands of soldiers, sailors, airmen, and marines and their families and friends follow the progress of our troops in Iraq and Afghanistan. But for the vast majority of Americans, the primary subject of conversation between 2007 and now has been the state of the economy. House prices softened in mid-2007 as the “real estate bubble” started to deflate, only to burst with the credit crisis of 2008–2009. The credit crisis itself started, as crises often do, with Â�gradually accreting indicators of problems within the financial system, culminating in the near collapse of some financial institutions, leading, in late 2008, to the government’s decisions to intervene to prop up institutions deemed “too big to fail.” The costs of the “bailout” of financial institutions, and of automakers GM and Chrysler, helped cause the federal budget deficit to balloon to near-record levels. Huge deficits, and consequent government actions to raise revenues and cut expenses, could have a significant effect both on the economy and on the very substance of public policy for years to come. With many states in worse financial shape than the federal government, and with the federal government providing extra funding to states for only a limited time, the growth of federal budget deficits and cutbacks in all government services at all levels seem inevitable. Yet people continue to demand public services from government, particularly since the federal government expanded heavily into everyday life in the 1930s in response to the Great Depression. All these matters highlight how terrorism, the economy, the price of gasoline (a national obsession in 2008), and many other matters influence other realms of public policy. The September 11 attacks may have changed, for a while at least, the agenda in American politics (agenda setting is described in chapter 6). But, as I noted in the preface to this book’s second edition, the attacks did not change the policy process that this book describes; nor has the financial crisis. Indeed, the policy process—and the actors and institutions that drive it—remain as robust as ever, even if some features of it, such as partisanship in Congress and arcane rules like the filibuster, seem to greatly impede change. In the spring of 2002 I taught a special topics course called “The September 11 Project,” in which we explored and attempted to understand the reaction to the September 11 attacks within the policy process. In that course we considered the influence of the attacks on the media and the congressional agenda—and these impacts were profound indeed. Consider the response to September 11. Clearly, this was no ordinary day: govern-

Preface

to the

Third Edition

ment offices shut down in New York and Washington, the stock exchange closed and didn’t reopen until September 17 (because the stock exchange was very near Ground Zero and the area secured after the attacks), and the president did not return directly from Florida to Washington until the scale of the attacks was better understood and his safety could be assured. But through all of this the key institutions of American government and the policy process—federal, state, and local governments, the media, the private sector—behaved pretty much as one with a basic understanding of American politics would expect. Congress, which reconvened soon after the attacks, passed resolutions condemning the attacks and praising the first responders. Congress also held hearings to find out how it was possible that four planes could be hijacked in one day and used as guided missiles to attack Americans. The president recommended legislation to Congress to provide for greater law enforcement power—the Patriot Act—and to authorize military responses to the terrorists based in Afghanistan. This legislation passed very quickly, as did legislation reforming the airline security system, because while the constitutional order in the United States tends to prize deliberation over rapid action, it is also true that the system can react quickly if properly induced to do so. Meanwhile, people and organizations began to take steps or at least think about taking steps to protect life and property in the face of terrorist attacks. Searches at airports became more stringent, and passengers became more vigilant about suspicious behavior. Certainly there were many hasty or even hysterical reactions after the September 11 attacks, such as when Arabs, Muslims, or people who looked like Arabs or Muslims were attacked, and, in at least one case, tragically murdered. But there were also commonsense steps taken by many people to be more observant and vigilant, which paid off in December 2001 when passengers on a flight from Paris to Miami thwarted an attempt by a terrorist to detonate a bomb hidden in his shoe. While we have since learned that much of the organization and management of counterterrorism in the United States was rather flawed—the FBI and CIA came under particular scrutiny—these agencies swung into action quickly after the events, and have had some success in tracking down terrorists and their supporters as well as shutting off at least some of their financing. The details of the “war on terrorism”—and whether or not the term “war” is meant literally or metaphorically—are best left to the experts in this field. My intention here is to reinforce the idea that even during a crisis as grave as the September 11 attacks, the policy process worked pretty much like it did before September 11. This is not to say that nothing changed after September 11. It is, however, to suggest that, in spite of the often overheated rhetoric, not everything changed after September 11. Rather, the policy-making environment, our national agenda, and the sorts of policies needed to address the newly revealed problems have changed. And there is reason to believe that policies will change in other areas as well. It is a testament to the capacity and resilience of the American political and policy system that some issues remain important even in the face of challenges like

xvii

xviii

Preface

to the

Third Edition

the financial crisis, terrorism, and environmental disasters. The Obama administration felt able to tackle health care issues, and before then, the George W. Bush administration had expanded Medicare coverage for elderly Americans. Education remains an important issue as well, as the Obama administration’s “Race to the Top” program atempts to build and improve upon the Bush program known as No Child Left Behind. Environmental policy remains as contentious as ever. The Bush administration substantially weakened environmental protections; but as the price of oil skyrocketed in 2008 to historic highs, even adjusting for inflation, greater interest in alternative fuels and ways of powering cars rose on the agenda, leading to, among other things, tax-credits for buying hybrid cars, and to a significant but short-lived jump in the price of corn, from which ethanol is made. In 2010, the so-called BP oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico returned the debate over energy policy to arguments over environmental impacts, and not just oil prices or national security matters. The scientific evidence on global climate change suggests, to many, that new approaches to energy must be undertaken; and national, state, and local governments have embarked on ambitious plans to promote biofuels as well as wind, solar, and nuclear power. Many environmentalists have begun to embrace new forms of nuclear power, which shows how changes in technology and in context can cause interested parties to modify or even abandon positions that were once immutable. Because we are a large, generally wealthy, and powerful nation founded on a set of principles that people hold dear—democracy, constitutional government, the rule of law, and liberty, to name a few—these political controversies will persist in American politics, not because we enjoy arguing (although some of us do enter politics for this reason!) but because many people passionately care about these issues, and believe just as passionately that their ideas are the ones that will work best. This passion was evident during the 2008 presidential debates and the 2010 midterm elections. When you strip away the candidates’ debate styles and demeanors, what was left was a remarkable discussion of ideas and how to translate those ideas into policies that benefit the broadest range of Americans. *** This edition of the book retains the organization and most of the text of the two previous editions. In the second edition I introduced Questions for Review, Reflection, and Research, which are designed to challenge you to think more carefully about the issues raised in each chapter, and to engage in the kinds of research questions that make the study of public policy so interesting. I have designed the questions to be provocative and, I hope, fun to explore. The research activities I have included are a direct reflection of my own best experiences with research, and I think you will enjoy them. I have also included Additional Readings at the end of each chapter. I do not list a great many additional readings, although I have added a few since

Preface

to the

Third Edition

the last edition, but my goal is to focus on classic works that I believe that students of politics and policy should know, if only as part of the intellectual history of our field. Advanced undergraduates and graduate students will find this feature useful, and their teachers may wish to use these Additional Readings as a starting point for explorations beyond this textbook. Finally, you will note some significant organizational changes. As mentioned earlier, a new chapter 2, titled “Elements of the Policy-Making System,” brings forward the idea of policy inputs and outputs and the environment in which the policy system operates. The chapter describes, more extensively than in previous editions, the key social, political, economic, and demographic factors that are shaping the policy environment in which choices will be made in coming years. I have also moved a great deal of what might be called the “philosophy of science” material as it relates to policy studies from chapter 1 to the discussion of theory generally, and contemporary policy theories in particular, in chapter 10. Finally, I have written new examples and case studies throughout the book to better reflect recent issues for which students may have personal memories and frames of reference; after all, the Exxon Valdez oil spill, one of the key examples in the first two editions, happened before many of the readers of this book were born! In the nearly ten years since I first began writing this book, I have been privileged to hear from many colleagues, students, and friends about how they used this book. I greatly value their comments and suggestions. The first edition would not have been possible without the extraordinary help and support of Scott Barclay, Brian Davis, Mark Donovan, Ben Fordham, Jennifer Krausnick, Regina Lawrence, Peter May, Henrik Minassians, Bob Nakamura, and Beryl Radin. In the second edition, I acknowledged the debt I still owe to my students in my undergraduate course, Introduction to Public Policy, and in my graduate courses in Politics and Policy and Biodiversity and Conservation Policy at the University at Albany. Since joining the faculty at North Carolina State, I have pored over this book several times with advanced graduate students and undergraduates. My students are thoughtful readers and careful critics, and many of the questions for discussion in this book have derived from the questions they raised in lecture and seminar, particularly my spring 2009 policy process doctoral seminar. I owe particular thanks to members of my spring 2010 graduate Policy Process course, including Shelley Gonzalez, Autumn Guin, Seth Palmer, Thomas Sutton, James Kribs, Tim Hamm, and Sarah DeYoung, for their very careful reading of (and editorial changes to) the DARE case study in chapter 1. Editorial assistance was provided by Adam Bunch, and Sarah Waterman, who was a student in my Albany course and who took one of my courses at North Carolina State, and Kristin O’Donovan, my research assistant, who patiently read several drafts of this book— they may know this material better than I do! At Albany, two teaching assistants, Paul Alexander and Michael Deegan, created the core of the definitions of the key terms and the discussion questions. Both Paul

xix

xx

Preface

to the

Third Edition

and Michael are careful and enthusiastic teachers of public policy, and I learned a great deal from them. To those friends and colleagues whose help I have failed to acknowledge, I thank you all for your support, ideas, and friendship. Those who read prefaces (you know who you are!) noted that I dedicated the first edition of this book to my wife Molly, and the second edition to our sons Oskar and Ike. I still dedicate this to them for their love and patience. But this edition, in particular, is dedicated to my mentor, Dr. James Klonoski, who passed away in 2009 after many decades of teaching and research at my alma mater, the University of Oregon. Dr. Klonoski was a legendary teacher of politics to generations of Oregon students, many of whom went on to professions in law, research, and politics. While I don’t know that I could ever be the inspirational force that Dr. Klonoski was in the classroom, I hope that his spirit of curiosity, passion, and commitment to motivating people to be involved with politics and public life is at least partially reflected in this book.

An Introduction to the

Policy Process

This page intentionlly left blank

1

CHAPTER

Introducing the Policy Process Chapter at a Glance Overview Politics and the Policy Process What Is Public Policy? Ideas and Problems in the Policy Process What Makes Public Policy Public? Why Do We Study Public Policy? The Place of Policy Studies in the Social Sciences Evidence and Argument in the Policy Process Case Study: Does the DARE Program Work? Summary Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading Overview This book is about how public policy is made in the United States. As a book on a particular field of the social sciences, it goes beyond simple description to introduce you to theories and ways of thinking about the policy process. This is not to deny the value of understanding the substance of the many policies themselves. I am sure that you, your family, and friends have often puzzled over why the government does some of the things it does, particularly when those things are contradictory. Why does, for example, the government provide support for tobacco farming and discourage people from smoking? Why does the government give people tax breaks for buying houses? Why don’t renters get similar tax breaks? Or landlords, who could pass the savings on to renters? Why doesn’t the United States have a comprehensive health insurance system? Why is primary responsibility for the police or education held by the state and local governments and not the federal government? Is regulation of consumer product safety better for public safety, or would greater reliance on the market and information work better to promote public safety? These are questions that motivate many people of all ideological and political persuasions to understand public problems and find solutions to them.

3

4

hapter

1

One of the most interesting reasons to study public policy is that public policy making is about problem solving. As this book outlines, we can study public problems and their solutions as participants in the public policy process. But understanding the substance of policy, while interesting in its own right, can only take us so far if we are interested in the social scientific aspects of the policy process. Many scholars have developed theories of how the public policy process works: that is, theories about how public problems are discovered and how policies are created to address those problems. This book introduces theories, frameworks, and models of the policy process. This focus on theory sets this book apart from many other textbooks on public policy. Most textbooks contain a thin treatment of theories of public policy— and the relation of these theories to broader social scientific questions—and then provide a series of case studies on “environmental policy” or “energy policy” or “national security policy.” There are many good books about all manner of policy issues, and I hope you find them in the subjects that you find most interesting. This book focuses on the process by which policies are made. An Introduction to the Policy Process describes how policy is shaped by social, institutional, political, economic, and other contexts. Much of this description is orthodox in political science; the discussion of the branches of government, of the Constitution, of the various groups and institutions, and the like, is similar to that found in introductory American politics textbooks. The difference is that I am interested in how groups, institutions, and structures work to solve problems through making public policies. And, in keeping with the interdisciplinary nature of policy studies, this book owes a debt to sociology, history, economics, public administration, and other disciplines. Politics and the Policy Process The study of public policy is generally considered an important aspect of political science, so it’s useful to start by asking, “What is politics?” One way to conceive of politics is as a process by which societies help figure out how to organize and regulate themselves; that is, how to govern themselves. What makes this “political” is its location in the public sphere, where decisions are made by the public to address issues that affect people in communities; all manner of other decisions are made in corporations, in families, and in other organizations that we do not consider to be part of the public sphere. The public sphere can be as small as an apartment complex, or a small village, or as large as a whole nation, or even the world. Whatever the scale, public policies address problems that are public, or, more importantly, that some number of people think should be public instead of private. Indeed, a key feature of politics and policy decision making is the very definition of what problems are public and which are private. While these questions may, at the outset, seem simple, they are in fact very complex. People have been trying to figure out how to work together in political

Introducing

the

Policy Process

communities for thousands of years. Philosophers such as Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle sought to understand how one can behave in a political context to help people make decisions within human societies, while reducing the possibility of political conflict turning destructive or violent.1 “Modern” political theory begins in the fifteenth century when Niccolò Machiavelli wrote The Prince for his patron, an Italian nobleman, to provide him with practical political advice. Machiavelli argued that if we understand and plan the political actions we take in pursuit of our goals, we are better prepared to seize the political opportunities that arise in the normal course of political life. The Prince depended on postulates—statements about how we think the political world works—and then argues that we should compare these postulates to the conduct of “real-world” politics. Developing and testing postulates about how the political world works is consistent with the way people thought of the human and natural world during the Enlightenment, when thinkers turned toward modern methods of scientific inquiry in hopes of better understanding all manner of phenomena—including physics, medicine, law, and politics.2 During this era of great scientific, political, and social foment, a host of brilliant thinkers turned their focus to understanding the use of power—a basic element of politics—in social settings. In continuing one’s exploration of political philosophy, one might read Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau on the nature of social and political interactions under what we call “the social contract.” In the American context, one would do well to read work by the French nobleman Charles-Louis de Secondat, baron de Montesquieu, who greatly influenced the most influential thinkers in America at the time of the American Revolution and the ratification of the Constitution; his work is best known for the idea of the separation of powers into the legislative, executive, and judicial branches, described in chapters 2 and 3. These ideas are reflected in The Federalist, a collection of essays written by Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, and John Jay to persuade New Yorkers to ratify the U.S. Constitution. The Federalist is still studied to gain insights into the meaning of the Constitution and the thoughts of its framers. To this foundation in American political thought you might add the writings of, among others, George Washington, Samuel Adams, Thomas Jefferson, Abraham Lincoln, and Woodrow Wilson. All of these statesmen sought to explain, to themselves and their countrymen, how our nation came to be, and how, in their minds, it was the best equipped to preserve individual rights and harness the creative power that ultimately made the United States one of the richest and most powerful countries in the world. European thinkers like Karl Marx and Max Weber sought to understand how people organize their societies, and how the socially and politically strong can, by accident or design, ignore the desires of the politically weak. From there we can move to modern theorists and philosophers such as John Dewey, who studied the question of knowledge and learning in social life, and John Rawls, whose major work, A Theory of Justice,3 sought to understand fundamental questions of fairness.

5

Enlightenment. Term used to describe a philosophic movement of the early eighteenth century, in which numerous theorists and philosophers developed new political and social philosophies based on reason and on insights from the natural sciences. The Enlightenment developed the thinking that spurred the American and French Revolutions, among other changes.

6

politics. In this book, I define politics the same way that Harold Lasswell does: the process by which society determines who gets what, when they get it, and how they get it.

hapter

1

Postmodern philosophers like Michel Foucault offer powerful challenges to social contract theory and explain how people come to be dominated by power structures beyond their control.4 These theorists have all contributed to our understanding of politics and social interactions. Their ideas help us to understand the historic and modern ways of thinking about the relationships between our governments and ourselves. All this thinking still doesn’t provide a concise definition of “politics,” because such a definition is difficult to produce. Harold Lasswell defines politics as “who gets what, when, and how.”5 This definition is simple, but we can discern on its own terms three essential aspects of politics: competition to gain certain resources, sometimes at others’ expense; the need to cooperate to make decisions; and the nature of political power. Let’s look at the ways the word politics is defined in Merriam-Webster’s online dictionary (www.merriam-webster.com). Here are two that I find particularly interesting: “the art or science of government” and “political activities characterized by artful and often dishonest practices.” (This dictionary defines artful as skillful or wily.) Many people focus on the artful or seemingly dishonest aspects of politics. They accuse people of “playing politics,” as if they engage in the process simply to gain personal or group advantages and not for any particular policy goals that would broadly benefit society. The negative sense of the term is reflected in a Google News search I did while writing this section. Using the search term “playing politics with,” I found the following headlines: • GOP Now Playing Politics with Kennedy’s Funeral • Justice Department Again Accused of Playing Politics with Cases • Missouri Families Demand Representative Blunt to Stop Playing Politics with Healthcare Reform • Playing Politics with Terrorism • Playing Politics with School Names (A story from Dallas, Texas, involving an effort to name two schools after Barack Obama and Sonia Sotomayor.) The process does seem to be tawdry to many people. Clearly, there are great concerns about the motivations and honesty of politicians and lobbyists. The influence of interest group money, particularly from big business and, to a lesser extent, organized labor, is a point of considerable concern. The legislative process often seems arcane and designed to be opaque so that ordinary people cannot understand or participate in politics. But the problem with claims of “playing politics” is that such an accusation can be countered with the statement that one is simply “acting in the public interest,” with no definitive answer emerging. Furthermore, the use of the term “politics” in this way reduces the word to something with a negative

Introducing

the

Policy Process

connotation, which is not the most fruitful way to think about politics. The careful study of politics and policy should not rely on analysis borne of frustration. Rather, as students of the policy process—which is a bit different from our roles as citizens—we need to carefully and scientifically understand why it is that money is so important in politics, why legislative processes can seem so confusing and slow, and whether and to what extent politics as currently practiced really works as a way of organizing our society. But while we can question our system and recognize that democratic or representative democracy, as practiced in the United States and in other world democracies may not be perfect, it also has significant advantages over autocracy and dictatorship, which is why Winston Churchill once defined democracy as “the worst form of government except for all the others.”6 With this in mind it remains useful to consider politics as, in the dictionary’s terms, “the art or science of government.” Politics is therefore a profession unto itself and an object of study. As such, it is the “the total complex of relations between people living in a society,” as defined by Merriam-Webster.com. What does this have to do with public policy? The study of public policy is the study of how we translate the popular will into practice. Of course, this is a simplification—the nature of the popular will is itself highly debatable—but it’s a good general way of considering what we study. What Is Public Policy? While the study of politics has a long history, the systematic study of public policy as we understand it is a fairly recent discipline. Daniel McCool argues that modern policy studies began in 1922, when political scientist Charles Merriam sought to connect the theory and practice of politics to understanding the actual activities of government. But McCool also notes that “the study of public policy did not suddenly spring into existence in the 1950s and 1960s.” The classic literature that founded policy studies—including much that is discussed in this book—is only about fifty years old, beginning with Harold Lasswell’s call for the development of a distinctive policy science.7 Because the field of policy studies is so new, many of the fundamentals of the policy sciences have only begun to be well understood in the last twenty years or so. Considerable debate remains over whether there is one coherent set of principles that can govern the study and understanding of what we call the public policy process.8 As in every field of endeavor, the definition of key terms and ideas is often very important, but it also can lead to considerable contention. There are many possible ways to define public policy; this section provides some reasons to pick one particular definition over another. In academic studies of policy, we offer definitions of public policy to understand the shape of the field we seek to study. For many people, defining public policy helps them define their own role in policy making, as well as that of the organization they work for. As I was writing this chapter for the first

7

8 Chapter 1 Table 1.1 Defining “Public Policy” Definition

Author

“The term public policy always refers to the actions of government and the intentions that determine those actions.” “Public policy is the outcome of the struggle in government over who gets what.” “Whatever governments choose to do or not to do.” “Public policy consists of political decisions for implementing programs to achieve societal goals.” “Stated most simply, public policy is the sum of government activities, whether acting directly or through agents, as it has an influence on the life of citizens.”

Clarke E. Cochran et al.a Clarke E. Cochran et al. Thomas Dyeb Charles L. Cochran and Eloise F. Malonec B.Guy Petersd

Clarke E. Cochran et al., American Public Policy: An Introduction. 6th ed. (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999). Thomas R. Dye, Understanding Public Policy. 7th ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1992). c Charles L. Cochran and Eloise F. Malone, Public Policy: Perspectives and Choices (New York: McGraw Hill, 1995). d B. Guy Peters, American Public Policy: Promise and Performance (Chappaqua, NY: Chatham House/Seven Rivers, 1999). a

b

edition of this book, a member of the policy analysis office of a New York State agency called me. The agency was engaging in a strategic planning initiative; to do so it needed to establish its mission—its very reason for existence. Because this agency influences taxation, spending, and government performance assessment— that is, public policy in the broad sense—the caller was particularly interested in defining the term public policy, so that her agency could know better how public policy relates to its work. The analyst ran through a list of the classic public policy texts, and asked if these were good sources of a definition of public policy. There are many good sources for such a definition, and I urged her to look at these sources because of scholars’ lack of a consensus definition of public policy. Thomas Dye argues that this search for a definition of public policy can degenerate into a word game that, eventually, adds little more understanding. It may be fruitless to look for one particular definition of public policy, and it is certainly not useful to continue to develop more definitions. I suggested to the caller that she review the texts and adopt a definition that the agency felt made the most sense in its particular context. Table 1.1 provides some examples of the definitions of public policy that the caller could draw from, and some strengths and weaknesses of these definitions. No single definition may ever be developed, but we can discern key attributes of public policy: • Policy is made in response to some sort of problem that requires attention. • Policy is made on the “public’s” behalf. • Policy is oriented toward a goal or desired state, such as the solution of a problem.

Introducing

the

Policy Process

9

• Policy is ultimately made by governments, even if the ideas come from outside government or through the interaction of government and nongovernmental actors. • Policy is interpreted and implemented by public and private actors who have different interpretations of problems, solutions, and their own motivations. • Policy is what the government chooses to do or not to do. While reaching a consensus on one definition of public policy has proved impossible, all the variants of the definition suggest that public policy making is public—it affects a greater variety of people and interests than do private decisions. This is why government and the policies made by government are sometimes so controversial, frustrating, and at the same time very important. But because the public is the source of political authority—that is, the authority to act on the public’s behalf—it is clear that government is at the center of efforts to make public policy. I define a policy as a statement by government—at whatever level—of what it intends to do about a public problem. Such statements can be found in the Constitution, statutes, regulation, case law (that is, court decisions), agency or leadership decisions, or even in changes in the behavior of government officials at all levels. For example, a law that says that those caught driving while intoxicated will go to jail for up to one year is a statement of governmental policy to punish drunk drivers. The National Environmental Policy Act (NEPA) is a statement of government policy toward the environment. The First Amendment specifies that Congress cannot abridge religious, speech, or press freedoms, by stating “Congress shall make no law. . . .” Judicial decisions are also statements of policy: the Supreme Court’s decision in Brown v. Board of Education is a statement of policy that governments cannot racially segregate schools. Because we also define public policy as what government chooses not to do, the lack of a definitive statement of policy may be evidence of an implicit policy. Aside from the constitutional examples, the government has never declared—and our system has never enshrined in the Constitution—a right to education, or health care, or a living wage; therefore, we can assume that the implicit policy is that there is no right to these things, while some other nations do express these as rights. Instead, while we might pass policies to address the problems that arise when dealing with these policy matters, we generally do not treat them as matters of right. Policies take many different forms. A policy might be a law, or a regulation, or the set of all the laws and regulations that govern a particular issue area or problem. This would be a sound but incomplete explanation. Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram provide a more extensive definition of policy: “Policies are revealed through texts, practices, symbols, and discourses that define and deliver values including goods and services as well as regulations, income, status, and other positively or negatively valued attributes.”9 This definition means that policies are not just contained in laws

policy. A statement by government of what it intends to do such as a law, regulation, ruling, decision, order, or a combination of these. The lack of such statements may also be an implicit statement of policy.

10 Chapter 1 and regulations; once a law or rule is made, policies continue to be made as the people who implement policy—that is, those who put policies into effect—make decisions about who will benefit from policies and who will shoulder burdens as a result. In studying policy, then, we look at the broader sweep of politics, not simply the written laws and rules themselves. Ideas and Problems in the Policy Process

problem. A usually undesirable situation that, according to people or interest groups, can be alleviated by government action. Compare with condition.

One of the most fascinating aspects of studying public policy is the relationship between ideas and problems. According to Merriam-Webster, a problem is “a source of perplexity, distress, or vexation.” Given this definition, I am sure you can think of a lot of problems in the world that are vexing. Big problems that people are worried about as I write this are the economy, including sluggish growth and high unemployment, the wars in Iraq and Afghanistan, the rapidly growing costs of health care and college tuition, and the potential for global climate change. Each of these things is—or is not—vexing to some number of people. Public policy is largely driven by arguments about whether something is a solvable problem, what the potential solutions are, what the costs of those solutions are, and whether the solutions will be wholly or—more likely—partially effective. There are a lot of people who work to promote an understanding of a problem, and, in framing the problem a particular way, they promote the likely set of solutions, as we will see in greater detail in chapters 6 and 8. What Makes Public Policy Public?

classical liberalism. In political theory, the ideological system that emphasizes individual liberty and the ownership and acquisition of private property as a means to improve overall wealth and happiness and discourage social strife. Liberalism is the political ideology on which the American political system is based.

The dominant ideological foundation of our constitutional system (and that of other countries that were once part of the British Empire, such as Canada, Australia, and Great Britain itself) is known as classical liberalism. This ideology is very clearly expressed in John Locke’s Second Treatise of Civil Government (1690). Among the many beliefs of liberalism is that power derives from the consent of the governed—that is, the people themselves. The people, and not royalty or the state, are therefore sovereign. Thus, when policy advocates seek to induce the government to make policy (by taking an action or refusing to do so), or when government actively engages in actions these advocates support, one can make a claim that the government does so in the public interest. Indeed, many states have groups called public interest research groups, or PIRGs, which promote their interpretation of the public interest. For example, agencies that regulate public utilities, such as electric companies, claim to regulate in the public interest by limiting rates or assuring service. Some policy advocates claim that laws that relieve tax burdens on the rich are in the public interest because they create overall public wealth, which leads to job creation, the creation of wealth, and, therefore, a more prosperous society over all.10 Those who

Introducing

the

Policy Process

argue that the rich should be taxed at a higher rate than the poor claim that taxation based on ability to pay is more in the spirit of the public interest. Public policy is related to the public interest because it affects all of us in some way. But as these examples show, we are not all affected by the same policies in exactly the same way, nor is one’s intensity of feeling about an issue necessarily equal to that of others. And many of us don’t have any particular issue that would cause us to mobilize with others to demand policy change. Most of us do not care too much about the day-to-day workings of government because we are busy with the day-to-day workings of our lives and because the activities of government seem removed from our daily interests and needs. Still, the federal government plays an important role in every aspect of our lives, from the nutrition labeling on our breakfast cereal to the standards for fire-retardant kids’ clothing. And state and local governments tax us, can restrict how we use our land through land use planning and zoning, define what the schools can and cannot teach, and make rules about everything from the operation of the state fairgrounds to where and when we can own and carry firearms. Big states, like California, are so influential that their standards—such as those on automobile emissions—are adopted by other states or in federal law. Not everyone likes rules like these, of course—industry for years battled against federal and state safety and emissions regulations on vehicles. But as oppressive as government is claimed to be by some interests, some government activities seem either benign or beneficial to most people, and we tend not to dwell on those policies until something goes wrong. And, as is often true in democracies, policies ultimately gain broad support so their repeal is unlikely, as with the social security program or tax deductions for dependents. You may be interested in public policy because you care intensely about particular public problems and the policies intended to address them, such as those dealing with the environment, civil rights, economic freedom, or the promotion of personal morality. But even the most intensely interested participants in the policy process are not concerned with every issue. There is a considerable division of labor in democratic politics; in the formal institutions of government, different people have different constitutional responsibilities, and the vast array of issues that government handles on our behalf require that even members of legislatures need to be specialists in fairly narrow fields. In the United States, as in many democracies, people tacitly delegate policymaking responsibilities to government and to specialists because everyone cannot concern themselves with the day-to-day panoply of issues that government must address. But in delegating these responsibilities we do not abandon our interest in what the government does or how it does it (and sometimes the procedures the government uses are at least as important as the goals to be achieved), or our right to promote our own ideas of what constitutes the public interest when we are sufficiently motivated.

11 public interest. The assumed broader desires and needs of the public, in whose name policy is made. The public interest is hard to define, but is something to which all policy advocates appeal.

12 Chapter 1 Why Do We Study Public Policy? While the concept of the public interest varies from person to person, and one person’s individual interests are likely to differ in some ways from their neighbors’ interests, most people are concerned about the impact of policies on their lives, such as how many services they receive or how much they have to pay in taxes. That said, why do you want to study the process that leads to the decisions to make these policies? Since you are reading this book, you probably already have an idea of why you are studying or working in public policy. Perhaps you have been interested in policy and politics since you were young; many people develop their interest in politics and policy at home. You may have been exposed to policy making when an interest in which you or your family believed was threatened, or if you perceived it was threatened. For example, you or your parents may have mobilized around plans to build a shopping mall, a power plant, a jail, or a polluting industrial facility near your home. And, for many people, politics and policy making are inherently fascinating, and people study the policy process simply because it’s interesting in its own right. Two texts in particular, by Clarke E. Cochran and his colleagues and by James Anderson,11 provide reasons for the study of public policy. The first of these is what Cochran calls a theoretical reason and Anderson calls a scientific reason. They argue that one studies public policy so that one can know more about the process, both in pursuit of knowledge for its own sake and to inform practitioners. One might compare the pursuit of knowledge to “pure” science and the practitioner orientation to “applied” science. The practical and applied study of public policy takes its cues from theory, but seeks more actively to apply those theoretical insights to actual cases of public policy formation, thereby helping theorists improve their theories. In a course on public policy, theory may be applied to particular cases or policy areas, as often seen in the later chapters of introductory public policy texts. As knowledge filters from the more abstract to the more applied, insights from the theoretical world are employed, knowingly or not, by practitioners. Conversely, students of public policy derive theory by observing the collective activity of the practitioners of public policy. This book considers theory more extensively in chapter 10. Related to the practical reasons for studying policy are political reasons. People with political goals study public policy to learn how to promote their preferred policy options. I hope you find this book useful in understanding the political process so that you can work toward reaching your policy goals while at the same time understanding why your best efforts may be thwarted. Some of you will become very active participants in the policy process. Some will become elected officials, appointed officials, or agency managers and staff. Others will lead interest groups, work in the news media, or provide scientific and technical information for others. Many of you, never thinking you’re involved in the process, will go on to successful careers in business, the arts, or other en-

Introducing

the

Policy Process

13

deavors. But some day, when you least expect it, you may get involved in policy making. Perhaps you will become active when you and your neighbors oppose the construction of a new shopping mall in your neighborhood. For some people this is the sort of problem that public policy is intended to address. But for others a mall is an opportunity for economic growth or an added convenience and the problem isn’t the mall, it’s the opposition to the mall. Perhaps your employer will ask you to participate in a public relations campaign to support or oppose a new policy. In short, chances are very good that you will become interested in the policy process at some point in your life, and I venture to guess that you will become involved in some way, given that you are reading this book! I hope that An Introduction to the Policy Process will help you become a more thoughtful and effective participant. The Place of Policy Studies in the Social Sciences Because of the focus on politics in this chapter, one might conclude that policy studies are or should be the sole province of political scientists and closely related scholars, such as those who study policy analysis or public administration. But this interpretation only holds true if we focus narrowly on the policy process. There are many ways to study policy making, as Peter May shows in his “public policy morphology” (Table 1.2). Many programs in political science, sociology, economics, public administration, law, and other disciplines allow students to specialize in the study of policy and the policy process as they work toward their bachelor’s, master’s, and doctoral degrees. Dozens of universities now offer master’s degrees in public policy (MPP degrees), and others offer bachelor’s or doctoral degrees in public policy that draw from multiple disciplines to provide training in policy studies.12 Most of these programs are interdisciplinary and draw their faculties from across the social, behavioral, and natural science disciplines. This interdisciplinary nature is both a strength and a weakness that has perennially faced policy studies. It is a strength because the discipline draws upon the best insights from the natural sciences, social sciences, and humanities. To some people, however, it is a weakness because policy scientists do not share a language that transcends disciplinary boundaries. Our challenge as students of public policy is to understand and profitably use the insights offered by the many disciplines that study, in various ways, public policy (Table 1.3). This book follows in the policy process tradition, which is more grounded in traditional political science. Students of the policy process view rational, scientific, and often quantitative policy analysis as part of the raw material of policy making that participants use to advocate for their preferred policies. The interplay of this evidence, the values and belief systems of the participants in the process, the structure of the process itself, and the distribution of power within the structure all have an important influence on public policy.

social science. The branch of the sciences that studies the actions and behavior of people, groups, and institutions. Political science, sociology, anthropology, and economics are social sciences. History is sometimes considered a social science. discipline. A field of academic research or study. Sociology, political science, and economics are social science disciplines; electrical, civil, and mechanical engineering are engineering disciplines. Disciplines approach similar problems in different ways.

14 Chapter 1 Table 1.2 A Public Policy Morphology Public policy education and research has four fairly distinct variants. This book focuses on the first approach, and can serve as a foundation for further study in other areas of policy study. • Public Policy Processes—This consists of research on the formulation and implementation of public policy usually limited to the American context emphasizing national, domestic policy. Using perspectives of American politics, individuals studying public policy processes address such topics as issue emergence and policy agendas, the cultural definition of policy problems, policy formulation, political feasibility, and policy implementation. The policy process literature can be distinguished from other flavors of public policy as follows: Unlike policy analysis, it does not emphasize the craft aspects of constructing and analyzing policies. Unlike policy research, it does not emphasize problem solving (rather, it is the study of how others define and seek to solve problems). And unlike comparative public policy, it tends to be limited to American settings although good comparative work is appropriate. The other variants of public policy are: • Comparative Public Policy—In principle, comparative public policy applies the logic of comparative analysis to the substance of different policy problems. Current writing and analysis tends to emphasize cross-national comparisons. There is also a newly emerging literature of comparative policy work among the American states. Much of this work is descriptive, rather than theoretical. • Public Policy Analysis—A logic of analysis and mix of techniques in support of public policy decision making. This tradition borrows heavily from economics. The logic of “rational” analysis contains a central focus on problem specification, generation of alternative policies, and assessment of policies in support of public policy decision making. The techniques include quantitative methods, economic analysis, welfare economics, and qualitative assessments. Most of this type of training takes place within public policy programs offering professional two-year masters degrees. Weimer and Vining’s policy analysis text and Eugene Bardach’s short volume on policy analysis are leading works in this field.13 • Public Policy Research—This consists of applied social science research aimed at documenting policy problems and evaluating interventions. The distinctive element of policy research is that it is problem driven. As such, the appropriate approaches and range of disciplinary relevance are in principle quite broad. â•… Typically, policy research training includes development of expertise in the substance of one or more policy areas (e.g., health, energy, and environment). This type of training takes place across a range of programs as reflected in the diversity of substantive public policy offerings in the social, natural, and behavioral sciences.

Source: Based on work by Peter J. May at the University of Washington.

Evidence and Argument in the Policy Process For years, political scientists have known that government is neither monolithic—that is, one single-minded body that speaks with one voice and works toward one set of goals—nor a neutral referee that dispassionately judges between policy alternatives by weighing their costs and benefits. The participants in the policy process—whether they are considered policy entrepreneurs, brokers, analysts, interest groups, or association leaders—are not all or even primarily neutral participants in the policy process. Along the same lines, as Clarke Cochran and his colleagues argue, there are few “neutral” policy analysts and by definition no neutral advocates of particular policy alternatives.14 Thus, as Giandomenico Majone and Deborah Stone note,15

Introducing

the

Policy Process

15

Table 1.3 Selected Disciplines That Study Public Policy Discipline

Description

Relationship to public policy

Some important journals

Political science

The study of political relationships; that is, the study of the processes by which societies seek to allocate political power and the benefits of such power.

The political process is the process through which policies are made and enforced.

American Political Science Review, American Journal of Political Science, Journal of Politics, Polity, Political Research Quarterly, Public Opinion Quarterly

Sociology

“Sociology is the study of social life, social change, and the social causes and consequences of human behavior. Sociologists investigate the structure of groups, organizations, and societies, and how people interact within these contexts.”*

Community and group activities are an important part of policy making, because groups of people often form to make demands.

American Sociological Review, Contemporary Sociology ; American Journal of Sociology

Economics

The study of the allocation of resources in a community, however defined. Economists study markets and exchanges. Welfare economists seek to understand the extent to which an overall community’s welfare can be maximized.

There are many economic factors that influence public policy, such as economic growth, productivity, employment, and the like. The tools of economics are often used to promote policies or to explain why policies succeed or fail.

American Economic Review, Econometrica, Journal of Applied Economics, Journal of Political Economy

Public The study of the management administration of government and nonprofit (PA) organizations, including the management of information, money, and personnel in order to achieve goals developed through the democratic process.

The management of public programs is an integral part of the policy process. PA scholars study the motivation of program implementers and targets, and help research innovations to improve service delivery.

Public Administration Review, Journal of Public Administration Research and Teaching

Public policy

We give this label to the highly interdisciplinary study of the public policy process. Policy scholars develop theories about how the policy process works, and develop tools and methods to analyze how policy is made and implemented.

Journal of Policy Analysis and Management; Journal of Public Policy, Policy Studies Review, Policy Studies Journal, Journal of Policy History

The study of what governments choose to do or not to do, including studies of the policy process, policy implementation and impact, and evaluation.

*American Sociological Association, http://www.asanet.org/public/what.html.

analysis is often undertaken in the name of advocacy, and is but one part of the rhetorical tools used in political debate. The results of “scientific” policy analysis are often abandoned when other rhetorical tools seem to work better. Indeed, as discussed later in this book, the act of identifying a problem is as much a normative judgment as it is an objective statement of fact; thus, if analysis proceeds from the identification of a problem, and the problem is defined normatively, then one cannot say that any subsequent analysis is strictly neutral.

16 Chapter 1 GROW UP WHAT DO YOU WANT WHAT DO YOU WANT GROW UP GROW UP NOTIONS NOTIONS GROW UP

IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF IT THE NEW SCIENCE OF

NOTIONS

NOTIONS WHAT DO YOU WANT GROW UP

NOTIONS

Do people make up their minds and then gather evidence, or gather evidence, then make up their minds? Source: Non Sequitur © 2009 Wiley Miller. Reprinted by permission of Universal Uclick. All right reserved.

As I wrote this chapter for the first edition, my introductory public policy course was giving its group presentations on issues related to the apparent outbreak of school violence incidents in places such as Springfield, Oregon, and Littleton, Colorado, in the late 1990s. One of the groups chose to focus on pending federal legislation, alternative policy choices, and the group’s analysis of the desirability of alternative solutions to the school violence problem. The group argued that armed guards, cameras in classrooms, metal detectors, and other measures seemed too severe. These security techniques would make

Introducing

the

Policy Process

17

Table 1.4 Anecdotes and Evidence Description

How it is used

Strengths/rationale

Stories told to illustrate a problem or the failure of a policy, such as “DARE kept my children off drugs” or “welfare queen” stories.

To justify starting or stopping programs by providing an easily understood story with obvious conclusions and underlying normative or moral principles.

Anecdotes are good for staking out a position on an issue, or for motivating people to believe certain things. They are less useful as part of serious analysis, because they do not delve deeply into how programs work.

Evidence Conclusions reached through from scientific scientific study of a problem or study from the outcomes of a policy.

To justify starting or stopping programs by providing the most scientifically sound information that policy makers can use to make decisions.

Scientific evidence is much stronger than anecdotes in understanding how and why things work the way they do. However, the results of scientific study are often controversial and unpopular, and sometimes run counter to popular expectations.

Anecdotes

schools seem like prisons and thereby damage the educational environment, in turn reducing academic performance. During a question and answer period, I asked the students whether they had any information that showed a link between these stern security measures and a poorer educational environment. They answered that they did not. I then asked, “Does it matter that you have no evidence?” After some discussion, we concluded that evidence is useful in policy debate, but it is not always necessary. Sometimes, the imagery and symbolism one associates with a policy—the image of a school that looks and in some ways works like a jail, in this case—are sufficient to carry an argument. Thus, while one can gather considerable information on the relationship between school security and the educational environment, one need not necessarily have all the evidence at hand if one’s argument strikes a chord with the public and decision makers. This means, more bluntly, that relatively little evidence is needed to make an argument if it is possible to appeal to popular prejudices and common misconceptions, or to common values or interests that are not too far outside the mainstream of current thought. This sounds cynical, but there are abundant examples in American history and world history of emotion overcoming rationality in policy making, such as the imposition of Jim Crow laws on black Americans based on a scientifically unfounded belief that blacks are genetically inferior to whites in some way. Because neither facts nor emotions are solely decisive, evidence and emotion play important roles in policy making, and sometimes emotion gains the upper hand. A summary of the differences between anecdotes and evidence is provided in Table 1.4.

18 Chapter 1

Case Study: Does the DARE Program Work? Let’s consider the adoption of public policy where there is little social science evidence to suggest the policy meets its goals, but it continues to be an important policy. You may be familiar with the DARE (Drug Abuse Resistance Education) program, either by reputation or personal experience.16 The reason for the creation of DARE, or any antidrug program, is simple: drug abuse—including the abuse of legal drugs, alcohol, and tobacco as well as illegal drugs—is associated with poor academic achievement, crime, and significant health problems for drug abusers. The federal, state, and local governments have created drug use regulations and educated the public about drugs for decades. DARE was an innovative program that linked schools with law enforcement in a way that would, its designers believed, be more effective than existing programs in preventing school-aged children from using (or “experimenting with”) illegal drugs, tobacco, and alcohol. The program was founded in 1983 by the police and schools in Los Angeles to address local problems with drugs and gangs. It has since been implemented internationally. DARE now serves forty-three countries and 75 percent of school districts in the United States. Originally designed for older elementary school students, DARE programs now address drug abuse, gangs, and violence with students in kindergarten through twelfth grade. The national DARE organization claims that the program helps students make good decisions and “ ‘humanizes’ the police: that is, young people can begin to relate to officers as people”; through the DARE program students may think of police officers as friends and helpers in the community. DARE designers felt that the inclusion of police officers as instructors would increase the credibility of the instructors and the program, a result that at least one study corroborated.17 While the DARE organization refers to itself as the “preeminent substance abuse education program”—a reasonable claim given the number of schools that use it—scientific evidence of its effectiveness is scant. The basic question is whether using the DARE program reduces drug use in that population of students compared with students who did not go through DARE. In a 2001 review of drug abuse prevention programs, the U.S. Surgeon General placed DARE in the “Does Not Work” category of these programs.18 A 2003 Government Accountability Office study reviewed the existing body of literature on DARE effectiveness and reported that the existing research found no significant difference in drug use between students who had completed DARE and students who had not. Research by the National Institutes of Health, Department of Education, and Department of Justice corroborated these findings. Perhaps most damaging to DARE was a study published in the American Journal of Public Health, which conducted an overview (a meta-analysis) of the most scientifically rigorous studies the researchers could find. They discovered that, overall, studies proved no effect from the DARE curriculum; in simple terms, the studies concluded that DARE did not have a measurable influence on drug use among school-aged children, especially when measured over time. As a result of the many studies that showed DARE’s ineffectiveness, federal money supporting DARE programs was cut, and some school districts have dropped the DARE program.19 Many organizations continued the DARE program through local fund-raising and taxation. Several responses to the negative research findings followed. First, DARE advocates argued that the outcomes of drug prevention education are difficult to quantify, that the studies cited by researchers were flawed, and that DARE’s satisfaction surveys revealed positive outcomes including high levels of parent, student, and community satisfaction. Advocates (continued)

Introducing

the

Policy Process

19

Case Study (continued) also maintain that positive experiences with law enforcement officers are significant, though difficult to measure. However, none of these claims or objections provides an answer to the fundamental research question about DARE’s effectiveness. The second response was more subtle, but more revealing. DARE, facing the loss of federal funding and its own credibility, revised its curriculum in response to several studies. In an undated document on its Web site, DARE suggests that the “new DARE” reflects changes in curriculum design and delivery and incorporates more effective instructional methods based on better science. The creation of the “new DARE” was likely motivated by the urging of DARE’s proponents’ to avoid losing federal funding and a desire to embrace science. The new program—which emphasizes teaching middle school children—was to be evaluated by a $13.7 million study funded by the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation—a highly respected institution devoted to health issues—to track the effectiveness of the program. However, the evaluators have not yet published results of their research on the fundamental question of DARE’s effectiveness. Why, then, does DARE remain so popular? There are several potential reasons, and the remainder of this book will help you to understand the logic behind the continued adoption of a program that “doesn’t work.” The first reason DARE remains popular is because people believe it works, because they draw on anecdotal evidence—that is, personal experience—to draw conclusions about its effectiveness. DARE supporters often raise the issue of DARE’s creation of good relationships between police officers and students. In one case, a county sheriff in Ohio noted that “There are studies out there that said that it didn’t work, that kids still used drugs. What it doesn’t measure is the relationships that are built between the kids and those officers.”20 A parent in Texas, reacting to the impending cut of DARE from her children’s school, said “I asked my kids, ‘Do you think that program is worth it?’ and they said, ‘Yes.’ They would never smoke—they never realized how many chemicals are in (a cigarette)—and it turned them off to drugs, too.”21 In another instance, a school superintendent in Suffolk County, New York, expressed his disappointment with the decision to drop DARE: “It has had a tremendous impact on the students and has become part of our school culture. I’m concerned that when the responsibility for teaching the curriculum falls on the shoulders of the teachers, who already have a full curriculum, that it won’t have the same effectiveness that it did when the police officers came to visit.”22 From the schools’ perspective, the DARE program fills important needs. As one police department notes, “Having a DARE program in the local school lifts the burden off teachers and administrators to provide drug education, and gives them additional time to do something else. It is popular with parents and the media because it conveys the idea that something is being done to combat the menace of drug abuse by children.”23 This idea of “doing something” is important in politics and public policy. In the DARE case, an expert on adolescent substance abuse noted the powerful reasons why DARE persists in so many schools: This evidence, of course, is not popular with parents, police officers and others since many of them believe DARE works. And kids do say the ‘right’ things after participating. But, research shows there are no long-term effects. A perfect formula for a belief-versus-science polarization. So, why the interest and support for ‘needing’ more DARE programs . . . despite

(continued)

20 Chapter 1

Case Study (continued) overwhelming evidence they don’t work? Well, it’s mostly about the comfort parents, school staff, police officers, and other adults receive when a program is delivered that is visible and, in their beliefs, helpful. It feels good to know that at least something is being done.24

Often, policy makers feel a great deal of pressure to “do something” about public problems, even when all the information is not available; indeed, as we will learn, information is often hard to come by. Furthermore, once a program is in place, many stakeholders—in this case, parents, teachers, the police, school boards, and local community leaders—have so much money, time, and personal belief invested in a program that it is difficult, even in the face of scientific evidence, to change the program. Another way to understand the persistence of DARE is by reframing the essential research question: Does DARE work? One can ask, “What does ‘work’ mean?” As originally defined by DARE’s developers, the program was supposed to keep kids from trying or using drugs. The scientific evidence suggests that this does not happen. But are there other benefits to DARE? What about the oft-cited relationships between police and children? Is this a positive benefit? How would one measure this? Do police officers benefit from meeting and interacting with the students in their communities? What about the use of police as instructors? Does this benefit teachers who may not feel comfortable teaching students about drug use and abuse? What benefits, if any, might accrue to a community as a whole for identifying, as so many signs do, particularly in small-town America, that “We are a DARE community”? Could a more scientifically sound program provide these benefits? Or is the drug problem so intractable—that is, hard to solve—that no program is likely to work? The DARE case illustrates how powerful rhetoric, symbolism, and storytelling that relies on anecdotes can promote a policy even when the evidence of its effectiveness is scant. Despite mounting evidence that the old DARE was ineffective, and the lack of evidence that the new program is effective, the curriculum continues to be used in many schools around the nation. It is very difficult to remove DARE from some schools because of the popularity of the idea of working with the police combined with the valued goal of preventing or reducing youth drug use and violence. Are there other policies that continue to be used even if they fail to achieve their goals? Are policies enacted that are unlikely to achieve the goals that their proponents claim? Why would people propose policies that they may know won’t work well? How do we measure whether a policy is “good” or not? Consider these questions—and the logic behind these questions—as you read this book.

Summary This chapter has provided an overview of the endeavor on which you are about to embark: the study of public policy. We learned that the study of public policy is rooted in the study of politics, which is an ancient field of study. But we also learned that the study of public policy, as we generally define it, is a recent innovation. I hope that this introductory chapter has motivated you to study the public policy

Introducing

the

Policy Process

21

process both to satisfy your own personal curiosity about how things work, and to motivate you to understand and perhaps play a more active role in the decisions that affect you, your family, and your community. This book is organized in three broad sections. This chapter and chapters 2 and 3 are overviews of the policy process and of the environment in which policy is made. Chapter 3 introduces the stages model of the policy process, which serves to organize the various parts of the process so that we can analyze them. Chapters 4 and 5 are about the actors in the policy process. Chapters 6 through 9 cover the outputs and processes of public policy. Chapter 10 brings all this together by considering modern, better theories of the policy process that improve upon the stages model and develop better grounded theories. As you read this book, I hope you will think of current ideas and events in the political world with public policy implications. As you do so, think about what you are learning from this book and how it can be applied to these new situations. Key Terms Classical liberalism Policy Politics Public

Public Interest Discipline Problem Interest

Enlightenment Social science

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. How is public policy grounded in the study of politics? What do you think the term “politics” means in this context? Do you think it would be possible to make public policy without politics? 2. Is there a real difference between playing politics and just the general political process of argument, negotiation, and compromise? Why do people think so negatively of politics given that this is the process by which we address public problems? 3. Discuss the study of public policy. Are there other disciplines that aren’t mentioned here that contribute to the study of public policy? In what way might those disciplines contribute to policy making? (Think broadly. How do scientists and engineers help make public policy? Doctors? Social workers? Other professions?) 4. Compare policy analysis to the study of the policy process. How are they similar, and how are they different? 5. Ask your friends, neighbors, or parents what comes to mind when they hear the word “politics.” Then, ask what they think when they hear the term “public policy.” How are their responses similar to and different from the ideas discussed in this chapter?

22 Chapter 1 6. Find an article on a public policy issue in a newspaper. Consider carefully whether the people making arguments for or against a particular policy are making normative or positive arguments. Are they using anecdotes or evidence? How can you tell the difference? Whose arguments do you consider most persuasive? Why? Additional Reading In this chapter I argue in favor of evidence-based policy advocacy. The making of public policy based on scientifically gathered evidence (by which I mean evidence from the natural sciences, social sciences, and engineering) is not a new idea; indeed, this sort of evidence is at the heart of Lasswell’s call for a distinctive policy science. On this conception of policy science, see Harold D. Lasswell, A Pre-View of Policy Sciences (New York: American Elsevier Pub. Co., 1971); and Daniel Lerner and Harold D. Lasswell, The Policy Sciences; Recent Developments in Scope and Method (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1951). The journal Policy Sciences publishes research that follows Lasswell’s ideas about the policy sciences. But the role of rhetoric and argument, combined with evidence and scientific inquiry, is important, and is a theme taken up by Giandomenico Majoine in Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989). A similar work is Deborah Stone’s Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decisionmaking, revised edition (New York: Norton, 2002), a work that you will encounter through this book and that has been very influential in my thinking about policy. There are many popular treatments of how Americans engage with the political system, and why people are often so frustrated by it. A classic in this genre is E.J. Dionne, Why Americans Hate Politics (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1991). The book is nearly twenty years old, but its central premise remains relevant: that describing public problems and solutions as “conservative” or “liberal” ignores problem definitions and solutions that could be said to be centrist, not leaning to either ideological pole. Because I tend to believe that, in many cases, governmental institutions and the political process can identify and solve problems, I particularly like Paul Light’s book, Government’s Greatest Achievements: From Civil Rights to Homeland Security (Washington: Brookings Institution, 2002), which reminds us that not all government activity is futile or wasteful. Because this chapter describes policy analysis as an important part of the policy sciences, readers may wish to look at some of the classic works in the field. The classic works based in economics are Edith Stokey and Richard Zeckhauser, A Primer for Policy Analysis (New York: W.W. Norton, 1978) and David Leo Weimer and Aidan R. Vining, Policy Analysis: Concepts and Practice, 4th edition (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall, 2004). It is important to understand both the welfare economics traditions from which Stokey, Zeckhauser, Weimer, and Vining draw their ideas as well as the problems with using these approaches as the sole lens through which to view

Introducing

the

Policy Process

23

public policy making. Examples of research that use the welfare economics approach can be found in any issue of the Journal of Policy Analysis and Management (JPAM). Those who seek a more descriptive or narrative approach to policy analysis would do well to review Eugene Bardach’s short volume, A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Effective Problem Solving, 3d edition (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2009). This book helps readers to think about public problems. I drew on Bardach’s ideas about problems in this chapter. Notes 1. Daniel C. McCool, Public Policy Theories, Models, and Concepts: An Anthology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995), 1. 2. Peter Gay, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1966). 3. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999). 4. This is, admittedly, an incomplete list of the range of political philosophers that influence modern American political thought. Students with an interest in the fascinating realm of political theory would do well to take a political theory course, or to read works such as Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, History of Political Philosophy, 3d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987). 5. Harold D. Lasswell, Politics: Who Gets What, When, How (New York: Meridian Books, 1958). 6. This is a paraphrase of the full quotation: “Many forms of Government have been tried and will be tried in this world of sin and woe. No one pretends that democracy is perfect or all-wise. Indeed, it has been said that democracy is the worst form of government except all those other forms that have been tried from time to time.” Speech in the House of Commons, November 11, 1947. 7. McCool, Public Policy Theories, 1; Lasswell, Politics: Who Gets What, When, How. 8. This theme is persistent in most advanced treatments of public policy. A good discussion of this can be found in chapter 1 of Michael Howlett and M. Ramesh, Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems (Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1995). 9. Anne Larason Schneider and Helen Ingram, Policy Design for Democracy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997), 2. 10. Alan D. Viard, “The Trouble with Taxing Those at the Top,” Tax Policy Outlook, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, no. 2, July 2007, http://www.aei.org/docLib/20070614_TPO02_g.pdf (accessed August 24, 2009). 11. Clarke E. Cochran, Lawrence Mayer, T.R. Carr, and N. Joseph Cayer, American Public Policy: An Introduction, 6th ed. (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999); James E. Anderson, Public Policymaking, 4th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2000). 12. David Leo Weimer and Aidan R. Vining, Policy Analysis: Concepts and Practice, 4th ed. (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall, 2005); Eugene Bardach, A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Effective Problem Solving, 3d ed. (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2009). 13. A considerable amount of information on such programs can be found on the National Association of Schools of Public Affairs and Administration Web site, http://www.naspaa.org. 14. Clarke E. Cochran et al., American Public Policy. 15. Giandomenico Majone, Evidence, Argument; Deborah Stone, Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making, rev. ed. (New York: Norton, 2002); Deborah A. Stone, “Causal Stories and the Formation of Policy Agendas,” Political Science Quarterly 104, no. 2 (1989): 281–300. 16. Unless otherwise noted, all claims about DARE’s history, structure, and effectiveness come from the organization’s Web site, www.dare.com/. 17. Augustine Hammond, Zili Sloboda, Peggy Tonkin, Richard Stephens, Brent Teasdale, Scott F. Grey, and Joseph Williams, “Do Adolescents Perceive Police Officers as Credible Instructors of Substance Abuse Prevention Programs?” Health Education Research 23, no. 4 (2008): 682–96.

24 Chapter 1 18. U.S. Surgeon General, Youth Violence: A Report of the Surgeon General, http://www.surgeongeneral.gov/ library/youthviolence/chapter5/sec4.html. 19. Carol Hirschon Weiss, Erin Murphy-Graham, and Sarah Birkeland, “An Alternate Route to Policy Influence: How Evaluations Affect D.A.R.E.,” American Journal of Evaluation 26, no. 1 (2005): 12–30. 20. Dana Wilson, “DARE Program Cut Back Statewide,” The Columbus Dispatch, August 29, 2009, http://www. dispatch.com/live/content/local_news/stories/2009/08/29/nodare.html (accessed February 21, 2010). 21. Rhiannon Meyers, “School Wants to Drop DARE,” Galveston County Daily News, April 5, 2009, http:// galvestondailynews.com/story.lasso?ewcd=7533c2754fe11037 (accessed February 21, 2001). 22. Linda Saslow, “Suffolk Schools to Say Goodbye to DARE,” New York Times, November 25, 2007, http:// www.nytimes.com/2007/11/25/nyregion/nyregionspecial2/25dareli.html (accessed February 21, 2010). 23. Lafayette (Indiana) Police Department, “D.A.R.E./SRO,” April 14, 2008, http://www.lafayette.in.gov/egov/ docs/1208202879833.htm (accessed February 21, 2010). 24. Peter B. Rockholz, “Is DARE Effective? ‘Overwhelming Evidence’ Shows DARE Has No Lasting Impact,” The News-Times, February 19, 2010, http://www.newstimes.com/opinion/article/Sunday-debate-Is-DARE-effectiveOverwhelming-372445.php (accessed February 21, 2010).

Elements of the Policy-Making System Chapter at a Glance The Policy Process as a System The Structural Environment The Social Environment The Political Environment The Economic Environment Inputs Election results Public Opinion Communications to Elected Officials and Public Managers Interest Group Activity The News Media Outputs Laws Oversight and Evaluation Summary Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

The term “policy process” suggests that there is some sort of system that translates policy ideas into actual policies that are implemented and have positive effects. Traditionally, public policy textbooks have presented what is known as the “textbook model” or “stages model” of the policy process. The process is shown in Figure 2.1. This figure serves both as an overview of the process, and, to some extent, the organization for this book. In this model public problems emerge in a society through various means, including sudden events like disasters or through the advocacy activities of concerned citizens and interest groups. If the issue gains sufficient attention it is said to have reached the agenda, a process described in chapter 6. Given the size and complexity of governance in the United States and the number of governments—over 80,000, from the federal government to the smallest local water district—there are lots of problems and lots of ideas on many agendas. Once

25

2

CHAPTER

26 Chapter 2 Figure 2.1â•… The Stages Model of the Policy Process ,VVXH(PHUJHQFH

systems thinking. A way of thinking about natural or social phenomena as a system, in which various inputs into a system are handled, processed, and interact with each other to create a set of discernible outputs. input-output model. A model of the policy process that assumes a set of policy demands or inputs, which are then processed by the political system into laws, programs, and the goods and services government provides.

$JHQGD6HWWLQJ

$OWHUQDWLYH 6HOHFWLRQ

(QDFWPHQW

,PSOHPHQWDWLRQ

(YDOXDWLRQ

an issue moves up on an agenda it moves to the development of alternative policy responses—some might call them solutions—to public problems. From there, we move to alternative policy selection; that is, the choice of policy tools we will use to address the problem, whereupon policies are enacted. Enactment means that a law is passed, a regulation is issued, or some other formal decision is reached to take a particular action to solve a problem. After that decision is reached, the policy is implemented, a process described in chapter 9. The policy is then evaluated and the results of evaluation provide feedback to the process, where it begins anew. This model has been subject to considerable critique in recent years. A main critique of the stages, or textbook model of policy making is that it implies that policy making proceeds step by step, starting at the beginning and ending at the end.1 Critics point out that a policy idea may not reach every stage. For example, policy ideas often reach the agenda, but move no further than that. Others argue that one cannot separate the implementation of a policy from its evaluation, because evaluation happens continuously as a policy is implemented. These critics suggest that the stages model does not constitute a workable theory of how the policy process works. (These critiques are taken up when we delve into advanced theories of the policy process, including a discussion of what a theory means, in chapter 10.) But I used the stages model to organize this book because it remains a remarkably helpful way to structure our thinking about the policy process. As political scientist Peter deLeon notes many scholars have written extensive studies that describe each stage of the process.2 Thinking of policy making in stages is a way of organizing our thinking and of isolating and understanding the most important elements of the process. The Policy Process as a System The stages model of the policy process owes a great deal to systems thinking, a way of thinking about all manner of things—from social to biological to mechanical systems— that became much more prominent after World War II. The simplest model of the policy process is an input-output model. The inputs are the various issues, pressures, information, and the like to which the actors in the system react. The outputs are, in simplest terms, public policy decisions to do or not do something. David Easton’s book, A Systems Analysis of Political Life, was among the first works to describe politics in this way.3 A simplified depiction of this system is shown in Figure 2.2.

Elements

of the

Policy-Making System

27

Figure 2.2â•… A Systems Model of Politics and Policy 7KHHQYLURQPHQW²VWUXFWXUDOVRFLDOSROLWLFDODQGHFRQRPLF²DIIHFWVDOOSDUWVRIWKHV\VWHP ,QSXWV (OHFWLRQUHVXOWV 3XEOLFRSLQLRQ &RPPXQLFDWLRQVWRHOHFWHGRIILFLDOV 0HGLDFRYHUDJHRILVVXHV 3HUVRQDOH[SHULHQFHVRIGHFLVLRQPDNHUV

7+(32/,7,&$/6'0 o,r$' 0,rJ' ~

~

~

~

~

~

0,'\'"0,rJ>0,'\'00,rJ>o,'br:::.0,rJ> 0,rJ> 0,rJ> ~ ~

~

0,rJ> 0,rJ>

0,rJ> 0,rJ> 0,rJ>

0,,,>'"

Source: Office of Management and Budget, The President’s Budget FY 2010, historic tables, http://www.whitehouse. gov/omb/budget/historicals/. Figure 4.3â•… Federal Government Outlays as Percentage of GDP, 1940–2014 Outlays as percent of GOP

50.0 45.0 40.0 35.0 30.0 25.0 20.0 15.0 10.0 5.0 0.0

,i ~o}< ..,1' ~,,>" ~,,>'o ~'or:::. ~rJ' ~~ ~'\" ~,\'o l

..,o,tf'

~.

~" ..

June 2003

October 2003

i ::0

I

February 2003

June 2002

October 2002

February 2002

June 2001

October 2001

February 2001

June 2000

October 2000

~

~

...

Households

..... ~

Figure 5.5â•… Trends in Home Internet Adoption, 2000–2009

Source: http://www.websiteoptimization.com/bw/0906/indextest.html, using data from the Pew Internet and American Life project at http://www.pewinternet.org/.

tous, is often available free at restaurants and coffee shops, and is open to anyone with $500 for a laptop computer or even less for a smart phone. Still, not everyone is online, because access is somewhat expensive and because the computer needed to access it remains a relatively expensive consumer good. In general, people with college educations are far more likely than people without high school diplomas to access the Internet. With this greater penetration of broadband, as shown in Figure 5.5, users are able to consume audio, video, and text, but, more to the point, many people are able to distribute (or, as is often the case, redistribute from existing sources) news and political information independently. This leads to what I call the “diversity” argument: there are thousands of outlets, so people can choose from newspapers (and their Web sites), TV, newsletters, blogs, or social networks to get their news. But there is much less diversity than one might suppose. For example, as I was writing this section, I originally wrote, “many people are able to produce news and political information independently.” But I changed this to “distribute news” or even “redistribute” news because, in almost all cases, social networkers, bloggers, and the like are not gathering and writing the original news stories, but are linking to and commenting on them. This is reflected in Figure 5.6, which shows that over 60 percent of visits to Internet news sites are to traditional news sources (TV and newspaper Web sites) and 30 percent are to news aggregator sites, where the stories

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

153

Figure 5.6â•… Most Commonly Visited Types of Internet News Sites, February 2008

Newspapers

29%

Aggregator 31%

New media-conservative

4% New mediaOther

TV

liberal 1%

3%

32%

Source: http://www.naa.org/blog/digitaledge/1/2008/03/Nielsen-Online-Names-Top-30-News-Sites.cfm, from Nielson Online. Note: Data are based on the top 30 most visited sites, and are percentages of unique viewers in February 2008. Newspapers include individual newspapers and news services (like Gannett); TV includes cable TV news sites and national broadcast networks and their affiliates.

originate from newspapers, TV, wire services, and from other sources such as press release distributors. Wire services include the Associated Press, Reuters, and the like. Taken together, most “new media” outlets only constitute about 8 percent of the Web news audience. Thus, the bulk of gathering, writing, and distributing news falls on traditional news organizations, whose problem is not in figuring out how to be journalists, but how to make journalism pay in a starkly changed business environment in which people are consuming news for free, or almost for free. This trend has, in particular, angered Rupert Murdoch, chairman and CEO of News Corporation, which owns The Wall Street Journal and Fox, among other media outlets. Murdoch argues that Google News “steals” its content when it brings up his properties (The Wall Street Journal, Fox News Channel, and so on) in their searches.33 If journalists continue to produce news, we must remember that journalists often cover political campaigns in packs, and use the same themes in their stories. Indeed, a journalist for a mainstream publication who deviates too far from the consensus line of the story is likely to be asked why.34 Pack journalism may be an exaggerated term, but years of experience show that media follow dominant themes. What’s more, greater diversity—which would break down the influence of pack journalism—does

154 Chapter 5 not really exist. Instead, the same organizations that traditionally covered the news on radio and TV are covering the news in the new media environment. The news is still gathered by a relatively small number of journalists for mass audiences. The number of journalists is growing smaller as local newspapers cede coverage of national and international news to relatively few news services and newspapers, and all but the very largest newspapers close bureaus and lay off staff. Even if more information—or more access to information—is a given, it is not clear that the diversity of information on the Web extends to information useful for people in a democracy. Like many social scientists, I tend to be critical of the media because of their shortcomings in providing information that citizens can use to make political and policy choices. Indeed, much of the material published online, even by sites like CNN, is soft news (and my impression is that, in the last ten years, it has gotten much softer) such as celebrity gossip, and a great deal of bandwidth is consumed by fluff from sites like TMZ and Perez Hilton (which is entertaining, no doubt). The news media are not the only resource for policy makers. Citizens therefore may be at an informational disadvantage compared with the “insiders” if the news media do not cover important policy information and choose, instead, to give over their space to fluff. John Kingdon, in his interviews with key decision makers in transportation and health care, found that relatively few of them cited the media as an important source of information and ideas.35 And Howlett and Ramesh note that policy makers are for the most part intelligent and resourceful individuals who understand their own interest and have their own ideas about appropriate or feasible policy options and are not easily swayed by media or the mere fact of media attention. Indeed they often use the media to their own advantage. It is not uncommon for public officials and successful interest groups to provide selective information to the media to bolster their case.36

Note that Howlett and Ramesh are saying two things here: that ideas do not necessarily come from media attention or coverage pressure, but that groups still recognize the value of the media in helping them make their case. In this realization, groups and officials know what students of the media have suspected for years: that the media do not tell us what to think, but help shape the things we think about. And, as Baumgartner and Jones note, when the news media cover an issue intensively and “negatively” (from the perspective of the groups under scrutiny), the more likely public pressure for some sort of solution will ensue.37 This sort of pressure can be generated and continued in online outlets. Subgovernments, Issue Networks, and Domains If this chapter were to end here, you might be left with the impression that there are no patterns in the relationships between the actors in the policy process and that the

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

process is characterized by chaos or a lack of interaction between groups. You know intuitively that this is not true: the actors in the policy process can and must interact with each other to advance policy proposals. Without this interaction, nothing would happen, and policy making would come to a standstill. Fortunately, we need not worry that Congress, bureaucrats, the president, the courts, the people, the media, interest groups, and all the other actors will suddenly stop making policy. Rather, our task is to make some sense of these very complex interactions. The Constitution and statute law structure many of these interactions, such as the relationships among the three branches of government. Others are informally structured but equally important to policy making. To understand how these interactions work, we start with the idea of a policy domain. A policy domain is the substantive area of policy over which participants in policy making compete and compromise,38 such as the environmental policy domain or the health care policy domain. Of course, some of these domains are so vast that they contain other domains, such as the air pollution domain, the water pollution domain, or the mental health domain. The activities that take place within these domains are influenced by other domains, and issues and ideas often spill over from one domain to the others.39 And, indeed, the boundaries between domains are often so indistinct that it is sometimes difficult to discern exactly what the “health care policy domain” or the “homeland security domain” really is.40 The political culture of the nation and the existing legal environment and doctrine influence the overall environment in which policy is made in these domains. As we have seen, these environmental features are fairly stable in the short run but often change in the long run; our political culture and legal doctrines treat women and minorities considerably differently than they did fifty years ago, for example. The domain is also influenced by how people conceive of the nature of a problem, what causes the problem, and the range of potential solutions to the problem. Contained within the policy domain is the policy community, which consists of actors who are involved in policy making in a particular domain. The policy community consists of those who are most expert in studying, understanding, negotiating, or explaining an issue. The nature and composition of the policy community is not, however, permanently fixed. There is variation in how easily one can join a policy community. Some are open to participation by a variety of interests and actors. Others tend to be closed and operate in relative obscurity. A considerable amount of effort has been expended by political scientists in trying to explain how policy communities organize themselves into something less than a political free-for-all in which every possible interest fights with all comers. Rather, we know intuitively that these interests and groups are likely to form connections, alliances, and coalitions. One way these participants organize is in an iron triangle of mutually reinforcing relationships between regulated interests, the congressional committee or subcommittee charged with lawmaking on the particular issue, and the agency charged with regulating the interests in question.

155

policy domain. The substantive area of policy over which participants in policy making compete and compromise, such as the environmental policy domain or the health policy domain.

policy community. The group of actors—such as interest groups, government agencies, the media, and elected officials—that is actively involved in policy making in a particular domain. This group is generally thought of as being more open and dynamic than an iron triangle or subgovernment.

156 Chapter 5 iron triangle. A particular style of subgovernment in which there are mutually reinforcing relationships between a regulated interest, the agency charged with regulation, and the congressional subcommittee charged with policy making in that issue area. This way of characterizing policy-making relationships has largely given way to more sophisticated subgovernment concepts, such as issue networks. logrolling. The legislative practice of trading commitments to vote for members’ preferred policies.

The most striking feature of the iron triangle is the mutually reinforcing nature of the relationships therein. The regulated interest, the agency, and the congressional subcommittee make policy based on their common perception of the issues and goals. The regulators tend to negotiate with the regulated, rather than imposing their ideas. Because there are benefits to all parties, this relationship has the potential for long-term stability. Baumgartner and Jones call such tightly knit relationships “policy monopolies.”41 For example, farm policy is largely controlled by the appropriate bureau in the United States Department of Agriculture, by its parallel subcommittee (for example, the Subcommittee on Livestock, Dairy, and Poultry), and by the interest being regulated or supported (in this case, livestock, dairy, and poultry interests). Other areas in which iron triangles are found include public works projects and big water projects, particularly in the western states, where subcommittees in the Department of the Interior committee are committed to logrolling (that is, trading commitments to vote on each other’s bills) and promoting member interests, usually related to helping local constituents, in their districts. The iron triangle continues to have a significant influence over the way relationships involved in policy making are depicted in texts on American politics. Given that so much policy is made outside of popular or media scrutiny, this seems sensible. But the problem with this depiction of policy making is that, as Hugh Heclo writes, the “iron triangle concept was not so much wrong as it is disastrously incomplete.”42 The examples of the types of policies that iron triangles address are largely distributive policies in which costs are dispersed and benefits are concentrated. (I discuss these policy types in detail in chapter 7.) In such policies, few “outside” interests meddle in decision making: bureaus, subcommittees, and regulated interests dominate, and the relationships between organizations remains stable. But if we look at the other policy types, we see greater conflict, more peak organization involvement, and greater involvement on the part of committees and whole houses of Congress, rather than individual subcommittees. Due to the controversial nature of some policies, something less closed and secretive than iron triangle styles of subgovernment must exist and the iron triangle concept covers only a small part of policy making. Even the policies that were characterized by iron triangle politics have become more prone to conflict as new actors and new voices enter and others exit the debate. Congress’s assertion of its power in the early 1970s, combined with the decentralization of power in Congress itself, created more conflict between committees and more points of entry to the political and policy processes. Baumgartner and Jones argue that these multiple points of access allow interest groups to go “venue shopping” in a search for a committee or subcommittee to serve as the most likely forum for their claims. Additional access to the policy process has been afforded through greater government openness, such as through sunshine laws and the Freedom of Information Act (see chapter 2), and through greater sophistication of interest groups in exploiting

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

points of access, such as committee hearings and public comment opportunities for regulations. This is not to say that policy is generally made out in the open; rather, social scientists now believe that policy making in general is not as closed as the old iron triangle model would lead us to believe. Heclo also notes that the federal budget and the volume of rule-making activity have substantially increased since 1950. With very large amounts of money and power at stake, politics and policy have become more contentious; the opening of government to greater citizen participation has allowed more groups to weigh in on policy, with an associated increase in conflict, number of veto points, and so forth. Heclo notes that, with greater funding being passed to state and local units of government and greater regulation accompanying these transfers of funds, more of these units of government are operating as lobbyists and serving as interest groups in their own right. All state governments, many city governments, and the key associations that represent governors, legislators, state judges, and local governments have offices in Washington and participate in federal policy making at every stage of the process. At the same time, the devolution of power to local and state governments creates new venues for interest groups to participate in policy making, because state and local governments are again very important decision-making bodies. How, then, do we describe policy-making relationships without reverting to the old iron triangle formulation? The term subgovernment came into use in the late 1960s to describe a policy network or policy subsystem that was most involved in making policy in a particular policy domain. As Ripley and Franklin define them, “subgovernments are clusters of individuals that effectively make most of the routine decisions in a given substantive area of policy.43 Heclo proposes the “issue network” as a superior way of depicting subgovernment politics. The issue network consists of the various government agencies, committees, groups, and interests that hope to influence an issue. This term is very similar to the idea of policy communities, which were defined earlier, and both communities and “networks are ways of describing subgovernments that are more open to information and to participation than are closed systems like iron triangles. In large and contentious issues like health care reform, the policy community is vast, with hundreds of interest groups plying every member of Congress (not solely key committee members) with ideas to promote their interests. While these depictions of issue networks and policy communities have proved useful to students of public policy, they do not help us to understand the ebb and flow of policy making over time. Baumgartner and Jones argue that policy making still involves relatively long periods of stasis punctuated by changes in the political equilibrium. Paul Sabatier provides a framework for policy making called the advocacy coalition framework (ACF), which helps us to make some sense of what often look like chaotic issue networks.44 We return to the ACF in chapter 10, where we examine current models of public policy. Finally, on the question of how we conceive of the organization of interests, we

157

sub� government. The policy network or subsystem that is most involved in making policy in a particular domain. policy network. Another term for issue network.

issue network. A term that describes the relationships between the various actors and interests in a particular policy issue. Hugh Heclo promoted this term because it describes a more open policymaking system that contains more actors and relationships than the older iron triangle concept.

158 Chapter 5 policy regime. A system of policies intended to achieve broad policy goals, such as homeland security. Policy regimes can be more or less coherent in terms of the goals and structure of the policies and of the participants in the process.

can think more broadly about the idea of a policy regime. The policy regime idea is particularly well suited to policies where there is no single clear, coherent, policy community where people speak the same language, even as they have sufficiently similar goals that suggest that their efforts can or should work together. These “boundary spanning” problems cannot be fully described by traditional notions of policy networks and domains. Policy regime theory borrows from research on international regimes and urban regimes, and recognizes that there is more to a policy subsystem than a series of institutional arrangements. Indeed, while we understand that policy subsystems are not solely about government action—there are many other actors involved—it is understood that thinking about policy regimes moves us far away from institutions as central to policy regimes, and moves us closer to realizing that groups, interests, and ideas are central to thinking about how group politics is organized.45 Prying Open Policy Networks While policy scholars now think more in terms of regimes, networks, communities, and coalitions than issue networks, access to policy making is clearly not wide open. For example, in environmental policy, major business interests often dominate smaller groups with limited resources. This is particularly true when an issue is local or when the big national environmental groups, such as the Sierra Club, choose not to engage an issue. In homeland security, major defense contractors tend to dominate other participants in policy making. In health care policy, big insurance companies, the pharmaceutical industry, and the American Medical Association tend to dominate the debate. But policy change is possible, as was evident in the New Deal, the civil rights movement, and the Great Society programs, all periods in which government took on more tasks and protected more groups and interests. Policy changed in the other direction during the Carter, Reagan, and Bush administrations, when more conservative preferences led to attempts to make government smaller. These changes happened because policy networks were forced to open up to other voices and participants. As a result, the nature and composition of advocacy coalitions changed, and new coalitions were created or significantly altered. Nor are big, sweeping changes that involve great matters of state and ideology the only sorts of policy changes. There are many examples of relatively small, focused movements grabbing attention and adherents nationwide. Civil rights and environmental groups started as relatively small groups in the early twentieth century. These groups grew as concerns about equality and environmental damage became more important to more people. In the past twenty-five years, groups such as Mothers Against Drunk Driving (MADD) have spawned policy changes. MADD not only advanced the issue of drunk driving to the national agenda, but also succeeded in inducing states to stiffen their penalties for driving while intoxicated (DWI). In a

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

sense, a small social movement was created calling for greater individual responsibility and stricter sanctions against those who do not exercise responsibility. There are many ways that new and established groups can follow in the footsteps of these historic examples, all of which have one thing in common: they all created opportunities for participation in policy making where such opportunities were inaccessible. There are at least four ways to gain this access. Exploiting the Decentralization of American Government By definition, grassroots groups are unlikely to tackle vast federal-level problems. Indeed, James Madison, one of the founders of our Constitution, argued that the constitutional structure was designed to prevent or compartmentalize national movements. In MADD’s case, drunken driving was to a large extent a state and local issue that involved establishing and enforcing DWI laws. Tackling the problem at the local level—in this case, California—made the most sense in terms of the early MADD’s limited resources and because the founder of the group, whose child was killed by a drunk driver, lived in California. Modern communications media, however, make it easier for new and grassroots groups like MADD to mobilize, expand issues, and grow in both membership and geographic reach. Going Public If government institutions such as congressional committees are closed off to groups promoting change, such groups are likely to appeal to others besides these institutions. Given that, at least theoretically, political power is derived from our consent, it is reasonable for groups to appeal to us directly in conjunction with trying to gain status within a policy network or community. There are many ways groups can “go public.” Traditionally, groups have run direct mail campaigns and phone solicitations and have placed ads in major newspapers. If you subscribe to magazines with an identifiable ideological label, you will often get mailings from groups associated with that ideology: those who subscribe to The Nation, for example, are more likely to get mail from the American Civil Liberties Union (ACLU) than are readers of the more conservative National Review. Large full-page ads run in The New York Times and other important journals of news and opinion, both to mobilize people to join a cause such as protesting the World Trade Organization or questioning the importance of global warming, and to influence the key policy makers who read these publications. An emerging method of going public is the increasing use of the Internet and its possibilities for low-cost communication among group members and potential members. Kevin Hill and John Hughes argue that the Internet allows groups to communicate at considerably lower “transaction costs” than more traditional means of communication: after all, once a group sets up a Web site, it costs no more for

159

160 Chapter 5 one person or one thousand or one hundred thousand to see it. An e-mail message to one member of a group can just as easily be sent to several thousand simultaneously.46 It is fair to say that the Internet has provided campaigns and causes with important and efficient new tools for mobilizing people and advancing their policy ideas. A recent example of such a group is MoveOn.org, a liberal group that began an e-mail campaign to press Congress to “move on” after the impeachment, but failed conviction, of President Clinton in 1998 and 1999. The group continued as an active mobilizer on the left, and its high-water mark may have been its successful efforts to defeat then-Democratic Senator Joseph Lieberman of Connecticut in the 2006 primaries; its influence did not extend to the general election, however, which Lieberman won as an independent. Lieberman continues to caucus, for the most part, with Senate Democrats and MoveOn’s later efforts became so controversial that their influence began to wane. But the group still exists, and has served as a model for Internet-based mobilization for liberal and conservative groups alike.47 Conclusion Many people find it very hard to understand what the government does and how they can play a role in it. As many public opinion polls have shown, people think that the government is distant, uncaring, hard to understand, and unable to be influenced by individual action. This feeling is understandable—governments are large, complicated, and sometimes frustrating institutions. However, to give up on trying to understand government and to fail to participate in its decisions is to abdicate one’s rights and, indeed, one’s duties as a citizen. Because our government rules us, in John Locke’s words, “with the consent of the governed”—that is, with our consent—we have a role in overseeing the government. This argument is clearly rooted in a sense of civic obligation, and induces some people to vote, keep up with the news (and not just by watching the TV), and be aware of community concerns. But doing one’s civic duty is often less compelling than the desire to do a good job, be a good parent/friend/neighbor/partner, or just relax and avoid the stress that sometimes accompanies current affairs. A more compelling reason for getting involved in making public policy is that if you and your friends fail to get involved, other people, who may very likely be working contrary to what you perceive to be your interests, may be effective in their work with the opposition. For example, you may find a book in the library that you believe contains racist, sexist, obscene, or antisocial material that is suitable for adult use only. You believe that minors’ access to the book should be prohibited. If you and your friends (or political allies) do nothing, it is likely that the book will remain on the shelf. If, however, you and your political allies mobilize to restrict access to adults only, it is likely that this restriction will be imposed. Conversely, if you believe strongly in freedom of thought and information, you might mobilize to counter the actions of those who would restrict access to books.

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

A cynic would argue that the inequities in power and resources make it impossible to take on interests that would block policy change, and that any effort to promote change would be a waste of time. Policy making is indeed a slow and challenging process, and sometimes groups are disadvantaged and unable to do much to cause change. It is not easy to achieve social change. Indeed, the constitutional structure of the United States is in many ways explicitly designed to promote stability and hinders change.48 I am not suggesting here that policy change is easy, that you or a group that you form or join will see results immediately, or even that your policy preferences will be translated into actual governmental policy. But if a goal is worth achieving, it is worth the hard work and patience needed to achieve it. American policy history is full of examples in which people decided not to remain on the sidelines. The women’s suffrage movement, the civil rights movement, the women’s equality movement, and the crackdown on drunk driving are examples of social movements that relied upon the involvement of citizens, not big interest groups with an army of expensive lobbyists. In recent years, citizens and their attorneys have sued tobacco companies for damages caused by smoking. This success in turn emboldened states to sue the tobacco companies to recover state Medicaid costs incurred by sick smokers. In pursuit of tougher drunk-driving laws, MADD stood its ground against the restaurant, bar, tavern, and beverage interests. Labor unions have fought and won political battles with management. In addition, in perhaps the most important social change in our nation’s history, people coalesced to fight institutionalized racism and to secure the rights of African Americans to vote, buy property, and seek and hold employment. Lest you think that all these movements are “liberal” in the popular sense, there are current social movements to press for abortion restrictions or prohibitions, to reduce taxes, to ensure the right to own and legally use firearms, and to introduce moral education and values in the school. All these struggles are difficult, none have been fully resolved to everyone’s satisfaction, and we may not agree on what they are trying to accomplish, but they do yield important changes in policy and in public attitudes. And regardless of whether you agree with the ideologies behind these struggles, these issues are important and worth debating and discussing, if for no other reason than to ensure the continued vitality of our political process. Unfortunately, many people do not participate in these debates, leading to atrophy in our political institutions. This trend will continue at great peril to our social, political, and economic well-being. Why, if the odds are stacked, as they often seem to be, against the “little people,” do people get involved in policy making? Perhaps a main reason is that people sense that they can influence policy, particularly at the local level, by taking a clear and public position on an issue that affects them. Often people have an intense interest in the substance of issues. Many people who care deeply about the environment, for example, feel they have a responsibility to address environmental problems to ensure a better life for future generations. Other people get involved simply because

161

162 Chapter 5 they like to participate in politics and enjoy it the same way other people enjoy sports or hobbies. Most people get involved in the policy process when something happens in their local community that mobilizes them and induces them to care deeply about a particular issue. Those of us who are intensely interested in politics and policy should not condemn those who fail to meet our standards of passion and fascination with the process. While most people do not follow day-to-day politics, many people can be mobilized to address a particular issue when it is of interest and concern to them. Sometimes their mobilization will dismay you—if you are a liberal, you would rather not see conservatives mobilize to exclude certain books from libraries—but keep in mind that there are plenty of people who will work with your side to attempt to advance your preferred style of policy change. Key Terms Astroturf groups Economic interest groups Free rider Institutional interest group Interest group Iron triangle Issue network Lobbying

Logrolling Mobilization Muckrakers Peak association Policy community Policy domain Policy network Policy regime Policy subsystem

Public interest Public interest groups Social media Social movement Subgovernment Think tanks Venue shopping

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research ╇ 1. Many people have argued that there really isn’t any difference between the Democratic and Republican parties—that they stand for basically the same things and that it really doesn’t matter which party gains power. Do you agree or disagree? Can you think of ways one would objectively compare the differences between the policy preferences of the two parties? Would the 2008 elections change some people’s position on this statement? Do you think the formation of a third party could somehow change the nature of American politics and result in noticeable policy change? ╇ 2. Consider Madison’s view of interest groups in Federalist 10. Do you think if James Madison were alive today that he would think that “special interests” have become too powerful in Washington, DC? In what ways would he be concerned? In what ways might he not be too concerned? ╇ 3. Have you considered working as a lobbyist? If you could be a lobbyist, what would your dream job look like? For whom or for what interest

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

would you lobby? Whom would you lobby? How would you influence the people you want to influence? What would be your goals and your measure of whether you successfully met your goals? Would you have to compromise your beliefs and values to be a lobbyist? Would this matter? ╇ 4. What were muckrakers? Can you think of any examples of muckraking journalism today? Is such journalism very common? Why or why not? Has the advent of the Internet created more or fewer opportunities for muckraking or for, to use the more neutral terms, “investigative journalism” or “enterprise journalism”? Has the rise of the Internet and new media reduced traditional journalism’s capacity or commitment to investigative journalism? ╇ 5. From which media outlets do you get your news? Radio? TV? Newspapers? Web sites? Which sources among these media do you rely on most? Compare your newsgathering habits to those of your friends and family. How are they similar or different? Do people’s choices vary by age or by political ideology? Which medium do you consider the most complete and most trustworthy? Why? ╇ 6. In what sense are the media not passive actors? How do the media influence public policy? Many members of the news media say that they are just a “mirror” of society and that they simply reflect what happens in society. They would argue that their influence is relatively small. Do you agree or disagree with this position? ╇ 7. Think of a policy area that might be characterized by an “iron triangle” style of subgovernment. Why do you think this is better described as an “iron triangle” than as an “issue network”? Why does Heclo believe that an issue network is a preferable way to describe subgovernment politics than the iron triangle model? ╇ 8. Think of an area of public policy you care a great deal about. Using the various searching tools available at your library, find four or five years’ worth of congressional hearings on a subject. Find out who testifies before Congress on these issues. Are you surprised by what you found? Do you think that some voices are over- or underrepresented? Why? 9. Along the same lines, search news media coverage of issues using LexisNexis or similar databases (don’t use just Google or another search engine— you can get outdated or otherwise odd results). Whom do journalists quote the most in the stories you found? Are there voices that are left out? 10. Search the Internet for interest groups on an issue of importance to you. One way to make sure you get interest groups is to ask Google to search only sites that end in .org. For example, if you were interested in endangered species you would enter into Google this search: endangered species site: .org. What do you find? Are there a lot of groups or just a few? Do they

163

164 Chapter 5 seem equally large and powerful or is there some variation in their apparent power and influence? What led you to your conclusions? 11. I Googled think tanks and found some interesting results. There is a World Directory of Think Tanks published by the National Institute for Research Advancement (NIRA) in Japan (http://www.nira.or.jp/past/). Click on Think Tank Information then NIRA’s World Directory of Think Tanks. This page lists think tanks by country. Scroll down the page and click on the list of think tanks in the United States. Are some of the think tanks listed in the United States clearly ideologically based? Are others more politically neutral? How can you tell from reading their Web sites—if you can tell at all? (A decidedly Left-leaning view of think tanks is available at SourceWatch .org, http://www.disinfopedia.org/wiki.phtml?title=Think_tanks.) Additional Reading On the question of why interest groups form, and why it is that interest groups must form to pursue their interests, the classic text is by Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971). The interaction of parties and groups in the policy process is taken up in two books: John C. Green and Daniel M. Shea, eds., The State of the Parties: The Changing Role of American Political Parties, 5th ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2007); and Ronald Hrebenar, Political Parties, Interest Groups, and Political Campaigns (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999). The question of whether or not one can say that the interest group universe is characterized by pluralism or elitism remains controversial in the social sciences. There are hundreds, if not thousands, of books on the news media and politics. Many of these books are ideological attacks on the so-called liberal or conservative media. Such analyses are generally not useful for understanding the influence of the media in a scientific and rational way. More useful analyses undertaken by social scientists include Doris A. Graber, Mass Media and American Politics, 8th ed. (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2010); W. Lance Bennett, News, the Politics of Illusion, 6th ed. (New York: Longman, 2004); and Timothy E. Cook, Governing with the News: The News Media as a Political Institution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998). Recent works on the Internet, politics, and journalism include Eric Boehlert, Bloggers on the Bus: How the Internet Changed Politics and the Press in 2008 (New York: Free Press, 2009); Natalie Fenton, New Media, Old News: Journalism and Democracy in the Digital Age (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2009); and Philip Meyer, The Vanishing Newspaper: Saving Journalism in the Information Age, 2d ed. (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2009). The literature on the organization of policy subsystems, networks, or subgovernments is quite rich. Among the most influential articles on this question is Hugh Heclo’s “Issue Networks and the Executive Establishment,” in The New American

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

165

Political System, edited by Anthony King (Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1978). Paul Sabatier’s work on the Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF) has been particularly influential in our understanding of how policy communities are organized. Two key books on the ACF include Paul Sabatier’s Theories of the Policy Process (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999), and Paul Sabatier and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith, Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993). Notes 1. James Chesney and Otto Feinstein, “Making Political Activity a Requirement in Introductory Political Science Courses,” PS: Political Science and Politics 26, no. 3 (1993): 535–38; Hindy Lauer Schachter, Reinventing Government or Reinventing Ourselves: The Role of Citizen Owners in Making a Better Government (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997). 2. Center for Information and Research on Civic Learning and Engagement, The 2006 Civic and Political Health of the Nation: A Detailed Look at How Youth Participate in Politics and Communities (College Park, MD: Center for Information and Research on Civic Learning and Engagement, 2006), http://www.civicyouth.org/PopUps/2006_CPHS_Report_update.pdf. 3. Cliff Zukin, Scott Keeter, Molly Andolina, Krista Jenkins, and Michael X. Delli Carpinin, A New Engagement? Political Participation, Civic Life, and the Changing American Citizen (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006). 4. Morris P. Fiorina, Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment, 2d ed. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004). 5. Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States, 2d ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 1979). 6. Andrew McFarland, “Interest Groups and Theories of Power in America,” British Journal of Political Science 16 (1978): 129–147. 7. Michael Howlett and M. Ramesh, Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems (Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1995), 57. 8. AARP used to stand for the American Association of Retired Persons, but the organization is simply known now as AARP because it claims to represent the interests of older Americans, whether or not they are retired. A humorous discussion of this name change is found in Jennifer Fisher, “Becoming a ‘Classic’; Everything Old Needs to be Renamed,” Pittsburgh Post-Gazette, August 17, 2004, B2. 9. All quotes from Howlett and Ramesh, Studying Public Policy, 57. 10. Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971). 11. There are, of course, both benefits and costs to this tax deduction. See Edward L. Glaeser and Jesse M. Shapiro, “The Benefits of the Home Mortgage Interest Deduction,” in NBER Working Paper Series (Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research, 2002), http://www.nber.org/papers/w9284. 12. David B. Robertson and Dennis R. Judd, The Development of American Public Policy: The Structure of Policy Restraint (Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman and Company, 1989). 13. Barbara Barrett, “North Carolina companies spend big to influence health bill,” Politics AP, July 29, 2009, http://www.miamiherald.com/news/politics/AP/story/1162716.html (accessed August 24, 2009). 14. See http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/health-system-reform/index.shtml (accessed October 1, 2009). 15. Olson, The Logic of Collective Action. 16. 528 U.S. 377 (2000). 17. “The Fog of Ethics in Albany,” The New York Times, October 27, 2009, http://www.nytimes.com/2009/10/28/ opinion/28wed1.html. 18. 410 U.S. 113 (1973). 19. The term “venue shopping” in the policy process is described in some detail in Frank Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones, Agendas and Instability in American Politics, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009).

166 Chapter 5 An example of the importance of venue shopping in actual policy making is provided by Sarah B. Pralle, “Venue Shopping, Political Strategy, and Policy Change: The Internationalization of Canadian Forest Advocacy, Journal of Public Policy 23, no. 3 (2003): 233–60, extended upon in her book Branching Out, Digging In: Environmental Advocacy and Agenda Setting (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006). Randall Rosenberg provides a critical view of the use of litigation as a means of inducing policy change in the judiciary in The Hollow Hope (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991). 20. Samuel J. Eldersveld, Political Parties in American Society (New York: Basic Books, 1982); John C. Green and Daniel M. Shea, eds., The State of the Parties: The Changing Role of Contemporary American Parties, 4th ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003); Ronald Hrebenar, Political Parties, Interest Groups, and Political Campaigns (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999). 21. A comprehensive listing of think tanks is available at the University of Michigan’s Web site, http://www.lib. umich.edu/govdocs/psthink.html. As noted in this chapter, a leftist perspective on think tanks can be found at http:// www.disinfopedia.org/wiki.phtml ?title=Think_tanks. 22. Dean E. Alger, The Media and Politics, 2d ed. (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1996); Doris A. Graber, Mass Media and American Politics, 8th ed. (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2010); Timothy E. Cook, Governing with the News: The News Media as a Political Institution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998); W. Lance Bennett, News, the Politics of Illusion, 6th ed, (New York: Longman, 2004). 23. For example, Carl Bernstein, and Bob Woodward, All the President’s Men (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974). 24. Found at http://www.pulitzer.org/bycat/Public-Service. 25. Anya Kamenetz, “Will NPR Save the News?” Fast Company, March 18, 2009, http://www.fastcompany. com/magazine/134/finely-tuned.html?page=0,0. 26. Annenberg Public Policy Center, University of Pennsylvania, “Daily Show Viewers Knowledgeable about Presidential Campaign, National Annenberg Election Survey Shows,” September 21, 2004, http://www.annenbergpublicpolicycenter.org/naes/2004_03_late-night-knowledge-2_9–21_pr.pdf (accessed October 1, 2004). 27. E.E. Schattschneider, The Semisovereign People (Hinsdale, IL: The Dryden Press, 1975). 28. Ibid. 29. Baumgartner and Jones, Agendas and Instability. 30. Roger W. Cobb and Charles D. Elder, Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda Building, 2nd ed. (Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1983). 142–43. 31. See, for example, Lawrie Mifflin, “An ABC News Reporter Tests the Boundaries of Investigating Disney and Finds Them,” The New York Times, October 19, 1998, 8C; and “Timid Media Giants,” Phoenix Gazette, December 9, 1995, B6. 32. My thinking on this point is particularly influenced by W. Lance Bennett, News: The Politics of Illusion, 7th ed. (New York: Longman, 2006). 33. Dirk Smillie, “Murdoch Wants a Google Rebellion,” Forbes.com., April 3, 2009, http://www.forbes. com/2009/04/03/rupert-murdoch-google-business-media-murdoch.html (accessed February 17, 2010). 34. One of the first and still one of the classic treatments of pack journalism is Tim Crouse, The Boys on the Bus (New York: Random House, 1973). 35. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies, 2d ed. (New York: Harper Collins, 1995), 57–61. 36. Howlett and Ramesh, Studying Public Policy, 59. 37. Baumgartner and Jones, Agendas and Instability. 38. Edward O. Laumann and David Knoke, The Organizational State: Social Choice in National Policy Domains (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987). 39. Kingdon, Agendas, 190–94. 40. Peter J. May, Ashley E. Jochim, and Joshua Sapotichne, “Policy Regimes and Governance: Constructing Homeland Security.” Paper presented at the Public Management Research Association, Columbus, OH, October 2009. 41. Baumgartner and Jones, Agendas and Instability. 42. Hugh Heclo, “Issue Networks and the Executive Establishment,” in The New American Political System, ed. Anthony King (Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1978), 88.

Unofficial Actors

and

Their Roles

in

Public Policy

167

43. Randall Ripley and Grace Franklin, Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy, 5th ed. (Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks-Cole, 1991). 44. Sabatier and his colleagues have written extensively on this framework. The most comprehensive treatment is Paul Sabatier and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith, Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993). 45. Ashley E. Jochim, and Peter J. May, “Beyond Subsystems: Policy Regimes and Governance.” Paper presented at the Association for Public Policy Analysis and Management, Washington, DC, 2009. 46. Keven A. Hill and John E. Hughes, Cyberpolitics: Citizen Participation in the Age of the Internet (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998). 47. Christopher Hayes, “MoveOn.org Is Not as Radical as Conservatives Think,” The Nation, July 16, 2008, http://www.thenation.com/doc/20080804/hayes (accessed December 31, 2009); Art Moore, “‘Conservative MoveOn. org’ Targets Hillary Case,” World Net Daily, January 14, 2008, http://70.85.195.205/news/article.asp?ARTICLE_ ID=59676 (accessed December 31, 2009). 48. Robertson and Judd, Development of American Public Policy.

Agenda Setting, Power, and Interest Groups

agenda. The list of things being discussed and sometimes acted upon by an institution, the news media, or the public at large. agenda setting. The process by which problems and alternative solutions gain or lose public and elite attention, or the activities of various actors and groups that cause issues to gain greater attention or prevent them from gaining attention.

6

CHAPTER

Chapter at a Glance Agenda Setting The Idea of Political Power Groups and Power in Public Policy Overcoming the Power Deficit—Ways to Induce Policy Change Indicators, Focusing Events, and Agenda Change Group Coalescence and Strategies for Change The Social Construction of Problems Conditions and Problems Symbols Causal Stories Numbers as Indicators of Problems Case Study: The September 11 Attacks as a Focusing Event Conclusion Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

In The Semisovereign People, E.E. Schattschneider asserts that “the definition of the alternatives is the supreme instrument of power.”1 The definition of alternative issues, problems, and solutions is crucial, because it establishes which issues, problems, and solutions will gain the attention of the public and decision makers and which, in turn, are most likely to gain broader attention. This chapter considers the processes by which groups work to elevate their issues on the agenda while denying other issues a place on the agenda. The discussion begins with the agenda-setting process and then turns to a review of current thinking about political power in the context of public policy making. Readers who value broad-based participation in politics and policy making—that is, those who believe that American politics is characterized by pluralism—may find this discussion of political power dispiriting, as much of the current literature on political power and interest groups adopts the elite theory perspective. Elite theory suggests that relatively few people in key positions in government, industry,

168

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

academe, the media, and other institutions control a disproportionate share of the nation’s economic and political resources. In the discussion that follows, you will see distinct echoes of this way of thinking. At the same time you will learn that policy elites do not all think alike or move in lockstep with each other to promote a unified “agenda.” Also, these elites are not static. As discussed in earlier chapters and as noted here, while the American system of government and politics often favors more powerful and more focused economic interests over less powerful, more diffuse interests, often the less powerful interests—or, as I sometimes call them, disadvantaged interests—can coalesce and, when the time is right, find avenues for the promotion of their ideas. Before we turn to this discussion, let us consider how issues reach public attention in the first place: that is, how they reach the agenda. Agenda Setting Agenda setting is the process by which problems and alternative solutions gain or lose public and elite attention. Group competition to set the agenda is fierce because no society, political system, official actor, unofficial actor, or individual person has the capacity to address all possible alternatives to all possible problems that arise at any one time.2 Groups must promote their issues’ places among all the other issues sharing the limited space on the agenda, or to prepare for the time when a crisis makes their issue more likely to occupy a more prominent space. Even when an issue gains attention, groups must fight to ensure that their depiction of the issue remains in the forefront and that their preferred approaches to the problem are those that are most actively considered. They do so for the very reasons cited by Schattschneider: The group that successfully describes a problem will also be the one that defines the solutions to it, thereby prevailing in the policy debate. At the same time, groups fight to keep issues off the agenda.3 At this point, it is very important to understand what I mean by the term “agenda.” The term has morphed, in recent political discourse, as a way to promote fear and divisiveness over another groups’ goals in the policy process. Merriam-Webster’s online dictionary provides two definitions of the word “agenda.” 1: a list or outline of things to be considered or done 2: an underlying often ideological plan or program

The Oxford English Dictionary provides a similar second definition: “A campaign, programme, or plan of action arising from underlying principles, motivations, etc. Hence: the set of underlying motives or ideals of a particular individual or group.” The term has come to take on sinister overtones about “hidden agendas,” which many people associate with conspiracies or, at least, unclear motives. Of course, a group’s overt agenda—that is, the implicit or explicit list of things it would like to

169 pluralism. In group theories of politics, the theory, assumption, or belief that there are many groups that compete with each other in a reasonably open political system and that policy results from this group competition. Contrast with elitism. elite theory. In studies of groups and politics, the theory or belief that policy making is dominated by the best educated, wealthiest, and most powerful elites. This position is most closely associated with sociologist C. Wright Mills. Contrast with pluralism.

170 Chapter 6

condition. A fact or situation that may be unpleasant but about which nothing can be done. For example, the weather can be thought of as a condition. Compare with a problem. enactment. The act of putting a decision, such as legislation or regulation, into effect. Statute laws are generally enacted in the United States when the president or a state governor signs a bill presented by the legislature or when a legislature or Congress overrides a governor’s or president’s veto. systemic agenda. Any issue, problem or idea that could possibly be considered by participants in the policy process, provided that the idea does not fall outside well-established social, political, ideological, and legal norms. agenda universe. The list of all the possible ideas that could ever be advanced in any society. Compare to the systemic agenda.

accomplish—can be used to attack that group. A common contemporary version of this usage is in discussions of gay, bisexual, lesbian, and transgendered (GBLT) groups’ efforts to achieve certain civil rights like marriage and the ability to adopt children, or to be protected from hate crimes. Their opponents—particularly among political conservatives—use the phrase “gay agenda” to describe what they believe are these groups’ efforts to promote their ideas. This terminology is equally applied to left- and right-wing groups, but, it is testament to Americans’ continued beliefs in political conspiracies, shadowy plots, and unclear group motivations, as famously noted by Richard Hofstadter.4 These types of arguments resonate well in a culture that, since the founding, has valued organized group action as an important part of pluralism, while also bemoaning the power of certain groups. To help you understand groups, power, and agenda setting, I begin with a brief discussion of the idea of political power, since one of its main uses is to keep ideas and issues on or off the public agenda. I then describe how the debate over issues begins with whether something is a problem, about which something can be done, or a condition, about which little can be done. I then turn to a discussion of the levels of the agenda and how groups use their power to influence agenda items by advancing alternative social constructions of problems. Central to understanding agenda setting is the meaning of the term “agenda” as it is meant in the social sciences. An agenda is a collection of problems; understandings of causes, symbols, solutions, and other elements of public problems that come to the attention of members of the public and their governmental officials. An agenda can be something as concrete as a list of bills that are before a legislature or a series of beliefs about the existence and magnitude of problems and how they should be addressed by government, by the private sector, by nonprofit organizations, or through joint action by some or all of these institutions. Agendas exist at all levels of government. Every community and every government entity—Congress, state legislature, county commission—has a collection of issues that are available for discussion and disposition. All these issues can be categorized based on the extent to which an institution is prepared to make an ultimate decision to enact and implement or to reject particular policies. Furthest from enactment are issues and ideas contained in the systemic agenda, which contains any idea that could possibly be considered by participants in the policy process. Some ideas fail to reach this agenda because they are politically far beyond the pale in a particular society; government ownership of big businesses is, for example, generally off the systemic agenda in the United States because it is contrary to existing ideological commitments. Of course, recent experience with government assistance to General Motors, big banks, and major insurance companies shows how a major crisis can change the boundaries between what is and what is not an acceptable government undertaking. It is important to think of several levels of the agenda, as shown in Figure 6.1. The “largest” level of the agenda is the agenda universe, which contains all ideas

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

171

Figure 6.1â•… Levels of the Agenda

Agenda Universe

Groups seeking policy change seek to advance issues closer to the decision agenda

Systemic Agenda

Institutional Agenda

Decision Agenda Groups that oppose change seek to block issues from advancing on the agenda

that could possibly be brought up and discussed in a society or a political system. In a democracy, we can think of all the possible ideas as being quite unconstrained, although, even in democracies, the expression of some ideas is officially or unofficially constrained. In the United States, aggressively racist and sexist language is usually not tolerated in reasoned public discourse, even if it is protected, to some extent, by the Constitution. In Germany, it is illegal to write in praise of Nazism or to deny that the Holocaust happened, and Canada has laws prohibiting hate speech and expression that would probably conflict with the First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution. Ideas like the establishment of aggressively racist, fascist, or communist policies are so far out of bounds of politically appropriate discourse that they rarely are expressed beyond a fringe group of adherents. Indeed, policy ideas are sometimes labeled as “socialist” or “fascist” to place these ideas outside the realm of acceptable discussion. For example, health care reforms that would involve an increase in government activity have long been dismissed as “socialized medicine,” with the threat of “socialism” used to derail the idea. This often is an effective rhetorical technique because the very idea of socialism has such a negative connotation in the United States, but carries no such connotation in other countries. Many ideas in the agenda universe, however, are more or less

172 Chapter 6

institutional agenda. The list of issues that is being currently considered by a governmental institution, such as an agency, legislature, or court.

decision agenda. The agenda that contains items that are about to be acted upon by a governmental body, such as bills, court cases, or regulations.

“acceptable” in a political sense, and may come and go on the systemic agenda. President Obama’s health care reforms have, for example, advanced on the agenda, although not in the form first proposed because some ideas were politically acceptable and others were not. Cobb and Elder say that “the systemic agenda consists of all issues that are commonly perceived by members of the political community as meriting public attention and as involving matters within the legitimate jurisdiction of existing governmental authority.” The boundary between the systemic agenda and the agenda universe represents the limit of “legitimate jurisdiction of existing governmental authority.”5 That boundary can move in or out to accommodate more or fewer ideas over time. For example, ideas to establish programs to alleviate economic suffering have waxed and waned on the agenda when the national mood is more expansive toward the poor, as it was during the 1960s, or less compassionate, as during the 1990s. The boundary shifted in 2008 and 2009 as government intervened in the economy, as health care reform became more likely, and as the U.S. military’s own leadership began to suggest that allowing openly homosexual people to serve in the military would not harm the armed services. If a problem or idea is successfully elevated from the systemic agenda, it moves to the institutional agenda, which is “that list of items explicitly up for the active and serious consideration of authoritative decision makers.”6 The limited amount of time or resources available to any institution or society means that only a limited number of issues are likely to reach the institutional agenda.7 However, we have learned over the past several years that institutions can increase their “carrying capacity” and can address more issues simultaneously, either when there are many pressing issues, or when resources or technology are available to manage this increased load. Even with this increased carrying capacity, however, relatively few issues will reach the decision agenda, which contains items that are about to be acted upon by a governmental body. Bills, once they are introduced and heard in committee, are relatively low on the decision agenda until they are reported to the whole body for a vote. Notices of proposed rule making in the Federal Register are evidence of an issue or problem’s elevation to the decision agenda in the executive branch. Conflict may be greatest at this stage, because when a decision is reached at a particular level of government, it may trigger conflict that expands to another or higher level of government. Conflict continues and may expand; this expansion of conflict is often a key goal of many interest groups. The goal of most contending parties in the policy process is to move policies from the systemic agenda to the institutional agenda, or to prevent issues from reaching the institutional agenda. Figure 6.1 implies that, except for the agenda universe, the agenda, and each level within it, is finite, and no society or political system can address all possible alternatives to all possible problems that arise at any time. Even though we can

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

HEALTH C ARE

173

ARE HEALTH C

Is it possible for the presidency—or any institution—to have too much on its agenda at once? © Tribune Media Services, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Reprinted with permission.

Is it possible for the presidency—or any institution—to have too much on its agenda at once? Source: © Tribune Media Services, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Reprinted with permission.

use resources and technologies to increase the agenda carrying capacities of some institutions, ultimately there will still be substantial competition for what will inevitably be limited agenda space. It is also important to understand that, even when a problem is on the agenda, there may be a considerable controversy and competition over how to define the problem, including the causes and the policies that would most likely solve it. For example, after the 1999 Columbine High School shootings, the issue of school violence quickly rose to national prominence, to a much greater extent than it had after other incidents of school violence. So school violence was on the agenda: the real competition then became among depictions of school violence as a result of, among other things, lax parenting, easy access to guns, or the influence of popular culture (TV, movies, video games) on high school students. This competition over why the Columbine shootings happened and what could be done to prevent future school shootings was quite fierce, more so than the competition between school violence and the other issues vying for attention at the time.8

174 Chapter 6 The Idea of Political Power The ability of groups—acting singly or, more often, in coalition with other groups— to influence policy is not simply a function of who makes the most technically or rhetorically persuasive argument. We know intuitively that some groups are more powerful than others, in the sense that they are better able to influence the outcomes of policy debates. This argument suggests an elite model of policy making, in which relatively few people make the important decisions affecting public policy. But power is more than this. Social scientists have developed more sophisticated ways of thinking about the sources and uses of power. When we think of power, we may initially think about how people, governments, and powerful groups in society can compel people to do things, often against their will. In a classic article in the American Political Science Review, Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz argue that this sort of power—the coercion of one person by another—is one of two faces of power. The other face is the ability to keep a person from doing what he or she wants to do; instead of a coercive power, the second face is a blocking power. Of course power is exercised when A participates in the making of decisions that affect B. But power is also exercised when A devotes his energies to creating or reinforcing social and political values and institutional practices that limit the scope of the political process to public consideration of only those issues which are comparatively innocuous to A. To the extent that A succeeds in doing this, B is prevented, for all practical purposes, from bringing to the fore any issues that might in their resolution be seriously detrimental to A’s set of preferences.9

In the first face of power, “A participates in the making of decisions that affect B,” even if B does not like the decisions or their consequences. This is the classic sort of power that we see in authoritarian regimes, in which the government and its supporters impose policies on its citizens without their input or even approval. In the United States and other democracies, this sort of power exists because there are many groups that have very little power to influence decisions made on their behalf or even against their interests. Prisoners, for example, have little power to influence the conditions of their sentencing and incarceration because they are social “deviants” and therefore find it difficult to mobilize in defense of their very real but socially marginal interests.10 This is not to say that other people and groups do not speak for prisoners. There are several prison rights organizations in the nation, and concerns about the rate of incarceration of young black men and those who commit nonviolent drug offenses are growing. But the people who speak for people in prison are speaking for this socially deviant population that carries with it a severely negative image. Here’s another example of the first face of power that you may have experienced directly. Adults have a lot of power over children; children, as a matter of

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

law, are generally those under age eighteen, at least as far as voting is concerned. Most people are not allowed to legally drink until age twenty-one. States have varying ages at which they allow people to marry without parental consent. Why are there all these rules? Because children are not considered able to make adult decisions, because they are too young, have not yet developed key ways of logic and thinking, are potentially impulsive and impressionable, and because adults have an interest in ensuring the welfare and safety of children. Yet, remember your late teen years—did you feel that you needed this sort of “protection.” Many readers of this book may have been working and supporting themselves—and, in some cases, their families—before reaching adulthood. If we accept the paternalistic argument that children are not fully formed adults until about age eighteen or twenty-one, why are children in some states tried for serious crimes as adults and put in adult prisons? There are few good answers for this paradox, except to note that children and prisoners are, compared with other categories of people, relatively powerless. In the second face of power, A prevents B’s issues and interests from getting on the agenda or becoming policy, even when actor B really wants these issues raised. But even issues with some public support may have trouble trying to gain a place on the agenda. Environmentalism, for example, was, until the late 1960s and early 1970s, not a particularly powerful interest, and groups that promoted environmental protection at the time found that their issues rarely made the agenda because industrial interests worked to keep such matters off the agenda, and because the public did not perceive any significant problems. Not until crises such as the environmental damage done by the pesticide DDT, coupled with the writing of authors like Rachel Carson, in her book Silent Spring, was the issue elevated to the point where some attention was paid to it. Even then, one can argue that actor A, representing the business and industrial sector, bent but did not break on environmental issues and is still able to prevent B, the environmental movement, from advancing comprehensive (or “radical,” depending on your position) ideas that could have a profound effect on the environment. The blocking moves of the more powerful interests are not simply a function of A having superior resources to B, although this does play a substantial role. In essence, we should not think of the competition between actor A and actor B as a sporting event on a field, with even rules, between two teams, one vastly more powerful than the other. Rather, the teams’ power imbalance is as much a function of the nature and rules of the game as it is a function of the particular attributes of the groups or interests themselves. E.E. Schattschneider explains why this is the case: All forms of political organization have a bias in favor of the exploitation of some kinds of conflict and the suppression of others because organization is the mobilization of bias. Some issues are organized into politics while others are organized out.11

175

176 Chapter 6 In other words, some issues reach the agenda because the bias—that is, the tendencies of the political system—allows them to be raised. Other issues do rise on the agenda because they are not, according to the bias of the system, fit for political consideration. There is no political right in America for people to have decent housing, or health care, or jobs, because the bias of the American political system is heavily influenced by cultural values of self-reliance; this has led to the United States lagging behind other nations in declaring housing, education, employment, and health care as matters of right. This bias is neither static nor God-given, but is continually reinforced by interests that, for whatever reason, oppose broader access to these things as a matter of right. This is not to say that groups oppose jobs, or education, or health care—they just seek to avoid elevating these things to the same status as other rights, such as speech or voting, because elevating these issues on the agenda could likely yield policy ideas that run counter to the interests of those who believe in maintaining the status quo, or, at least, believe in slower or different policy change. Other scholars of political power have conceived of a third face of power, which differs substantially from the second face of power in that large groups of people who objectively have a claim that they are disadvantaged remain quiescent—that is, passive—and fail to attempt to exert their influence, however small, on policy making and politics. This is the story John Gaventa tells in his book Power and Powerlessness.12 Gaventa explains why a community of Appalachian coal miners remained under the repressive power of a British coal mining company and the local business and social elite. As Herbert G. Reid notes in his review of the book,13 Gaventa takes on the traditional idea that political participation in Appalachia is low because of the people’s own shortcomings, such as low educational attainment and poverty. Rather, in the third face of power, social relationships and political ideology are structured over the long term in such a way that A, the mining company, remains dominant and B, the miners, cannot conceive of a situation in which they can begin to participate in the decisions that directly affect their lives. When B does begin to “rebel” against the unfair system, the dominant interests can employ their ability to make nondecisions: in essence, they ignore the pressure for change because they can withstand such pressures. In the long run, people may stop fighting as they become and remain alienated from politics; quiescence is the result. This necessarily brief discussion of the idea of power is merely an overview of what is a very complex and important field of study in political science in general. It is important to us here because an understanding of power helps us understand how groups compete to gain access to the agenda and to deny access to groups and interests that would damage their interests. Groups and Power in Public Policy Social constructionist understandings of agenda setting complement E.E. Schattschneider’s theories of group mobilization and participation, which rest on his oft-cited

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

contention that issues are more likely to be elevated to agenda status if the scope of conflict is broadened. There are two key ways in which traditionally disadvantaged (losing) groups expand the scope of conflict. First, groups go public with a problem (as noted in chapter 5) by using symbols and images to induce greater media and public sympathy for their cause. For example, in early 2009 groups that opposed a major government bailout of the “Big Three” automakers (Ford ultimately didn’t seek federal aid) called attention to company executives use of private jets to fly to Washington—to testify before Congress—as evidence of wastefulness and company mismanagement. Tellingly, the next time the executives testified to Congress they drove, proving how both sides can use symbols to their benefit. Of course, one might make a business case for using the jets: they are quicker, more secure, possibly safer, and allow executives to use their time more efficiently. But such arguments often fail in the face of successful depictions of things like corporate jets as symbols of waste or privilege. In other words, the rhetoric prevails over the evidence or logic of an issue or problem. Second, groups that lose in the first stage of a political conflict can appeal to a higher or different decision-making level, such as when losing parties appeal to state and then federal institutions for an opportunity to be heard, hoping that in the process they will attract others to their cause. Conversely, dominant groups work to contain conflict to ensure that it does not spread out of control. The underlying theory of these tendencies dates to Madison’s defense, in Federalist 10, of the federal system as a mechanism to contain political conflict. Schattschneider’s theories of issue expansion explain how in-groups retain control over problem definition and the way such problems are suppressed by dominant actors in policy making. These actors form what Baumgartner and Jones call policy monopolies,14 which attempt to keep problems and underlying policy issues low on the agenda. Policy communities use agreed-upon symbols to construct their visions of problems, causation, and solutions. As long as these images and symbols are maintained throughout society, or remain largely invisible and unquestioned, agenda access for groups that do not share these images is likely to be difficult; change is less likely until the less powerful group’s construction of the problem becomes more prevalent. If alternative selection is key to the projection of political power, an important corollary is that powerful groups retain power by working to keep the public and out-groups unaware of underlying problems, alternative constructions of problems, or alternatives to their resolution.15 This thinking is a central tenet of elite theory. Many of the arguments made by elite theorists such as C. Wright Mills and E.E. Schattschneider, acknowledge the shortcomings of the pluralist approach. As Schattschneider famously put it, “The flaw in the pluralist heaven is that the heavenly chorus sings with a strong upperclass accent.”16 While an accent is not the same thing as perpetual upper-class or elite domination, it does suggest that the upper classes—the social, political, and economic elites—have power disproportionate to their numbers in society.

177 symbol. Something that stands for something else, usually for a broader concept. For example, “the flag” often means patriotism; a low or high unemployment rate symbolizes a strong or weak economy.

policy monopoly. A term coined by Frank Baumgartner and Bryan Jones to describe a fairly concentrated, closed system of the most important actors in a domain, who dominate or monopolize policy making; this is similar to the idea of the iron triangle.

178 Chapter 6 Overcoming the Power Deficit—Ways to Induce Policy Change

window of opportunity. Term used in Kingdon’s streams metaphor to describe the point in time at which policy change becomes more likely as the various “streams” are joined.

Baumgartner and Jones argue that when powerful groups lose their control of the agenda, less powerful groups can enter policy debates and gain attention for their issues. This greater attention to the problem area tends to increase negative public attitudes toward the status quo, which can then produce lasting institutional and agenda changes that break up policy monopolies. There are several ways in which groups can pursue strategies to gain attention for issues, thereby advancing them on the agenda. The first way for less advantaged interest groups to influence policy making relates to Kingdon’s streams metaphor for agenda change.17 “Windows of opportunity” for change open when two or more streams—the political, problem, or policy stream—are coupled. In the political stream, electoral change can lead to reform movements that give previously less powerful groups an opportunity to air their concerns. One example is the Great Society programs enacted under President Lyndon Johnson’s administration, which sought to attack poverty, poor health, racial discrimination, and urban decline, among other problems. This package of programs was made possible by an aggressively activist president and a large Democratic majority in the Congress, the result of the Democratic landslide of 1964. Similarly, a window of opportunity to roll back government regulation of business opened when President Ronald Reagan was elected in 1980. Second, changes in our perception of problems also influence the opening of a window of opportunity for policy change. In the 1930s people began to perceive unemployment and economic privation not simply as a failure of individual initiative, but as a collective economic problem that required governmental solutions under the rubric of the New Deal. Similar thinking is behind the government economic stimulus actions taken in 2008 and 2009. In the 1960s and 1970s, people began to perceive environmental problems, such as dirty air and water and the destruction of wildlife, not as the function of natural processes but as the result of negative human influences on the ecosystem. And, third, changes in the policy stream can influence the opening of a window of opportunity. In the 1960s poverty and racism were seen as problems, but were also coupled with new and more effective policies to solve these problems, such as the Civil Rights Acts, the Voting Rights Act, and the War on Poverty. Lest we think that all this change is in the liberal direction, it is worth noting that other periods of change, notably the Reagan administration, were also characterized by the joining of these streams. These include changes in the political stream (more conservative legislators, growing Republican strength in the South, the advent of the Christian Right as a political force), the problem stream (government regulation as cause, not the solution, of economic problems, American weakness in foreign affairs), and the policy stream (ideas for deregulation and smaller government,

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

179

increased military spending and readiness) that came together during the first two years of the Reagan administration. These factors help explain policies favoring increased military spending, an increase in attention to moral issues, and a decrease in spending on social programs. In each of these instances, it took group action to press for change. Groups worked to shine the spotlight on issues because, as Baumgartner and Jones argue, increased attention is usually negative attention to a problem, leading to calls for policy change to address the problems being highlighted.18 But the simple desire to mobilize is not enough. Groups sometimes need a little help to push issues on the agenda; this help can come from changes in indicators of a problem or focusing events that create rapid attention. And groups often need to join forces to create a more powerful movement than they could create if they acted as individuals. Indicators, Focusing Events, and Agenda Change John Kingdon discusses changes in indicators and focusing events as two ways in which groups and society learn of problems in the world. Changes in indicators are usually changes in statistics about a problem; if data collected by various agencies and interests indicate that things are getting worse, the issue will gain considerable attention.19 Examples include changes in unemployment rates, inflation rates, the gross domestic product, wage levels and their growth, pollution levels, crime, student achievement on standardized tests, birth and death rates, and the many other things that sophisticated societies count every year. These numbers by themselves do not have an influence over which issues gain greater attention and which fall by the wayside. Rather, the changes in indicators need to be interpreted and publicized by interest groups, government agencies, and policy entrepreneurs, who use these numbers to advance their preferred policy ideas. This is not to say that people willfully distort statistics; rather, it means that groups will often selectively use official statistics to suggest that problems exist, while ignoring other indicators that may suggest otherwise. The most familiar indicators, such as those reflecting the health of the economy, seem to need little interpretation by interest groups or policy entrepreneurs—when unemployment is up and wages lag behind inflation, the argument is less about whether there is an economic problem but, rather, what to do about it. But even then, the choice of which indicator to use is crucial and just about any indicator is subject to multiple interpretations. For example, in late 2009 the federal Bureau of Economic Analysis announced that the U.S. GDP had grown by 2.2 percent from the second quarter to the third quarter of 2009. The second quarter showed a change of –0.7 percent over the first quarter—that is, negative growth. So is the third quarter figure good news? Some may argue yes, it is: it’s growth, any growth is good, and under the circumstances—the collapse of the housing market, the fiscal crisis, the poor sales of cars—this is a good result. Others, however, may argue that 2.2 percent

indicator. Evidence of a problem, often based on statistics; for example, a decline in the Gross Domestic Product or an increase in the unemployment rate are indicators of economic problems. People can and do argue about what indicators mean.

180 Chapter 6

Focusing event. A sudden event that can generate attention to public problems or issues, particularly issues and problems that are actually or potentially harmful.

growth is anemic compared with the usual target of about 3.0 percent GDP growth sustained over a year, and compares poorly with good years over the last decade. In another example, the number of new unemployment payment claims in the United States at the end of December 2009 was less than had been expected. Is this good news? There are still people applying for unemployment benefits, regardless of the number. How many claims are too many? How much or how little growth and job creation can the nation reasonably expect? These are important interpretative questions, and one reason Deborah Stone argues that we can treat numbers as symbols that stand for ideas that require explanation and interpretation. Focusing events are somewhat different from indicators. Focusing events are sudden, relatively rare events that spark intense media and public attention because of their sheer magnitude, or sometimes because of the harm they reveal. Focusing events thus attract attention to issues that may have been relatively dormant. Examples of focusing events include airplane accidents, industrial accidents such as factory fires or oil spills, large protest rallies or marches, scandals in government, and events that are inherently unusual or that may be usual but have some feature that makes them noteworthy. Peaceful protest marches, for example, are often little noted or remembered, but the outbreak of violence or the threat of violence makes them more compelling. Earthquakes are also fairly common, but really big earthquakes can make buildings and highways collapse and kill people, at which point the event becomes very important. Terrorist attacks worldwide are very common and are noted but do not dominate the agenda. But the September 11 attacks gained particular attention because of where they happened (New York and Washington), how they happened (flying airplanes into buildings), and the results (the World Trade Center destroyed, thousands killed). Focusing events can lead groups, government leaders, policy entrepreneurs, the news media, or members of the public to pay attention to new problems or pay greater attention to existing but dormant (in terms of their standing on the agenda) problems, and potentially, can lead to a search for solutions in the wake of perceived policy failure. The fact that focusing events occur with little or no warning makes such events important mobilization opportunities for groups that find their issues hard to advance on the agenda. Problems characterized by statistical indicators will gradually wax and wane on the agenda, and their movement on or off the agenda may be promoted or resisted by constant group competition. Sudden events, on the other hand, are associated with “spikes” of intense interest and agenda activity. Interest groups—often relatively powerful groups that seek to keep issues off the agenda—may find it difficult to keep major events off the news and institutional agendas. Groups that seek to advance an issue on the agenda can take advantage of such events to attract greater attention to the problem. In many cases, the public and the most informed members of the policy community learn of a potential focusing event virtually simultaneously. These events can very rapidly alter mass and elite consciousness of a social problem. I say “vir-

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

181

tually” because the most active members of a policy community may learn of an event some hours before the general public. A classic example is the grounding of the Exxon Valdez in Alaska in March 1989. This ship ran aground just after midnight in Alaska, or just after 4:00 a.m. on the East Coast. Most people were asleep when the spill occurred, but learned of it through the morning radio or TV news or late morning newspapers. Certain members of the policy community, however, such as key employees of the Exxon Corporation, the local Coast Guard contingent, fishers in south central Alaska, and others with a direct interest in the event, learned of the spill within minutes or hours. Still, the span of time that passed between local and national knowledge—or between elite and mass knowledge—of the spill was far too short for Exxon and its allies to contain news of the spill, which, therefore, suddenly became a very prominent issue on the agenda.20 The oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico in 2010 shows similar dynamics, with the sudden explosion drilling rig signaling a problem of some sort. However, unlike the Exxon Valdez spill, the magnitude of the so-called “BP oil spill” was not well known for days after the explosion, but soon the spill became a major national news story and policy problem. While the immediate news converage of the spill started fading even before the well was successfully capped, legislative attention had only just begun to increase in mid-2010.

Case Study: The September 11 Attacks as a Focusing Event While it may be obvious that the September 11 attacks were major events, it is important to understand how large an influence they had on the media and congressional agendas with regard to terrorism. This case study considers the nature of agenda expansion in the mass media, using The New York Times as a measure of the media agenda. I use the Times because it is considered one of the best newspapers in the nation and because it is so large and influential. It is sometimes called the “newspaper of record” for the United States. It is read by most key decision makers in government and business, and influences the agenda of other news outlets. Figure 6.2 shows the relative coverage of the concept of “terrorism” in the Times by year from 1990 through 2002. The stories are categorized by the “desk” from which they originated— national, metro, or foreign—which helps us determine whether the Times treated the story as a metropolitan, national, or world news issue or problem. The index is set so that the mean number of stories per desk per year from 1990 to 2000 equals 100. This allows comparisons across desks that would be more difficult to see if we just counted up the number of stories generated every year. The data were gathered from the LexisNexis database. There were at least three actual or suspected terrorist incidents between 1990 and 2001 that may have been terrorist-related: the first bombing of the World Trade Center, the 1995 Oklahoma City federal building bombing, and the unsolved Olympic Park bombing in Atlanta during the 1996 Olympics. But none of these events triggered the extent of coverage by the Times that the September 11 events did. Clearly, the September 11 attacks “brought home” (continued)

182 Chapter 6

Case Study (continued) the issue of terrorism. Terrorism became a domestic problem rather than primarily an overseas issue. Foreign news on terrorism also increased due to the extensive coverage of foreign reaction to the September 11 attacks and the escalation of violence in the Middle East. While Figure 6.2 shows the dramatic effect of the event on the national news agenda, it also shows that news coverage of the September 11 events followed a typical trend. In general, the news media aggressively covers an issue for a short time and then coverage fades as the event recedes into the past and as political institutions decide whether or not to act in substantive or symbolic ways. However, one cannot say that news coverage of terrorism has returned to pre-September 11 levels. Through 2002, there was more coverage of terrorism across all the Times’ various desks than in any year other than 2001. This trend continued in 2003. While I do not show the data here, preliminary analysis of more recent data shows that this trend has continued, with September 11 being the most extensively covered terrorist attack in United States, and perhaps world, history. Like the news media, Congress has paid a great deal of attention to the attacks, but the expansion of the agenda was not as great as the media’s attention to the issue. This reveals important differences between the news media and Congress. Figure 6.3 shows a significant increase in news coverage of terrorism in the two weeks after September 11, followed by a substantial Figure 6.2â•… News Coverage of Terrorism, by New York Times “Desk,” 1990–2002 1800 1600 Foreign

. 01>

'U

·Metropolitan

National

1400 1200

.E 1000 800 600 400 200 0 1990

1991

1992

1993

1994

1995

1996

1997

1998

1999

2000

2001

2002

Index: Mean number of stories per year, 1990–2000 = 100

(continued)

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

183

Case Study (continued) drop off in coverage after that first two-week period, although not to relatively low pre-2001 figures. News coverage of terrorism as a national issue remained high, but it never returned to the levels reached in the first two weeks after September 11. Congress, on the other hand, saw its terrorism agenda expand continuously in the six weeks following September 11, and the prominence of the issue actually peaked on the agenda in March 2002, about six months after the event. Congress, as a decisionmaking body, cannot simply take note of an issue and then, in the manner of the news media, tackle the “next big thing.” Congress is a deliberative body by design and moves slower than the media, but in many ways it is more purposive in its actions. This case study illustrates how a large, shocking event can rapidly change the nature of the agenda, but it also shows that, in some ways, Congress is more attentive to issues over a longer period than the news media, which is more interested in the episodic nature of big events. Are there other events in American history that you think had such a profound influence on the agenda in so little time? Are there events of similar magnitude that did not influence the agenda? Why not? How would you gather data and track the issue in a way similar to what you see here? Figure 6.3â•… Media and Congressional Attention to Terrorism, 1990–2002 1600

Index

1400 1200 1000 800

National Desk

All New York Times

600 Congressional Iestimony

400 200 0

1990 1991 1992 1993 1994 1995 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002

Index: Mean number of stories or items of testimony per year, 1990–2000 = 100

184 Chapter 6 Group Coalescence and Strategies for Change A major shortcoming of elite theory, and of power theories in general, is that they assume that some—or most—interests simply accept their fate, providing elites little competition for the agenda and for shaping the issues. Related to this is the assumption that the elite is somehow a monolith, single-mindedly marching toward the same goal of upper-class domination of political life. Neither of these assumptions is true. Less advantaged interests in the United States, and indeed the world, often fight against power, often against long odds and at considerable personal risk to the individuals involved. In the United States and most Western democracies, most policy disputes can be entered without the threat or reality of state suppression; this is in marked contrast with countries like North Korea and Burma, which have created totalitarian regimes that suppress any political expression. Powerful economic interests often conflict with each other, such as when producers of raw materials like oil and steel want to raise prices while producers of goods that use these inputs, such as automobile makers, seek to keep raw material costs low. Within industries, vicious battles over markets and public policy can occur, as in the ongoing legal and economic battles between Microsoft and its rivals, or between different types of Internet service providers (ISPs: e.g., cable, DSL, satellite, wireless), and major airlines and discount carriers. These are not merely arguments over business matters—they often go to the heart of key public policy problems. For example, Google now allows people to make free or very inexpensive phone calls via its Google Voice service. It therefore competes with telephone companies. Does this mean that Google is now a telephone company? An ISP? Or something else? It’s not an ISP, because Google does not provide Internet access directly, except for a few experimental installations. It’s not really a phone company, but it provides phone services. These are real conundrums that will have real implications for phone companies, for companies like Google and Skype, and for regulators who must figure out how, whether, and to what extent existing regulations cover these new systems and whether new regulation is required. The phone companies would like Google to be regulated as a phone company, to create what interests often call a “level playing field.” Google argues that it is not a phone company. The controversy, as of this writing, is not settled.21 We must also keep in mind that many movements that seek policy change are led by people whose socioeconomic condition and background are not vastly different from those of their political opponents. For example, labor union leaders are often well compensated and live near powerful people, not their union members. In this section, we will review how less advantaged interests, led by bright and persistent leaders, can and sometimes do overcome some of their power deficits. The first thing to recognize about pro-change groups is that they, like more powerful interests, will often coalesce into advocacy coalitions. An advocacy coalition, as noted in chapter 5, is a coalition of groups that come together based on a shared

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

set of beliefs about a particular issue or problem. These are not necessarily the core beliefs of these groups; rather, Paul Sabatier, the originator of the advocacy coalition framework, argues that groups will coalesce based on their more peripheral beliefs, provided that the coalition will advance their goals in the debate at hand. Changes in indicators and focusing events may bring the issue to greater mass and policy maker attention and at the same time may induce groups to form coalitions to promote their common interests. These coalitions can attract greater attention from policy makers and create greater access to the policy-making process, thereby balancing the power of elites. But where should a group begin to seek to influence policy once it has formed a coalition and mobilized its allies and members? Baumgartner and Jones address this question in their discussion of “venue shopping” in the policy process.22 Venue shopping, a term we first encountered in chapter 5, describes the efforts groups undertake to gain a hearing for their ideas and grievances against existing policy.23 By venue we mean a level of government or institution in which the group is likely to gain the most favorable hearing. We can think of venues in institutional terms—legislative, executive, or judicial—or in vertical terms—federal, state, or local government. The news media are also a venue, and even within a branch of government, there are multiple venues. Groups can seek to testify before congressional committees and subcommittees where the chair is known to be sympathetic to their position or at least open-minded enough to hear their case. This strategy requires the cooperation of the leadership of the committee or subcommittee, and unsympathetic leaders will often block efforts to include some interests on witness lists. But the many and largely autonomous committees and subcommittees in Congress allow groups to venue shop within Congress itself, thereby increasing the likelihood that an issue can be heard. After a major focusing event, it is particularly hard to exclude aggrieved parties from a congressional hearing. The numerous survivors, and their supporters, who testified before Congress after the widespread failures to properly respond to Hurricane Katrina made the problem vivid to committee members and contributed, in part, to the large amounts of money appropriated to aid in storm recovery. However, the actual pace of recovery and the speed with which aid funds are being spent are both rather slow, and reflect another aspect of event-driven agenda setting—the speed at which the issues raised by the event recede from the agenda, as public, media, and policy makers’ attention wanes, as the appropriation of funds or the enactment of new laws or rules appears to “solve” the problem, and as new problems emerge and crowd the older issues off the agenda. Those older issues may not entirely disappear, but they do fade from attention. It is worth noting, however, that as issues like the response to Hurricane Katrina recede from media and public attention, they can remain important in the congressional committees that are charged with dealing with the problem. Groups that cannot gain a hearing in the legislative branch can appeal to executive

185

186 Chapter 6

NIMBY Acronym for “Not in My Backyard,” the usual local response to the location of unpopular public or private developments ranging from landfills to homeless shelters to wind farms. Planners have coined the term LULU (locally undesirable land use) to describe such facilities.

branch officials. Environmentalists who cannot get a hearing in the House Natural Resources Committee may turn to the Environmental Protection Agency, the Fish and Wildlife Service, the various agencies that compose the Department of the Interior, and other agencies that may be more sympathetic and might be able to use existing legal and regulatory means to advance environmental goals. While an appeal to these agencies may raise some conflict with the legislative branch, this tactic can at least open doors for participation by otherwise excluded groups, particularly if the executive branch sees these groups as allies against policy proposals coming from the legislative branch. Groups often engage in litigation as a way to get their issues on the agenda, particularly when other access points are closed to the group. A classic example of the litigation strategy involves the civil rights movement, in which black lawyers sued and desegregated law schools, graduate schools, universities, and, ultimately, all schools for blacks. While Gerald Rosenberg, in The Hollow Hope, argues that this litigation strategy was not entirely successful, requiring legislation to fully implement policy change, others argue that the legal strategy served as a catalyst for the civil rights movement and that landmark cases such as Brown v. Board of Education sparked a movement that resulted in more effective demands for change. Had the civil rights proponents not taken their fight to court, this argument holds, it is less likely that Congress and the president would have taken their claims seriously.24 Groups may seek to change policies at the local or state level before taking an issue to the federal government, because the issue may be easier to advance at the local level or because a grassroots group may find it can fight on an equal footing with a more powerful group. This often happens in NIMBY (not in my backyard) cases, such as decisions on where to put group homes, cell phone towers, expanded shopping centers, power plants, and the like. And, of course, groups sometimes must address issues at the state and local level because these governments have the constitutional responsibility for many functions not undertaken by the federal government, such as education or, as became clear in the same-sex marriage issue, the laws governing marriage. In the latter example, it’s clear that gay rights groups have adopted a state-by-state or even more local strategy because it does not make sense to seek change at the federal level as the federal government has extremely limited power over marital and family law. On the other hand, groups may expand conflict to a broader level (i.e., from the local to the state level or from the state to the federal level) when they lose at the local level. E.E. Schattschneider calls this “expanding the scope of conflict.” This strategy sometimes works because expanding the scope of conflict often engages the attention of other actors who may step in on the side of the less powerful group. The civil rights movement was in many ways contained in local actions in the South until images of violent crackdowns on civil rights protesters became more prominent on the national news, thereby expanding the issue to a broader and somewhat more sympathetic public. A more recent example of expanding the scope of conflict is

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

found in the health care debate, in which the Obama administration sought to mobilize mass publics and to negotiate the cooperation of insurance companies, major industries like the auto industry who have huge health care benefit expenses, and pharmaceutical companies to support a consensus on health reform. This effort was not entirely successful, but recognized the need to broaden the scope of conflict to get as many people involved as possible. Groups and interests often seek media coverage as a way of expanding the scope of conflict. Media activities can range from holding news conferences to mobilizing thousands of people in protest rallies. These activities are more newsworthy if they address an issue of current concern, such as the gay rights tea party protests held in Washington, DC, in the fall of 2009. Indeed, we don’t often see mass mobilization and protest over issues like inadequate earthquake engineering or impending asteroid collisions with the earth, because the number of people directly involved in addressing these problems is small, they have other, much more fruitful avenues for political expression, and because these are broadly viewed as highly technical matters in which public input is neither offered or sought.25 Finally, gaining a place on the agenda often relies on coalescing with other groups. Many of the great social movements of our time came about when less powerful interests coalesced. The civil rights movement involved a coalition, at various times, with anti-war protestors, labor unions, women’s groups, antipoverty workers, and other groups who shared an interest in racial equality. By coalescing in this way, the voices of all these interests were multiplied. Indeed, the proliferation of interest groups since the 1950s has resulted in greater opportunities for coalition building and has created far greater resources for countervailing power. Before concluding this discussion, we must recognize that elevating issues on the agenda in hopes of gaining policy change is not always resisted by political elites. Cobb and Elder argue that, when political elites seek change, they also try to mobilize publics to generate mass support for an issue, which supports elite efforts to move issues further up the agenda.26 This type of effort is known as internal mobilization. Such efforts can constitute either attempts to broaden the influence of existing policy monopolies or attempts by some political elites (such as the president and his staff) to circumvent the policy monopoly established by interest groups, the bureaucracy, and subcommittees (the classic iron triangle model). The president or other key political actors may be able to enhance the focusing power of an event by visiting a disaster or accident scene, thereby giving the event even greater symbolic weight. The Social Construction of Problems Humans and democratic governments are problem solvers. Many of the social and technological advances made throughout human history were solutions to claimed problems: Vaccination is a solution to pandemic disease; the electrical light is a superior solution

187

188 Chapter 6 public goods. Goods that, once provided for one user, are provided for everyone, such as national defense or police services; economists say that public goods are indivisible and nonexclusive, because they cannot be divided into parts for individuals to consume and because one person’s use of the good does not deny others the use of the good. social construction. The process by which issues and problems are defined in society.

to gas lights or torches for illumination; and the wheel, the railroad, the telephone, the airplane, and the Internet are solutions to the problems posed by distance. At the same time, many social problems remain that people believe should be “solved,” or at least made better. Poverty, illiteracy, racism, immorality, disease, disaster, crime, and any number of other ills will lead people and groups to press for solutions. Often, these social problems require that governmental action be taken because services required to alleviate public problems that are not or cannot be addressed by private actors are public goods that can primarily be provided by government actors. While in the popular mind, and often in reality, economic and social conservatives stand for limited government activity, these conservatives also believe there are public goods, such as regulation of securities markets, road building, national defense, and public safety, that are most properly provided by government. It is probably best to define the problem before worrying about whether public or private actors must resolve it. Deciding whether a problem really is a problem at all is an important part of political and policy debate. Problems can be defined and depicted in many different ways, depending on the goals of the proponent of the particular depiction of a problem and the nature of the problem and the political debate. The process of defining problems and selling a broad population on the definition is called social construction. It refers to the ways in which society and the various contending interests within it structure and tell stories about how problems occur. A group that can create and promote the most effective depiction of an issue has an advantage in the battle over what, if anything, will be done about a problem. In Policy Paradox, Deborah Stone considers how people present the background of a problem by using symbols, numbers, and stories about causes. Rather than summarize or paraphrase her argument, I will highlight issues raised by Stone and other scholars. One of the things that problems create is uncertainty, inequity, and other burdens that some people believe are undesirable. However, many policies that reduce uncertainty for one group or one person create a burden or greater uncertainty or “annoyance” for others. Creating social welfare programs, regulating TV content, or regulating guns creates annoyance and uncertainty for, among others, civil libertarians and gun rights advocates (who are not necessarily one and the same). For some, a “problem” is really just a fact about which nothing can realistically be done; that is, the problem, as unpleasant as it is, is really a condition. People and groups will work very hard to prove that a problem is a problem and that a solution can be found. Merely stating a problem is not enough: one must persuade others that the problem is real or that the problem being cited is the real problem. The definition of a problem is an important part of the persuasive process and effects the choice of solutions. Joseph Gusfield argues that one can look at the drunken driving problem in a number of ways.27 Most of us tend to look at the drunken driving problem as one of individual responsibility, which presumes that stiffer penalties to punish the responsible party are needed to address the problem. But what if we

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

looked at the problem as one of inadequate transportation? If the United States had better systems of mass transit, it is likely that fewer people would need to drink and drive; they could drink and ride a bus or a train. Or what if the problem is deeply embedded in our culture, one that prizes recreation, relaxation, and even glamour and links these benefits to relatively easy access to alcohol by adults? The social construction of a problem is linked to the existing social, political, and ideological structures at the time. Americans still value individual initiative and responsibility, and therefore make drinking and driving at least as much a matter of personal responsibility as of social responsibility. The same values of self-reliance and individual initiative are behind many of our public policies, dealing with free enterprise, welfare, and other economic policies. These values differentiate our culture from other nations’ cultures, where the community or the state takes a more important role. In those countries, problems are likely to be constructed differently, and different policies are the result. Conditions and Problems Conditions can develop over time into problems, because citizens, doctors, scientists, engineers, and so on are constantly trying to take things that we think of as conditions and turn them into problems that we can realistically try to solve. Until Dr. Jonas Salk and other scientists developed the polio vaccine, millions of children and their parents lived in fear of this crippling disease. Without the polio vaccine, this disease seemed to be a condition about which little could be done. Many communities would quarantine people with polio, and parents often voluntarily kept their kids away from swimming pools, school, camps, and playgrounds to help them avoid contracting polio. These voluntary and involuntary quarantines, and the treatments for those with polio, carried very high social costs, and were not very effective. But polio became a much more tractable problem once the polio vaccine became available. Governments—in particular, public health officials—responded by encouraging or directly providing polio vaccine to children. Today, the polio rate is vastly lower than it was just sixty years ago, and one may argue that the polio problem has been solved, except in the very poor countries where polio remains endemic. Today, the discussion of polio— and of various forms of the flu, chicken pox, measles, mumps, and other similar diseases—revolves more around the safest method of vaccine administration (oral or via injection) than around the disease itself; in other words, the solution became a problem in its own right, although not as big a problem as the disease.28 As technological progress continues, the original problem becomes forgotten, and when the solution to that problem is somehow disrupted that disruption becomes the problem. Electricity was harnessed in lighting, heating and cooling, and the powering of machinery to overcome the problems posed by darkness, extreme temperatures, or the limits of human muscle power. We have now become a society so dependent on electricity that a major power outage becomes the problem. For everyone who relies on the Internet and cell phones, service interruptions are a major inconvenience.

189

190 Chapter 6 Internet outage effects e-mail, social networking, instant messaging, and a range of other services, all of which were designed to solve some problem (social isolation, expensive communication, or business inefficiencies, to name a few). When problems such as power or Internet outages arise, people often demand government actions to solve them to ensure the lights stay on or that Internet access is not interrupted. An interruption in electricity, the Internet, or cable TV, is a problem that most believe should never happen at all! And lest we believe a power outage is a minor inconvenience with few political repercussions, consider the power outage that struck Auckland, New Zealand, in February 1998.29 The outage lasted for over ten days, closing businesses, forcing evacuations of apartments due to water and sewer failures, and ending up costing New Zealanders millions of dollars. The cause of the outage was the failure of overtaxed power cables; but regardless of the cause, people do not expect or lightly tolerate the loss of something taken for granted for so long. Indeed, the blackouts that struck eight eastern states and two Canadian provinces in August 2003, or the one that struck Brazil and Paraguay in 2009, lasted hours, not days, for most locations, but led to significant social and economic disruption as elevators failed, subways ceased to work, computer systems shut down, and all the modern features on which urban societies rely were unavailable. Most problems are more subtle than sudden blackouts, so people have to be persuaded that something needs to be done; still more persuasion may be necessary to induce a belief that government needs to do something about a problem. However, there are often instances, such as in the Gulf of Mexico oil spill in 2010, where the public demands that government do even more than it is empowered to do under existing law. Symbols Because policy making is usually a process of political argument and persuasion, groups and individuals promoting particular policy options will work to gain whatever rhetorical advantage they can in these debates. Because a hallmark of successful policy advocacy is the ability to tell a good story, groups will use time-tested rhetorical devices, such as symbols, to advance their arguments. A symbol is “anything that stands for something else. Its meaning depends on how people interpret it, use it, or respond to it.”30 Politics is full of symbols, some perceived as good, others as bad, and still others as controversial. Some symbols are fairly obvious; the American flag, for example, is generally respected and even revered in the United States. However, the American flag is often used outside of the United States to symbolize the alleged abuses and wrongdoings of our nation—thus, the same flag means very different things in different contexts. In most parts of the world, flying a flag bearing the Nazi swastika is considered somewhere between poor taste and an actual violation of the law, because of the extremely troubling connotations of the swastika and the Nazi regime that used it. Before the Nazis took power, the swastika was a relatively obscure religious symbol, and its use as such remains tolerated.

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

Deborah Stone outlines four types of stories that use rhetorical symbols. First, she discusses narrative stories, which are stories told about how things happen, good or bad. They are usually highly simplified and offer the hope that complex problems can be solved with relatively easy solutions. Such stories are staples of the political circuit, where candidates tell stories about wasteful bureaucrats or evil businessmen or lazy welfare cheats to rouse the electorate to elect the candidate, who will impose a straightforward solution to these problems. Stories are told about how things are getting worse, or declining, to use Stone’s term, or how things were getting better until something bad happened to stop progress, or how “change-is-only-an-illusion” (p. 142). For example, stories may be told on the campaign trail or the floor of the legislature in which positive economic indicators are acknowledged but are said not to reflect the “real” problems that real people are having. Stories of helplessness and control portray situations in which an issue or problem previously could not be resolved but a solution now exists. These stories are closely related to the condition versus problem tension. Helplessness-and-control stories are often cast in us-versus-them terms, such as when interest groups are called special interest groups because the term “special” denotes something different about these groups, and perhaps something outside the mainstream. Conspiracy theories are also a major part of these stories, as people seek to make sense of the world around them. Conspiracies include claims of hidden agendas and sinister goals. Recent conspiracy theories in the United States that gained small fringe attention include the belief that Israeli government agencies attacked the World Trade Center to incite anger toward Muslims, or theories that the collapse of buildings 1, 2, and 7 were “controlled” demolitions designed to hide secrets. Anti-vaccine proponents argue that mandatory vaccination exists primarily to enrich the makers of vaccines, or that the risks of such vaccines have been covered up. Proponents of health care reform are said to be conspiring to “ration” health care, or to grow government because the proponents just want bigger government for its own sake. There are many good reasons to question the assumptions behind health care reform and other policy changes, but conspiracy theories usually collapse under the weight of their own illogic and lack of evidence. But they can persuade enough people to create political problems for proponents of policies based on sound science and evidence. Conspiracy theories are related to the stories and anecdotes people use to describe problems. Thus, as Stone notes, the idea of the cheating “welfare queen” took hold in the 1980s, even though such people represented a small and atypical portion of the welfare population. Related to such stories are “horror stories” of government regulation run amok. Such stories are usually distorted: Stone cites the example of how those opposed to industry regulation claimed that the Occupational Safety and Health Administration (OSHA) “abolished the tooth fairy” by requiring that dentists discard any baby teeth they pulled; the actual regulation merely required that appropriate steps be taken to protect health workers from any diseases that may be transmitted in handling the teeth. The media stirred up a small controversy by

191

192 Chapter 6 reporting that OSHA was advising companies with home workers that they were responsible for the health and safety of telecommuters. The media, elected officials, and business interests raised the specter of OSHA invading every telecommuter’s privacy to inspect their workspace; this horror story, coupled with long-standing industry dislike for OSHA and the prior propagation of horror stories, made this a very compelling and disturbing prospect. The truth of the matter was more subtle: OSHA had simply sent a letter to an employer that interpreted its existing rules on workplace safety, stating that the employer does bear some responsibility for home workers’ safety in home offices. Regardless of this important distinction, OSHA backed away from the letter in the face of media ridicule and political pressure.31 You probably have heard or even told these and other horror stories about policies. Television news shows such as 60 Minutes and 20/20 have made an industry out of telling these horror stories, often failing to place them in their proper context. In the same way, interest groups often neglect to place stories in the proper perspective as their main goal is to advance their policy preferences. Interest groups will therefore tell stories that stretch the truth to the breaking point, to gain attention from other members of the policy community and to mobilize support or opposition for a particular policy direction. Causal Stories causal story. A narrative depiction of the causes of a public problem; such stories often contain normative statements about both the problem itself and why a particular solution will resolve the things that are said to have caused the problem.

An important part of storytelling in public policy is the telling of causal stories.32 These stories attempt to explain what caused a problem or an outcome. They are important in public policy making because the depiction of the cause of a problem strongly suggests a solution to the problem. Causal stories are similar to the causal theories of problems that are described in chapter 8; however, in this chapter, we are more concerned with use of these stories in rhetoric and debate than in decision making. Stone divides causal stories into four categories: mechanical causes, accidental causes, intentional causes, and inadvertent causes (see Table 6.1).

aggregate data. Data based on the adding up, or aggregation, of smaller data points. For example, data on the average family income in the census is based on smaller data elements gathered then aggregated for analysis.

Debates and controversies often involve the use of numerical information to make their points. Such numbers include the number of people living in poverty, the average amount of taxes people pay to the government, the number of people killed or hurt by various hazards, and so on. The use of numbers in policy debates is very attractive because numbers appear to have accuracy that anecdotal evidence lacks, particularly when the numbers provide a description of aggregate data—that is, when the data reflect a broader phenomenon. Such aggregate data include the unemployment rate, average school test scores, median family income, and the like. Indeed, I have used this sort of data to outline the policy environment in chapter 2. The use of numbers is particularly interesting, as Stone points out, because deciding to count a phenomenon is a policy decision itself. We collect data about

Numbers as Indicators of Problems

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

193

Table 6.1 Types of Causal Theories with Examples Consequences Actions

Intended

Unintended

Unguided

mechanical cause conspiracies that work

accidental cause conspiracies that work

intervening agents brainwashed people machines that perform as designed, but cause harm

nature weather earthquakes machines that run amok

intentional cause conspiracies that work

inadvertent cause conspiracies that work

oppression

intervening conditions unforeseen side effects avoidable ignorance carelessness omission

Purposeful

programs that work as intended, â•… but cause harm

Source: From Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making by Deborah A. Stone. Copyright © 2002 by Deborah A. Stone. Used by permission of W.W. Norton & Company, Inc.

phenomena because we want to know something more about them. We count unemployment, crime, health, education, and other statistics. Once we begin counting, there is considerable pressure to continue counting to see how problems are behaving: we want indicators of good things to go up (the GDP, wages, educational achievement) and bad things to go down (diseases and death, crime, welfare rolls). For each of these things, there is political pressure to make the problem better. But numbers are not entirely objective measures of a phenomenon and are subject to interpretation. Numbers used in the portrayal of a problem are not always accurate. Statistics on the GDP, unemployment, inflation, test scores, for example, have often been challenged. The census, which the Constitution requires be taken every ten years, is notorious for undercounting immigrants and minorities, placing cities at a disadvantage in the allocation of federal funds dispersed on the basis of population. On the other hand, statistical methods that might correct this undercount could introduce more error in the census than they would alleviate, or could simply stir up political opposition. Like so many other things we measure, a distinguished panel of statisticians found, ultimately, that the solution to the undercounting problem is less a technical problem than it is a social or political matter.33 This is as true today as it was in 2000, for the same reasons: the allocation of a state’s seats in the House of Representatives is directly related to census data; with the House capped at 435 members, every state that gains a seat does so at the expense of the state losing a seat. Educational tests, such as the Scholastic Assessment Test (SAT) and other state tests have become popular ways of assessing educational performance and are often used to assess whether students are allowed to advance in school or to graduate. Some

194 Chapter 6 people have challenged these tests, claiming that they are biased on the basis of race, class, and gender in favor of white males from well-to-do families and that the scores do not accurately reflect the academic potential of everyone who takes the tests.34 Perhaps the most notoriously questionable statistics come from the Uniform Crime Reports (UCR) collected by the U.S. Department of Justice. The UCR compiles reports of crime from police departments nationwide; but the reports include only those crimes about which the police have information. They do not include unreported crimes and some police departments may have an incentive to inflate or underreport crimes. In some cases, when police place special emphasis on particular crimes such as domestic violence, the apparent rate of crime goes up because more crime is reported and known to the police. People may report more of these crimes because they are encouraged to do so by the policy and legal authorities.35 Second, even if some measures are reasonably accurate, an important question remains: Is the indicator in question the best measure of a phenomenon or of progress toward a goal? For example, the GDP is a measure of all the goods and services produced in the nation. The financial press concentrates a great deal of attention on this figure and when it grows from quarter to quarter or year to year, this is said to be a good thing. Yet the GDP may not be the best measure of the nation’s overall wellbeing. Does the GDP, for example, deduct from the value of some goods the pollution and subsequent environmental damage they cause? Indeed, if there is an environmental disaster or nuclear power plant accident, the money spent to clean the plant, evacuate people living near by, and treat anyone injured in the accident is included in the GDP. Other things that perhaps we would not want to spend money on, such as lawyers’ fees, cancer treatment, and fixing car wrecks, are all counted in the GDP. Thus, economic growth may not equate with the good life, but rather reflects all the things that we spend money on, including the things we might not really want to buy.36 Many of you have taken a statistics class or two. Many of us approach such classes with trepidation. But the example of the use (or abuse) of statistics I am about to illustrate shows how useful some background in statistics can be for your own political self-defense. Being able to find and explain statistical fallacies is a very important skill in our number-driven world. The choice of the statistic being reported has a big influence on how one is supposed to interpret the underlying idea being conveyed. Take as an example family income. In a 2003 report by the U.S. Census Bureau, the average family income in the United States was $182,381. As a measure of what statisticians call “central tendency,” this figure is very misleading; because as we learned in chapter 2, so much wealth is held by relatively few people in the United States, their income skews the average higher than the two-earner median household income of about $80,000. The median is the number at the exact middle of a range of numbers; for every family below the median there’s one above this figure. One can imagine that if you wanted to argue that American families are doing well, one would report the average; a different result would follow from reporting the median.

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

For example, let us take King County, Washington, the county in which Microsoft and Amazon.com are headquartered. There are at least three major billionaires in the Seattle area: Microsoft founder Bill Gates, who is worth about $45 billion; Paul Allen, a cofounder of Microsoft, worth about $10 billion; and Jeff Bezos, founder of Amazon.com, also worth about $10 billion. These people have much higher family incomes (generally from sales of stock, dividends, investments, and the like) than the “typical” family, so their income distorts the average family income figure in King County much more than it would distort the median family income figure.37 In statistical terms, these families are called outliers—they fall outside the range of the bulk of the data points. This example shows why we sometimes talk in terms of median figures, such as median family income or median home prices: because if we used the mean or average of these figures, the few outliers, such as the really expensive houses or the really well-paid people, would distort the story we are trying to tell with the numbers. But if you were, say, a civic booster, you might use (or abuse) the average value as a way to make an affirmative argument about the overall prosperity of the people in King County, even if this prosperity isn’t equally shared. Finally, there are two things you should know about numbers and their depiction in policy debates. First, advocates for policy positions will choose numbers that put their arguments in the best light. This means that the use of numbers is likely to be significantly skewed or distorted for rhetorical advantage. This distortion is most often seen in charts and graphs, which citizens and policy makers must use with extreme caution. Many charts and graphs are deliberately or accidentally misleading, and it is an unfortunate by-product of modern printing and publishing technology that allows newspapers and magazines (USA Today was once notorious for this) as well as anyone with a copy of Microsoft Excel to print remarkably misleading and distorted statistical graphs that range from difficult to read to purposefully misleading. Edward Tufte’s work on the design of information graphics discusses these problems and will arm you with considerable defenses against what he calls “chartjunk.”38 Second, there is a difference between a number (that is, a data point) and the interpretation of that data. There is an old saying in information management that there is a big difference between data and information: data are just the raw numbers, while information is what we get when we interpret the numbers—and as you know, that information is very much subject to the interpretation of those with a stake in the meaning of that information. Conclusion The study of agenda setting is a particularly fruitful way to begin to understand how groups, power, and the agenda interact to set the boundaries of political policy debate. To me, the relationship between ideas, the social construction of problems

195 outlier. In statistics, a case (that is, a data point) that falls so far below or above the main cluster of data points that it significantly influences the mean value of all the data. A very large outlier will cause the mean to greatly exceed the median or middle value; a very small outlier will cause the mean to fall far below the median value.

196 Chapter 6 and solutions, the nature of agenda, the groups that are involved in agenda setting and in propagating ideas, and the very idea of power itself is not just a fascinating topic for research. I consider it the pivot point of the policy process. Groups that successfully amass resources, or that find winning rhetorical strategies, often gain power. Indeed, a winning symbol or causal story can, as with Mothers Against Drunk Driving, strike a chord that resonates throughout the political system and the policy process, creating pressure for policy change. We therefore know that agenda setting, like all other stages of the policy process, does not occur in a vacuum. The likelihood that an issue will rise on the agenda is a function of the issue itself, the actors that are involved, institutional relationships, and, often, random social and political factors that can be explained but cannot be replicated or predicted. But we do know enough about groups, power, and agenda setting to know that, as Robertson and Judd describe (summarized in chapter 3), policy restraint is still an important feature of American policy making. The struggle to shine attention on issues and on particular ways of portraying those issues is a continuing process. Those who understand the ebbs and flows of ideas and power will be better prepared to understand why policies change when they do, and how to participate in campaigns for change.

Key Terms Agenda Agenda setting Agenda universe Aggregate data Causal story Condition Decision agenda

Elite theory Enactment Focusing Event Indicator Institutional agenda NIMBY Outlier

Pluralism Policy monopoly Public goods Social construction Symbol Systemic agenda Window of opportunity

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. How does an elite theory of U.S. power differ from a pluralist theory? In your opinion, which theory better explains power in the United States? What evidence might you use to support your claim? 2. Why are issues likely to be elevated on the agenda if the scope of conflict is widened? 3. How do you think a policy monopoly would try to keep problems and underlying policy issues high or low on the agenda? 4. What are the two major ways in which groups and society as a whole learn about problems? Which of these two ways will lead to the most rapid increase of attention to a problem?

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

5. Why do interest groups engage in venue shopping? What are some of the different kinds of venues available to interest groups and other advocates? 6. Imagine you belong to an interest group that advocates for the things you care about. In which venues would your group seek to gain attention? Why did you choose your preferred venues? 7. How do a condition and a problem differ? Give some examples of each. Can you think of conditions that later became problems as the technologies or knowledge to deal with these conditions became available? Are there any conditions that will never be solvable problems? Can you think of examples of things that we thought were problems and were treated as such, but that later came to be defined as conditions? 8. Think about a problem that you care deeply about. Write, in a paragraph or two, a causal story about what causes the problem that you selected. Do you think your causal story will be accepted broadly in our society? Why or why not? 9. Assume that the county government plans to build a highly polluting incinerator next to your property. What actions could you take to remedy the situation? 10. Choose several issues. Explain how each issue may be socially constructed depending on what political ideology a person has. 11. This project may take longer than a semester, but you will find the results very interesting. Join an interest group that deals with issues you care about: for example, if you are an environmentalist, join the Sierra Club. If you are a shooter or hunter, join the National Rifle Association. When you join, alter your name slightly for just the one group so that you can track the mail you get when these groups share their membership lists with other groups. For example, I go by Thomas A. Birkland but would sign up as Thomas B. Birkland to see how my name is shared. And now that many groups send e-mail instead of “snail mail,” you might want to set up a separate e-mail account with Google (Gmail), Yahoo!, or Hotmail and use these identities to join the groups you are interested in. In several months, you may start to get mail and e-mail from other organizations or groups, some of which you may never have heard of (if you are using e-mail, check your spam filter—much of it will be junk, but you may be getting solicitations from other groups based on your interest in an issue). â•… What kind of groups contacted you? Are they sympathetic to the cause you originally joined? You will likely find that your name is widely shared among other groups with similar interests. From this mail you may be able to map the contours of the advocacy coalition to which you belong. You can also replicate this by signing up with political groups using an e-mail account. Set up an account with Hotmail or Yahoo! (or use a separate screen name in AOL). Sign up for one or two sites and see whether you receive other political or interest group e-mail (or spam, depending on your tastes).

197

198 Chapter 6 12. An interesting way to track the importance of an issue is to follow its relative position on the agenda over time. This has been made much easier with the Policy Agendas Project at the Center for American Politics and Policy at the University of Washington. At its Web site (http://www.policyagendas. org) you can find a number of datasets on congressional hearings, The New York Times coverage of issues, executive orders, and the like. These are all coded using a uniform subject code that allows you to compare issues across these different venues. You can download the data and use it in a spreadsheet program such as Microsoft Excel to track the agenda status of various issues. But you can also use the “Data Tools” on the project’s site to do live analyses of the project’s data without downloading the rather large datasets. â•… Pick an issue you are interested in and track it over time. When does Congress, or The New York Times pay more attention to an issue? For example, when I compared coverage of energy in The New York Times to congressional hearing activity on energy, I found that attention was relatively low until attention suddenly peaked in 1975 and again in 1979. Why do you suppose it suddenly jumped like this? Try looking at other issues and see whether they show steady activity or sudden surges or drops in attention. Additional Reading Nearly all discussions of agenda setting in American politics start with E.E. Schattschneider’s The Semisovereign People (Hinsdale, IL: Dryden Press, 1975), a short, wonderfully clear book that, among other things, describes why agenda setting is so important in American politics. In the policy process, Roger Cobb and Charles Elder, in Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building, 2d ed. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1983), provide one of the earliest and most complete treatments of how agendas are built by groups and interests. Roger Cobb and Marc Howard Ross continue this work in their Cultural Strategies of Agenda Denial: Avoidance, Attack, and Redefinition (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997), in which they describe how groups and interests work to deny other interests access to the agenda. John Kingdon’s Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies, 2d ed. (New York: Harper Collins, 1995) has been particularly influential in understanding how agendas work in the policy process; so much so, in fact, that the first edition was awarded the 1994 Aaron Wildavsky award for its continued influence on the study of public policy. Astute readers of this chapter will note that my ideas on focusing events, contained in my book After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy, and Focusing Events (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1997) have their genesis in Kingdon’s treatment of the subject. Such denial of agenda access is part and parcel of political power, and the oftcited work on this topic is Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz’s “The Two Faces of

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

199

Power,” American Political Science Review 56 (1962): 947–52, in which we learn that power involves getting people to do something they don’t want to do, as well as preventing them from doing what they want to do. To this formulation John Gaventa, in Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1980), adds a subtle third face of power. Gaventa describes how social relations in Appalachian coal-mining communities were structured so that people at the bottom of the economic and social ladder could not conceive of ways to escape their lot. Clearly, my thinking about how public problems are socially constructed is directly informed by Deborah Stone’s text Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making, (New York: Norton, 2002). Stone directly confronts the rationalist approach to policy analysis—she calls this the “rationality project”—by comparing rationalist notions of society (often derived from economics) as a market with a more politically and sociologically useful idea of society as the “polis.” She illustrates why there are so many paradoxes in politics and policy making that cannot be “rationally” explained by “decisionist” models of policy analysis. Stone’s book has the added benefit of being fascinating reading, although many readers (myself included) find that the book is so rich that it takes more than one reading to glean all its insights. However, it is important to ensure that you understand some of the standard policy analysis texts and techniques that contrast with Stone’s approach to policy studies. These include Edith Stokey and Richard Zeckhauser, A Primer for Policy Analysis (New York: W.W. Norton, 1978), and David L.Weimer and Aidan R. Vining, Policy Analysis : Concepts and Practice, 4th ed. (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall, 2005). Notes 1. E.E. Schattschneider, The Semisovereign People (Hinsdale, IL: Dryden Press, [1960] 1975), 66. 2. James Hilgartner and Charles Bosk, “The Rise and Fall of Social Problems: A Public Arenas Model,” American Journal of Sociology 94, no. 1 (1988): 53–78. 3. Roger W. Cobb and Marc Howard Ross, Cultural Strategies of Agenda Denial: Avoidance, Attack, and Redefinition (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997). 4. Richard Hofstadter, The Paranoid Style in American Politics, and Other Essays (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979). 5. Roger W. Cobb and Charles D. Elder, Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building, 2d ed. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1983), 85. 6. Cobb and Elder, Participation in American Politics, 85–86. 7. Hilgartner and Bosk, “Rise and Fall”; Laurence J. O’Toole, “The Public Administrator’s Role in Setting the Policy Agenda,” in Handbook of Public Administration, ed. James L. Perry (San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 1989). 8. See Regina G. Lawrence and Thomas A. Birkland, “Guns, Hollywood, and Criminal Justice: Defining the School Shootings Problem Across Public Arenas,” Social Science Quarterly 85, no. 5 (2004): 1193–1207; Thomas A. Birkland and Regina G. Lawrence, “Media Framing and Policy Change after Columbine,” American Behavioral Scientist 52, no. 10 (2009):1405–25. 9. Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz, “The Two Faces of Power,” American Political Science Review 56 (1962) : 952. 10. Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram, “The Social Construction of Target Populations: Implications for Politics and Policy,” American Political Science Review 87, no. 2 (1992): 334–348.

200 Chapter 6 11. Schattschneider, Semisovereign People, 71, emphasis in original. 12. John Gaventa, Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1980). 13. Herbert G. Reid, “Review of John Gaventa, Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley,” Journal of Politics 43, no. 4 (November 1981): 1270–73. 14. Frank Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones, Agendas and Instability in American Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993). 15. Gaventa, Power and Powerlessness. 16. Schattschneider, Semisovereign People, 35. 17. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies, 2d ed. (New York: Harper Collins, 1995). 18. Baumgartner and Jones, Agendas and Instability. 19. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives. 20. Those interested in learning more about focusing events might consult my After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy, and Focusing Events (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1997). 21. Ryan Singel, “Google Poised to Become Your Phone Company,” November 13, 2009, wired.com via CNN, http://www.cnn.com/2009/TECH/11/13/google.phone.service/index.html (accessed on February 15, 2009). 22. Baumgartner and Jones, Agendas and Instability, 31. 23. See, for example, Sarah B. Pralle, “Venue Shopping, Political Strategy, and Policy Change: The Internationalization of Canadian Forest Advocacy,” Journal of Public Policy 23, no. 3 (2003): 233–260; Sarah B, Pralle, Branching Out, Digging In: Environmental Advocacy and Agenda Setting (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006). 24. On the idea that the courts are constrained in their ability to promote social change, see Randall Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991). For a critique of this position see Michael W. McCann, “Reform Litigation on Trial,” Law and Social Inquiry 17, no. 4 (1992): 715–743. 25. Peter J. May, “Reconsidering Policy Design: Policies and Publics,” Journal of Public Policy 11, no. 2 (1990): 187–206. 26. Cobb and Elder, Participation in American Politics. 27. Joseph Gusfield, The Culture of Public Problems: Drinking-Driving and the Symbolic Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981). 28. There is a major controversy surrounding the safety of vaccines; this controversy was rekindled in 2009 with the introduction of vaccines for the so-called H1N1 virus or “swine” flu. Some celebrities made claims based on faulty science that the administration of these vaccines increases the risk of autism. There is no scientific evidence of such an effect. See Alan Lifson, “Vaccines Have Made World a Different, Better Place,” Minneapolis Star-Tribune, February 5, 2000, 15A; “Agency Recommends Shot Replace Oral Polio Vaccine,” Indianapolis Star, January 21, 2000, A9. 29. Ray Lilley, “Mayor Warns Blackout Could Continue for 10 Days in New Zealand,” Associated Press, February 23, 1998, via Lexis-Nexis, http://www.lexis-nexis.com. 30. Deborah A. Stone, Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making. Rev. ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 2002), 137; Murray Edelman; The Symbolic Uses of Politics, 2nd ed. (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1985); Political Language: Words That Succeed and Policies That Fail (New York: Academic Press, 1977); and Constructing the Political Spectacle (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988). 31. See, for example, “OSHA Won’t Hold Companies Responsible for Safety of Home-Offices,” CNN Interactive, January 27, 2000, http://cnn.com/2000/US/01/27/homeworker.safety.ap; “Red-Faced OSHA Drops Rules for Home Workers,” Human Events, January 14, 2000, 4. 32. Stone covers this topic in chapter 8 of Policy Paradox; she also explores the topic in “Causal Stories and the Formation of Policy Agendas,” Political Science Quarterly 104, no. 2 (1989): 281–300. 33. Harvey M. Choldin, “How Sampling Will Help Defeat the Undercount,” Society 34, no. 3 (1997): 27–30; David A. Freedman and Kenneth W. Wachter, “Census Adjustment: Statistical Promise or Illusion,” Society 39, no. 1 (2001): 26–33; Margaret E. Martin et al., “Report of the ASA Technical Panel on the Census Undercount,” American Statistician 38, no. 4 (1984): 252–56. 34. An interest group called Fairtest has developed around this issue. See its Web site at http://www.fairtest.org. Other references of interest include David K. Leonard and Jiming Jiang, “Gender Bias and the College Predictions of the SATs: A Cry of Despair,” Research in Higher Education 40, no. 4 (1999): 375–407; Jeffrey R. Young, “Researchers Charge Racial Bias on the SAT,” Chronicle of Higher Education (October 10, 2003): A34–A35.

Agenda Setting, Power,

and

Interest Groups

201

35. See Gary Newman, “Bluffs Leads State in Violent Crime: The City’s Police Chief Says the FBI Report Makes the Situation Appear Worse Than It Is,” Omaha World-Herald, December 8, 1999, 19; on the general point, see Adella Jones (Communications Director, St. Louis Metropolitan Police Department), letter to the editor in St. Louis Post-Dispatch, June 14, 1999, D14, and Carol Napolitano, “Why We Didn’t Use FBI Numbers,” Omaha World-Herald, November 8, 1999, 2. 36. On the environmentalist take on the GDP as a measure of well-being, see Jonathan Rowe and Mark Anielski, The Genuine Progress Indicator: 1998 Update—Executive Summary (San Francisco: Redefining Progress, 1999). 37. Another example of this problem of statistical outliers, also from King County, is described in Roberto Sanchez, “Medina? For Homes It Can’t Be Finer,” Seattle Times, February 20, 2000 (Sunday night final edition), B1. Medina is the city in which Bill Gates lives. 38. See, for example, Edward Tufte, The Visual Display of Quantitative Information (Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1983); Envisioning Information (Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1990); and Visual Explanations (Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1997). He extends his critiques to presentation software in The Cognitive Style of Powerpoint (Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 2003).

7

CHAPTER

Policies and Policy Types

Chapter at a Glance What Is a “Policy”? Codifying and Publicizing Policies Case Study: An Example of the Regulatory Process Policy Types Distributive, Regulatory, and Redistributive Policies Distributive Policies Regulatory Policies Redistributive Policies James Q. Wilson: Concentrated and Diffuse Costs and Benefits Other Policy Typologies Substantive and Procedural Policies Material and Symbolic Policies Public versus Private Goods Case Study: The Challenges of Policy Typologies: When Is a â•… Symbolic Policy Not Merely Symbolic? Liberal and Conservative Policies Conclusion Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

Public policy is one of the key outputs of the policy process. This chapter begins with a broad definition of the term policy and then describes how policies can be categorized by type. The effort to place policies into types has consumed a considerable amount of time and effort among political scientists; and for good reason. Political scientists seek to create policy typologies because we suspect, based on intuition and experience, that some policies will involve more groups in their formation and enactment, will see more conflict before and after enactment, and will be more visible than other types of policies. Sound policy typologies help to predict what sort of politics will accompany particular kinds of policies; that is, for a given proposal about what government should do or not do, we should be

202

Policies

and

Policy Types

203

able to predict who will participate and what the nature of conflict will be. There is no final word on how best to categorize policies, so when reading this chapter it is important not to pigeonhole or force fit policies into different categories; instead, a key goal is to consider the strengths and weaknesses of each typology in telling us something meaningful about the way policy is made and what its results likely will be. What Is a “Policy”? As discussed in chapter 1, public policy is, in general, what the government, acting on our behalf, chooses to do or not to do. This suggests a working definition of policy that may seem obvious, but that is a bit more complex than the simplest definition. I define a policy as a statement by government of what it intends to do or not to do, such as a law, regulation, ruling, decision, or order, or a combination of these. For example, a law that says that those caught driving while intoxicated will go to jail for up to one year is a statement of governmental policy to punish drunk drivers. The USA Patriot Act, passed in the aftermath of the September 11 attacks, is a statement of government policy relating to national security and terrorism. Judicial decisions are also statements of policy: the Supreme Court’s decision in Brown v. Board of Education is a statement of national policy that governments cannot constitutionally require schools to be segregated on the basis of race or ethnicity. Because we also define public policy as what government chooses not to do, the lack of a definitive statement of policy may be evidence of an implicit policy. For example, the government has never declared a right to education, or health care, or a living wage; therefore, we can assume that the implicit policy is that one cannot get these benefits as a matter of right. Some other nations do express these services and benefits as rights, which often makes for interesting and important comparisons between the United States and other countries. Codifying and Publicizing Policies Since we usually think of individual policies as statements of the things the government does intend to do, it is useful to consider how these policies are written down and codified. After all, if policies were not made public in some way, it would be very difficult to discern the government’s intent in enacting the policy, and it would be difficult for those affected by the policy—the people we call the targets of policies—to understand what government expects of them. Table 7.1 summarizes how policies are codified, listed in order from the most to the least visible and tangible types of policies. The table starts with the most visible sort of policy change—constitutional change—and ends with the very subtle changes in individual cognition and behavior that sometimes accompany changes in the behavior of organizations that make or implement policy. Clearly, constitutional

policy. A statement by government of what it intends to do or not to do, such as a law, regulation, ruling, decision, or order, or a combination of these. The lack of such statements may also be an implicit statement of policy.

204 Chapter 7 Table 7.1 Levels of Policy Codification Level of policy

Where codified

Visibility of codification

Constitutional

In the federal or state constitutions

Highly visible at the federal level: the Constitution has been edited very few times. Some state constitutions are more easily amended for minor changes.

Statutory

United States Code, Statutes at Large

Highly visible through codification in statute law, publication in Statutes at Large.

Regulatory

Federal Register, Code of Federal Regulations

Moderately visible through the Code of Federal Regulations and the Federal Register.

Formal record of standard operating procedures

Operating Procedures Manuals

Low visibility because S.O.P.s are often only internally published.

Patterned behavior by “street level bureaucrats”

Not formally codified; evidence of a “policy” may be found in some agency records

Low visibility because these are behavioral changes with variations among actors.

Subtle changes in cognition, in emphasis on problems, etc.

Not formally codified. Often revealed by the behavior of street-level bureaucrats themselves

Very low visbility. Not codified, and changes in perceptions and emphases may be subtle.

Federal Register. The daily journal of federal rule making and other administrative activity. Many notices of federal administrative activity are published in the Federal Register, the most important of which are codified in the Code of Federal Regulations.

provisions are the most visible and most clearly codified statements of national policy. The Constitution is the basic law of the land, and changing the Constitution is no trivial matter. To amend the Constitution, two-thirds each of the House and Senate must vote for the amendment, and then three-quarters of the state legislatures (thirty-eight states) must ratify the proposed amendment.1 With this many states involved, the process is very visible. The codification of statute law and regulation is less visible than constitutional change, although the visibility of the law and regulatory processes varies with the nature of the policy being considered. We often tend to think of policies as laws, such as the Civil Rights Act of 1964, the Voting Rights Act of 1965, the No Child Left Behind Act, or the USA Patriot Act. These are, of course, among the most visible laws on the books. Other laws deal with highly technical aspects that are of greatest interest only to the most expert stakeholders. But statute laws are readily available for anyone’s perusal in the United States Code, which codifies all federal laws in a way that makes laws easier to find and understand, and in the lists of Public Laws that are enacted every Congress.2 Once a law is enacted, it must be implemented, a topic taken up in chapter 8. The regulatory process is central to the implementation of broad public policy. Congress generally delegates highly technical matters to regulatory agencies, which issue regulations that govern various activities and industries. These regulations are published in the Federal Register and codified in the Code of Federal Regulations.

Policies

and

Policy Types

It is common to hear opponents of certain regulations—or of government regulation as a whole—claim that there is “too much” regulation, and that the volume of pages published in the Federal Register (which runs into the tens of thousands) is evidence of this.3 It is more accurate to note that the Federal Register is really a compendium of most of the executive branch’s policy making and policy implementation activity. The Federal Register contains such diverse features as “Airworthiness Directives,” which are regulations about the maintenance and safety of airplanes, announcements of disaster areas (published in the Federal Register by the Federal Emergency Management Agency, or FEMA), and of course, actual and proposed regulations. Most regulations start as a “Notice of Proposed Rulemaking,” the publication of which alerts everyone to the possibility of a regulation being adopted. This allows those with an interest in the matter at hand to weigh in on policy making. Many of the pages of the Federal Register are devoted to summarizing the comments made during the public comment period. Thus, to the extent that the Federal Register is a measure of the transparency of government, one can argue that the publication of fewer pages of the Federal Register might reflect less transparency, which would have substantive meaning for public policy. In any case, while the Federal Register hardly qualifies as compelling reading for most people, the people whose business it is to participate in policy making read the Federal Register, follow the regulatory process very closely, and comment when invited to do so to advance their policy goals or to protect their interests. The next set of policy statements encompasses policies that are often difficult for laypeople—and, in some cases, even experts—to track and understand. First, every agency has a manual of internal rules that encompasses what agencies call standard operating procedures. For example, my university has a manual of rules that govern things as disparate as computer use policies, tuition and fee payment schedules, and conflicts of interest between researchers and research funders. An agency I once worked for had a manual of standard procedures that encompassed ethics rules for dealing with contractors, rules for the use of agency vehicles, and rules that prohibited sleeping on the job! (This was a state transportation department, so for many jobs, sleeping on the job could be dangerous.) All these rules govern how agencies do their work, and have implications for policy outputs. State and local agencies that manage public services like Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF) or the Supplemental Nutrition Assistance Program (SNAP) (popularly known as food stamps) also have rules that govern how these services are delivered, and those rules can have real implications for needy people. Finally, we have two types of policies that are often part of what we refer to as tacit knowledge of an organization’s members, and that are not codified. The patterns of behavior by street-level bureaucrats are an important aspect of public policy. Street-level bureaucrats are the people at the front lines of public service delivery—police officers, teachers, social service caseworkers, fire fighters, clerks at

205 Code of Federal Regulations (CFR). The compilation (in print and online) of all federal regulations. These regulations are first published in the Federal Register and public comment is taken into account before the regulations are codified in the CFR.

street-level bureaucrat. A term coined by Michael Lipsky to describe the actors at the low end of the implementation chain, such as teachers, police officers, and social workers, who implement policies at the point of contact with the policy’s target population.

206 Chapter 7

Case Study: An Example of the Regulatory Process In May 1996, ValuJet flight 592, a McDonnell Douglas DC-9 airliner, crashed into the Everglades soon after takeoff on a flight from Miami to Atlanta, killing everyone on board. An investigation by the National Transportation Safety Board (NTSB) determined that the plane crashed because hazardous materials were illegally included in the cargo hold of the plane with some used tires that were being sent back to Atlanta. The hazardous materials were improperly capped oxygen canisters used to provide emergency oxygen when the plane loses cabin pressure. A fire broke out among the tires, which would likely have smoldered given the usual lack of oxygen in that cargo hold. But, in this case, the fire was fed by the oxygen from the illegally loaded canisters, thereby allowing a fire to breach the confines of the cargo hold, causing a series of mechanical and electrical failures that led to the plane’s crash in the swamp. Should there be a policy to make planes less likely to catch fire in flight? One could argue that there would not have been a crash had the oxygen canisters not been aboard. Indeed, the contractor that loaded the canisters on the plane, SabreTech, was later prosecuted and the firm ended up going out of business. This still left the problem of a fire in the cargo hold regardless of its cause or whether the improper loading of flammable materials could have been prevented. The NTSB strongly recommended that the Federal Aviation Administration (FAA) change its regulations to make the type of cargo hold in which the fire broke out (a so-called Class D cargo hold) less prone to fire, which would make planes much less prone to a loss of control caused by a fire. The FAA agreed, and on June 13, 1997, published proposed changes to regulations governing the construction and operation of airliners that, in essence, reclassified and strengthened the fire safety requirements for certain types of cargo holds in airplanes. This Notice of Proposed Rulemaking (NPRM) is lengthy, about two and a half pages contain a description of the proposed policy. The remainder of the notice contains a background of the problem, the history of other fatal or dangerous fires on airliners, and a rationale for the proposed regulation. The NPRM also noted an important change in the attitudes of the major airlines. While they may have opposed major changes to the rules on cargo hold fire safety before the ValuJet crash, their industry group, the Air Transport Association noted that their members had already begun voluntary measures to make the cargo holds less prone to fire. The FAA deemed these actions a good start, but still insufficient in the face of the hazard of a crash. Perhaps most importantly, the FAA noted in this NPRM that it was seeking comment about a wide range of matters in the rulemaking, ranging from what sort of chemicals are best suited to putting out fires in cargo holds to whether and to what extent the new rules would have an impact on commercial aviation in Alaska. The seeking of comments is consistent with the Administrative Procedures Act’s requirements that rules are first (continued)

Policies

and

Policy Types

Case Study (continued) announced as proposals, and that these comments are considered before they are finalized. The usual ninety-day comment period (until September 11, 1997) was included. The FAA did indeed receive many comments, most of which were supportive of the new rule changes. Comments were received from aviation regulators in the United Kingdom and Canada, from the Air Transport Association, and from at least one firm who wanted to make the FAA aware of its fire suppression technology. In all, over 100 comments were received. The final rule was published on February 16, 1998. The FAA adopted the proposed rule and explained in the Federal Register its reactions to the comments and its logic for proceeding with the new rule. The new rules were codified in the Code of Federal Regulations, in Title 14 parts 25 and 121: Part 25 is the section of title 14 that regulates the construction of airplanes; Part 121 is a very extensive set of rules that regulate the operation of major airlines, like the kinds most all of us fly on.6 None of these actions were taken capriciously by the FAA. First, the FAA must have legal authority under federal law to regulate airlines and airplanes. This authority is provided in Federal law—the Federal Aviation Act of 1958, as amended, codified in the United States Code in Title 49—in these rules, the FAA cites 49 U.S.C. 106 as its authority to regulate commercial aviation. Furthermore, other federal laws require that any regulation take into account the costs and benefits of a policy, its impacts on federalism, and on small business. In this case, there are few small businesses that run airlines, and since the regulation of aviation falls squarely within the power of the federal government, there are no federalism implications. Why doesn’t Congress just draft and apply the rules itself? First, Congress delegates the drafting of rules to others because laws are not intended to specify every element of their implementation. Lawmaking would be difficult, if not impossible, if we asked Congress to specify every aspect of the implementation of every program or policy. Even if Congress wanted to draft the detailed rules for every aspect of legislation, the public would demand opportunities for comment and input into the rule-making process, such that Congress would find itself bogged down simply in the process of making rules, particularly in highly technical areas such as aviation. The regulatory agencies have considerably greater expertise than does Congress and considerably greater resources for designing rules and managing the process. Furthermore, the bureaucracy is assumed by many as being more “neutral” than the more “political” Congress and, since matters of technical expertise are assumed to fall outside of “politics,” Congress can draw the broad parameters of policy and leave the bureaucracy to fill in the gaps, using neutral expertise rather than political judgment. Of course, it is extremely unlikely that the bureaucracy is truly neutral, and Congress does not always give the bureaucracy free rein. For example, Congress was very clear about standards used to achieve cleaner air and water in the Clean Air and Clean Water acts.

207

208 Chapter 7 the post office and the motor vehicles office—whose decisions and behaviors effect program management. For example, after the September 11 attacks, the security screeners at airports became much more thorough in their searches of passengers, to prevent passengers from bringing on box cutters and other small weapons that were used in the hijackings. This was not immediately accompanied by a change in any formal policy, and, in any case, the screeners would have changed their behavior to avoid being the ones responsible for such a tragedy. Sometimes, the behavior of street-level bureaucrats can blunt the effect of a formally stated policy. In 1961 the U.S. Supreme Court held, in Mapp v. Ohio,4 that evidence seized illegally from suspects by the police could not be admitted in court as evidence of the guilt of the suspect. The idea was that excluding the evidence from court would deter the police from breaking this important rule on searches and seizures, as governed by the Fourth Amendment. This decision substantially changed the way that police officers testified as to how they came by important evidence, such as drugs found on drug dealers in New York City. Often police find drugs when the alleged drug dealer drops the drugs while running from the police (attested to in so-called dropsy testimony) or the police find the drugs while frisking the alleged dealer. Researchers reported in the Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems that, in the six months before Mapp, two-thirds of all evidence was obtained by searches of the suspect’s clothing. After Mapp, between 80 and 90 percent of all contraband was discovered because suspects had dropped the contraband. Thus, dropsy testimony became prevalent in various courts. . . . It is both unusual and unlikely that suspects would suddenly drop incriminating evidence for police to discover, in New York or any other jurisdiction.5

This is but one example of how street-level bureaucrats can alter their behavior to conform with how they believe policy should work “on the streets,” rather than as envisioned by some very distant policy maker. Teachers, social workers, air traffic controllers, and other street-level bureaucrats often make their own decisions about how to make and implement policies to achieve what they believe are important and legitimate policy goals, such as ensuring aviation safety or ridding the streets of drugs. The example of police testimony that drug dealers were dropping drugs at a much higher rate than before the Mapp decision suggests potential wrongdoing on the part of the police. But it is important to understand the police officers’ behavior in the face of conflicting goals: Is their primary goal to arrest drug dealers and to collect evidence for their prosecution? Or is it to ensure that suspects’ constitutional rights are preserved? Is there any conflict here? In the end, the police officers—like many other bureaucrats—may weigh the two goals and value one over the other. This sort of discretion is exercised in many different settings every day. The final category of policy and of change is much more subtle than the purposive behavior of street-level bureaucrats. This level involves subtle changes in

Policies

and

Policy Types

behavior of policy makers and of bureaucrats—street level and others—triggered by a new set of beliefs or new information. For example, airport screeners may be targeting people who look “Middle Eastern” as higher risks for terrorism, even as official policy is that no such “profiling” is part of public policy. The screeners’ behaviors may not be well understood even by the screeners themselves—the biases or informational shortcuts they use to identify those deserving more screening are subtle, and changes in their behavior—the sum of which yields a particular policy direction—may be discernible only after careful analysis of trend data. There is, of course, a very blurry line between purposive behavior—like dropsy evidence—and subtle changes in behavior. But we should be, at this point, less concerned with the difference between these two types of behavior than with the idea that the last two rows of Table 7.1 describe public policies of a far more subtle and less official nature than statutory or regulatory law. Policy Types An important element of the public policy process is an understanding of how various interests are organized and how various interests react to different kinds of policies. We consider these two issues in one section because the two concepts are inextricably linked—one cannot profitably discuss policy types without understanding their apparent influence on politics, including group organization, mobilization, and reaction. In the previous section, we discussed a typology of policies based solely on the extent to which the policies themselves are highly visible and are easily found in constitutions, statutes, and regulations, or are more subtlety contained in standard operating procedures and behaviors. This is a useful way to think about how policies are organized, but it does not constitute a theory of policy types that would allow us to describe or predict the nature of participation and conflict in policy making. Efforts to develop policy typologies sought to do just this: explain policy outcomes by explaining and predicting key aspects of the politics underlying these policies. Like many elements of policy studies, creating typologies of public policies started with a great deal of enthusiasm but was quickly bogged down by some major problems. We will discuss these problems, but we wish to stress that the value of at least thinking about policy typologies is still great; such typologies are useful in understanding how and why some policies are made the way they are, and why some groups do better than others in policy debates and actual enactment. Again, as I stress throughout the book, the ideas generated by these theories are often more important than the internal consistency of the theories themselves. The earliest policy typologies generally separated policy into topical categories: education policy, health policy, or transportation policy, for example. This system was useful for sorting different kinds of policy domains, but it did not help us draw general conclusions about the politics that underlie these policies. The particular problem is

209

210 Chapter 7 that, by failing to tell us something more generalizable across the policy domains, these simple typologies made it difficult to learn from other types of policies and their underlying politics. By lumping together all policy types in one category, we were no closer to understanding similarities and differences among and between policies in all domains and were therefore no closer to a useful science of public policy. Distributive, Regulatory, and Redistributive Policies typology. A system for categorizing things based on similar characteristics, and for differentiating things with different characteristics. A policy typology is a way of organizing a broad range of public policies into a system of policy types to aid in understanding and analysis.

One of the most persistent efforts among policy scholars is the work intended to develop categories of public policies, or what we call typologies. The modern era of developing policy typologies began in 1964 when Theodore Lowi laid out the classic policy types often taught in undergraduate and many graduate courses.7 In the simplest terms, Lowi divides policies into three categories: distributive, redistributive, and regulatory. Later, Ripley and Franklin updated the typologies by dividing regulatory policy into two categories: protective regulatory and competitive regulatory8 (Table 7.2). Why do we create policy typologies? Because, as Lowi argued, knowing what kind of policy we are dealing with allows the policy designer to predict the sorts of policy conflict that would precede the policy’s enactment, and what sort of conflict might arise after the policy is adopted and implemented. This would therefore be a useful predictive tool that would take policy studies beyond the realm of mere description, as it spent much of its formative years, and would provide useful problem-solving information to policy designers, in the spirit of Lasswell’s call for a scientifically rigorous policy science. As we will see, this sort of theorizing had some potential, but also some significant shortcomings. Distributive Policies

distributive policy. In Lowi’s policy typology, this is a type of policy that takes a resource from a broad group of people and gives the resource to a narrower group; an example is so-called pork barrel policies that send money to particular districts for local programs.

Distributive policies involve the granting of some sort of benefit to a particular interest group or other well-defined, relatively small group of beneficiaries. Examples of distributive policy include farm subsidies and federal spending on local infrastructure projects such as dams, flood control systems, aviation, highways, and schools. These benefits are usually distributed in the process of developing authorization and appropriations bills as part of the budgeting process.9 Distributive policy allows for a considerable amount of negotiation and distribution of benefits to members of Congress, because they cite their effectiveness in bringing home money from Washington in their reelection campaigns. Because all members benefit equally from this “pork barrel” spending, there is a powerful incentive to engage in what political scientists call logrolling, in which members pledge to vote for each other’s funding bills. For example, a member of an urban congressional district may pledge to support a rural member’s farm subsidy bill in exchange for support for a

Congressional subcommittees and committees; executive bureaus; small interest groups Congressional subcommittees and committees; full House and Senate; executive agencies; trade associations Subcommittees; executive bureaus and commissions; small interest groups President and his appointees; committees and/or Congress; largest interest groups (peak associations); “liberals/ conservatives”

Distributive

Moderate High (regulatory agencies)

Moderately high

Low

Protective regulatory Competitive regulatory Redistributive

Congressional subcommittees

Very low; very little full congressional involvement High

Moderate

High

Low

Moderately low

Moderate to low

Low (supports High subcommittees) Moderately high Moderate

Congress as whole

Stable

Stable

Unstable

Low

Visibility of decision

High (“peak associations” representing clusters of interest groups)

Moderately high (regulated interests) High (regulated interests)

High (subsidized groups)

Private sector

Source: Table adapted from Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy, by Randall B. Ripley and Grace A. Franklin. Copyright © 1991 by Harcourt, Inc. Reprinted by permission of the author.

High

Low

Distributive

Bureaus

Influence of

Ideological and class conflict

Logrolling among favored actors

Bargaining; compromise

Policy type

High

Stability of relationship

Logrolling Stable (everyone gains)

Relationship among actors

President, presidency, and centralized bureaucracy

Redistributive

Competitive regulatory

Protective regulatory

Primary actors

Policy type

Actors, Stability, and Visibility of Various Policy Types

Table 7.2

211

212 Chapter 7

Interest group liberalism. According to Theodore Lowi, the dominant form of politics in the United States, in which government seeks to accommodate a wide range or relatively narrow interests, rather than attempting to weigh interests against each other and choose to support some interests more or less than others. competitive regulatory policies. These are policies designed to “limit the provision of goods and services to one or a few designated deliverers, who are chosen from a larger number of competing potential deliverers.” The licensing of various professions, and of radio and TV stations, are examples of such policies.

mass transportation bill. This “horse trading” is probably necessary for the expeditious passage of federal spending bills, but Congress’s procedures and norms also encourage this sort of negotiation, leading to more pork barrel spending, which serves to allow members to “bring home the bacon” to their districts. Distributive policy making is made even easier by the inability, in this style of policy making, to easily identify particular groups of people that are benefiting from the policy, while the costs of the policy are more broadly spread across society. Local officials and congressional representatives depict these policies as good for the local community, but as being paid for by the entire nation through general federal funds. Indeed, local spending programs are often justified as a way of gaining a community’s “fair share” of federal taxes paid by the district or state’s taxpayers. Because of the actual or assumed benefits to particular people without any counter groups seeking to stop spending, there is little conflict over distributive policy. It is usually made fairly quickly, easily, and with a minimum amount of scrutiny of individual spending decisions. When the news media or other members do scrutinize such spending, there may sometimes be a call for reform of this system, but the benefits of the current system of pork are so clear that the system of distributive policy endures. This type of policy making is problematic in a democracy, as Theodore Lowi notes in The End of Liberalism.10 Because government programs often create beneficiaries and groups to represent these beneficiaries, the United States is now characterized by what Lowi calls interest group liberalism, in which all claims to federal support and funding are assumed to be legitimate, and few, if any, decisions are made to separate the most compelling claims from the most minor. In such a system, the elected branches of government are more interested in servicing particular interests than in servicing the public interest—or at least something approximating it—as a whole. Regulatory Policies Regulatory policies are, in general terms, policies that are intended to govern the conduct of business. There are two broad types of regulatory policies. Competitive regulatory policy involves policies designed to “limit the provision of goods and services to one or a few designated deliverers, who are chosen from a larger number of competing potential deliverers.”11 Ripley and Franklin cite the allocation of radio and television frequencies by the federal government, and the awarding of cable television franchises by local governments as examples. Another example is policies intended to regulate trades or professions, such as law, medicine, engineering, electrical and plumbing contractors, or hairstyling. States generally assign the power to license professions to members of that particular profession; lawyers and doctors are licensed and regulated by their peers, through state bar associations and state medical associations, respectively. This system ensures

Policies

and

Policy Types

professional oversight of the activities of professionals, who must be trained and regulated to assure competent service to their clients. These policies also create barriers to enter a profession, thereby limiting the number of professionals who provide a service and, possibly, maintaining fees that are higher than they might be in a fully open market. For the most part, competitive regulatory policy is made without much public scrutiny. Much of this policy is made at the state level, further ensuring its low visibility, and the most active participants in such policies tend to be at the legislative committee and trade group levels. Much of this type of policy is relatively arcane and stimulates little public notice. Protective regulatory policy, on the other hand, is intended to protect the public at large from the negative effects of private activity, such as tainted food, air pollution, unsafe consumer products, or fraudulent business transactions. While most businesses and their leaders are responsible citizens who do not wish to hurt or alienate their customers, businesses are also motivated by profit. Businesses often resist regulation on cost grounds, saying that it would reduce or eliminate profit margins, make products uncompetitive on the market, place firms at competitive disadvantages vis-à-vis their foreign competitors (or competitors in other states, if the policy is made at the state level), and so on. Because businesses resist regulation while regulatory agencies insist that they are acting in the public interest, protective regulatory policy tends to be highly contentious. Congressional committees and the full body of Congress get involved, along with major trade organizations (such as the National Association of Manufacturers or the American Bankers Association). Decisions are reached based on negotiation and compromise, because, in most cases, neither business nor the regulators can entirely dominate policy making; Congress and its committees are often put in the position of broker, mediating between the goals of the regulatory agency and business interests.

213

protective regulatory policy. A type of policy that seeks to protect the public and consumers from market problems, such as deceptive advertising, faulty products, or negative externalities (e.g., pollution).

Redistributive Policies Redistributive policy is highly controversial, involving the highest levels of government and the leaders of what are called peak associations (see chapter 6) in policy making characterized by a high level of conflict and difficulty in changing policy. Redistributive policy is characterized by actions “intended to manipulate the allocation of wealth, property, personal or civil rights, or some other valued item among social classes or racial groups.”12 Based on this definition, obvious examples include welfare, civil rights for racial or social minorities, aid to poor cities or schools, and so on. While there has been considerable redistributive policy making in the United States since Franklin D. Roosevelt’s administration, these policies are difficult to pass because the less powerful must prevail over the more powerful interests or at least persuade more powerful groups that it is right and just to approve the redistribution of some resource to the less powerful.

redistributive policy. In Lowi’s policy typology, this is a policy that takes (or seems to take) a resource from one identifiable group and gives a benefit to another readily identifiable group. Such policies are the most controversial and contentious.

214 Chapter 7 It is worth noting, however, that redistributive policy can involve the transfer of resources from the less well off to the better off. During the Reagan administration, the recipients of federal redistributive benefits—the poor, urban areas, economically depressed areas—were depicted as unworthy recipients, and the policies intended to help them were severely criticized. The growing costs and apparently unrealized goals of federal social programs, coupled with the disdain felt by many people for these programs’ recipients, created a political atmosphere in which it became easier— and even politically acceptable—to propose policies such as tax cuts that shifted benefits from the poor to the wealthy.13 These same conditions made it possible for a Democratic president, Bill Clinton, to approve significant reform legislation in the late 1990s, enacted as the Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Act of 1996.14 This act reduced the length of time that individuals could receive public assistance (“welfare”) benefits. And, perhaps most spectacularly, the tax code in the first decade of the twenty-first century was substantially modified to allow more wealth to flow to the very wealthy, while income and wealth remained stagnant or flat for members of the “middle class” and below. Still, some people do speak for the less powerful, and any redistribution of resources—money or rights—is expected to engender controversy. Such policies include the classic welfare policies and also civil rights and liberties policies. The civil rights example is a good illustration of this notion of at least the perception of the redistribution of rights. When blacks began to demand the rights and resources guaranteed them under the Constitution, such as equal opportunity in education, housing, and employment; the right to vote; and the right to due process in criminal proceedings, many people resisted these policies because they believed that they would somehow be losers if blacks were “winners” of these rights. Civil rights legislation was passed in the mid-1960s, but only with high-level governmental participation and after intense and rancorous debate that suffused political and social life from Washington to Main Street. The issue of same-sex marriage also exhibits these characteristics, in which opponents of marriage rights for gay and lesbian couples argue that providing this right to these groups devalues the institution of traditional heterosexual marriage. Proponents of same-sex marriage argue that this would not occur, and that, indeed, allowing same-sex marriage would elevate marriage and family even more. In the end, these arguments about redistribution can be very difficult to analyze because the nature of the redistribution involves features of the good itself—which may be tangible, like money, or intangible, like a right or social position—and of the perceptions of the people from whom something is “taken” and to whom something is “given.” Redistribution also assumes that, in many cases, politics is a zero-sum game, but, as Deborah Stone argues, politics and policy making are not often zerosum propositions. Since the example of the tax code and the shifting of wealth to the wealthy was noted above, it is important to acknowledge the perceptions of various people

Policies

and

Policy Types

215

in the tax policy debate and explain why many people do not consider existing tax policy to be redistributive. Many people who compared Senator John McCain’s and then-Senator Barack Obama’s tax plans during the 2008 presidential election were very concerned that taxes would increase on “middle income” earners, even though both candidates, in one form or another, made clear that tax code changes would affect upper-income earners. But most people in the United States, across a very broad income range, self-identify as “middle class.” Statistically, that family income range is between about $40,000 to $60,000, and more broadly between $20,000 and $100,000. But people who self-identify as middle class have household incomes ranging from $40,000 to $250,000—a huge span, and those at the high end of that range make up the highest 3 percent of family incomes in the nation.15 Thus, concern about middle-class tax increases is likely to be as great among families making near the low end as among the high end of the range. And, most important for this case, many people and families at the lower end of the middle-class range aspire to move up that range, so that a threat to top earners is a threat to their aspirations, even if taxing people higher at the top end somehow benefitted people at the lower end. This shows why some redistributive policy may not be perceived as controversial, as the power of the people to whom the benefit is being distributed—and of the people who aspire to higher economic status—overwhelms the political power of lower-earning families. Lowi’s ideas continue to be quite influential, and for good reason. As Daniel McCool argues, Lowi is a leading theorist of policy types because he approaches policies not merely as outputs of government but as something that shapes and is shaped by political conflict. Thus, in the typology described in Table 7.2, the nature and visibility of political conflict will differ considerably with the type of policy in question. James Q. Wilson: Concentrated and Diffuse Costs and Benefits A persistent criticism of Lowi’s typology of policies is that it is difficult to assign policies to just one category. Some policies have redistributive and regulatory attributes, such as the regulation of consumer product safety that redistributes the responsibility for risk away from consumers and to the companies that manufacture products. Is this regulatory policy, or is it redistributive policy? Depending on how one looks at this policy, it can be both. James Q. Wilson responded to criticisms of Lowi’s policy types by developing a system that rejects ambiguous policy types. Instead, Wilson arranges policies in terms of the extent to which their costs and benefits are focused on one particular interest, or are spread across numerous people or interests. This typology is depicted in Table 7.3. What might be the easiest policies to advocate and enact? In Wilson’s costbenefit typology, a policy that provides an obvious benefit to one group would

cost-benefit analysis. Sometimes called cost-benefit-risk analysis, this policy analysis technique seeks to understand the costs of a course of action and its benefits. When risk is introduced, the risk of something bad happening is also taken into account.

216 Chapter 7 Table 7.3 Wilson’s Cost-Benefit Policy Typology Benefits

Costs

Concentrated among very few people

Distributed among many people

Concentrated among very few people

Interest group politics: conflict between groups that would benefit and those that would bear the costs. Treated as a “zero-sum” game.

Entrepreneurial politics: groups and their leaders seek to persuade policy makers to regulate in the public interest, in the face of opposition from the groups that would bear the cost.

Distributed among many people

Clientele oriented politics: close “clientele” relationships between policy makers, regulators, and the regulated interest.

Majoritarian politics: Relatively loose groups of people, or those acting on their behalf, who seek a substantive or symbolic statement of policy. Often leads to weak, ambiguous policies.

Source: Derived from James Q. Wilson, Political Organizations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995).

motivate that group to press for enactment of the policy; its task would be made even easier if the costs of the policy are hard to assign to a particular group, that is, if the costs are distributed broadly throughout some larger group. Wilson cites as examples the Civil Aeronautics Board (CAB, which, before 1978, regulated air fares and airline routes) and the Federal Communications Commission (FCC, which regulates broadcasting and communications industries) as two agencies that administer this kind of client-oriented policy in which the regulated organizations’ interests are afforded equal or greater importance than the broader “public interest.” In a more contemporary example, a tax benefit enacted in 2009 allows for large home building companies to count their losses in 2008 and 2009 against their profits from previous years, thereby reaping refunds of as much as $400 million from the federal government. In this case, the policy in question is obscure, the beneficiaries are a few companies that would generally like to keep this benefit quiet, and the ultimate cost for this policy will be borne by taxpayers.16 In a similar way, the FCC’s policies for licensing broadcasters ensure that the number of radio and TV stations in a market remains relatively fixed, thereby benefiting broadcasters by providing some sort of predictability, at the potential expense of the general public, which may favor a greater number of broadcast voices. In nearly all these examples, however, there are few organized interests to work against these policies, they are therefore “policies without publics,” and policy making is generally conducted under relatively closed systems that benefit a few interests. On the other hand, if the costs are easily pinned to a particular group or interest, it is likely that the cost-bearing group will take steps to oppose the policy. If the costs

Policies

and

Policy Types

and the benefits are concentrated on identifiable groups, a style of policy making involving interest group conflict becomes prominent. Wilson’s example is the battle between labor and business interests in the field of occupational safety. In particular, both the enactment and the implementation of the Occupational Safety and Health Act, and its administration by the Occupational Safety and Health Administration (OSHA), have led to fierce battles between labor unions and business, because the participants in this debate believe that the benefits of this policy flow to a relatively small number of interests (labor) and are paid for by a relatively small number of interests (business). It is not difficult to find many examples of policies that seek to impose costs on one group in favor of benefits for another within the broader business sector. The regulation of pharmaceutical prices, for example, would pit health insurance companies against drug makers. Tariffs on steel can benefit the domestic steel industry, but can hurt manufacturers who use lots of steel, such as carmakers. These examples show that in many cases “big business” is not monolithic— that some industry sectors’s interests can conflict with the interests of other sectors. What results, however, if both the costs and benefits of a policy are diffuse? Wilson uses as an example the Sherman Antitrust Act. This law prohibits firms from creating anticompetitive “trusts,” which was the term used in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries to describe monopolies or near monopolies that stifled business competition and raised prices in the absence of competition, thereby harming customers. Since so few companies are in a position to create a “trust” or a monopoly, there are very few firms that feel the cost of this policy; at the same time, the benefits of promoting competition are often diffuse, minimally affecting many people rather than having a major influence on our individual economic decision making. This sort of policy is therefore called majoritarian policy making because majorities of the public want antitrust legislation as a means of symbolically reining in business. Anti–big business sentiments were translated to policy without much heated opposition, in large part because the language of the law was so ambiguous—prohibiting “combinations in restraint of trade”—that “it was not exactly clear what was aimed at.”17 This is not to say that antitrust law is a quaint vestige of an earlier age; indeed, some of the most complex and expensive antitrust cases have been brought in the last decade in the computer industry, where companies such as Intel and Microsoft have been sued by governments or rivals for allegedly illegal business practices. The value of Wilson’s typology is not, however, in the names of the policy types; instead, Wilson notes that we should think of the concentration of benefits and costs as tendencies or as ends of two continua rather than as two dichotomies adding up to a four-cell matrix. This said, we can see some relationships between Wilson’s and Lowi’s ways of thinking about policy types and their connections to issue networks or subgovernments. For example, clientelism is closely associated with Lowi’s distribu-

217

218 Chapter 7 tive policy type, in which interest groups gain benefits that are paid for (financially or otherwise) by the bulk of society. This in turn is associated with the subgovernment or iron triangle model of interest relationships, in which interest groups, bureaucracies, and congressional subcommittees work together in a mutually reinforcing relationship.18 However, we should not make too much of this idea of subgovernments, as current research suggests that policy making is rather more open in most cases than the old subgovernment notion would suggest. On the other hand, policies that seek to redistribute costs and benefits—redistributive policies—are highly contentious because they are often perceived as zero-sum situations, in which any gain for one interest is accompanied by an equal and opposite loss by the other. The current discussion of health care reform is a classic example of this conflict, with opponents, in particular, to health care reform claiming that certain groups of people—the elderly under Medicare or the already-insured under employer-paid health insurance—will necessarily lose at lease some of their health care benefits if the system is reformed to provide health care to those who now lack it. But it is important to understand that this distribution of costs and benefits may be as much a social construction as the result of a real calculation of costs and benefits. If a group believes or is convinced that it will bear the costs of a policy, it is likely to act against the policy. Thus, a policy that seeks to reduce youth crime by providing after-school services may be resisted by a large number of citizens because they believe that they are paying a high cost for a less-than-obvious benefit to themselves. This illustration shows the difficulty of linking policies to actual benefits, but also illustrates how benefits and costs seem to be as much in the eye of the beholder as a carefully calculated accounting exercise. If these attributes of policy (cost/benefit, distribution/redistribution) are so prone to perception, then what good is any exercise in assigning policy types? Lowi noted in 1964 that “it is not the actual outcomes but the expectations as to what the outcomes can be that shape the issues and determine their politics.”19 Peter Steinberger also addresses this issue by “conceptualizing some of the ways in which participants tend to define policies.”20 In other words, policies may not have inherent meanings in terms of any policy typology but may gain their meanings only when groups discern meanings and propagate them among friendly and hostile audiences. For example, many safety innovations in automobiles and other consumer products cost relatively little per item produced, but manufacturers and their allies believe that the additional cost will make their products unprofitable. This argument will help persuade groups to mobilize in a particular way based on a perception of policy. Other Policy Typologies The Lowi and Wilson typologies are not the only ways to categorize public policies. The following are four additional and not mutually exclusive ways to categorize policies. Of course, as in any typology, policies may not fit into perfectly delineated boxes

Policies

and

Policy Types

219

or cells, but approaching policies in a manner described here may help you gain insight into the features of policy that are most important from an analytic perspective. Substantive and Procedural Policies James Anderson reminds us of the very important difference between policies that set the rules for policy making and the more familiar policies that actually provide the goods and services we expect from government. He defines the difference between substantive and procedural polices as what government does versus how it does it. Nevertheless, procedural policies are very important and actually have, in the end, a substantive effect on politics.21 Anderson cites the federal Administrative Procedures Act (APA) of 1946 as a particularly important procedural policy; the states have similar laws. The APA establishes the procedure by which government agencies make, issue, and enforce rules and regulations as they implement the laws passed by Congress. If a regulation (or a “rule,” in the language of the act) is established by an agency following the processes laid out by the APA, then it is assumed to have the force of law (like statute or case law). The APA governs how federal agencies let citizens know that they are going to make a rule and how the public can comment on the rule and offer suggestions or express their opposition to the rules, as we saw in the case study earlier in this chapter. While the details of federal rule making sound pretty dry, overall we can say that the APA is a very important policy. How would American government be different if there was no one way for the federal government to make rules in the open, accessible to public comment and opposition? Could certain interests benefit and others be harmed if the regulatory process were kept a secret? It would seem so, which is why, in future enactments, Congress amended the APA to make government even more open through the Freedom of Information Act and the Privacy Act of 1974, and the 1976 Government in the Sunshine Act. The overall goal, while procedural, is to ensure fairness in governmental dealing with citizens, which is substantively important as well.22 In most cases, procedural policy itself is not controversial. After all, procedural policy in the United States and in most democracies has been devoted to creating more transparent government, giving citizens more opportunities to participate in the process. While procedural policies are generally noncontroversial, the procedures are important in the history and resolution of controversies that have arisen. In recent years, organizations and interests that have been the subjects of regulation have sought to mobilize their supporters to respond during the public comment period for proposed regulations. Indeed, in the late 1990s and early 2000s, General Electric sought to mobilize public support against EPA decisions to require that they dredge the Hudson River in New York to reduce water pollution caused by their manufacturing plants. The pollution, from PCBs, was considered by many to be a human health hazard, but GE opposed dredging on cost grounds, and claimed that dredging would stir up more pollutants than it cleaned. By inspiring thousands of comments, GE delayed the final regulation, and the regulatory process generated

substantive policy. A policy that explains how the government will go about its policy goals in a particular area. Contrast with symbolic policy and procedural policy. procedural policy. A policy that determines how the government’s procedures—the way it goes about its work—are to be governed. The Administrative Procedures Act is an example of a procedural policy; such policies can have a substantive influence on policies. Administrative Procedures Act. A federal law (5 U.S.C. 551 et seq.) that requires regulatory agencies to follow particular procedures in rule making, such as public notice of new rules, public comment periods, publication of rule making activity in the Federal Register, and the like.

220 Chapter 7 more paper than it otherwise would have. Thus, the rules that allow public access to the regulatory process can benefit both regulated interests and the people who support the regulation. On the other hand, agencies are becoming savvy about extensive comments on regulations generated by interest groups and provided as part of a mass mailing or e-mailing campaign, in which opposition to (or, rarely, support for) a new regulation is expressed by nonexperts in a repetitive way.23 Material and Symbolic Policies

symbolic policy. A policy that satisfies public demand for statements of principles or values, without any resources to support them. The naming of post offices, highways, and airports after famous people, or the TV networks’ adoption (in the face of FCC and congressional pressure) of a voluntary system of television content ratings similar to those of movies, can be seen as symbolic policies, although the line between symbolic and substantive policies is not always clear.

Another way to categorize policies is to examine whether the policy is material or symbolic. While the distinction between these two is not absolute, one can distinguish between material policies, which provide a material (that is, tangible and obvious) benefit to people, and symbolic policies, which simply appeal to people’s values without any resources or actual effort behind them. A material policy, for example, may be a federal grant that provides money to local communities to hire police officers, as was implemented in the Clinton administration. Examples of symbolic policies include antidrug efforts such as the “Just Say No” and Drug Abuse Resistance Education (DARE) campaigns, and legislation and proposed constitutional amendments that would prohibit burning the flag (the latter laws were held as unconstitutional by the Supreme Court in Texas v. Johnson24). As Anderson notes, these policies appeal to our values and our sense of idealism, but do not really deliver any particular benefit, whether they claim to or not. Sometimes symbolic policies allege to have an impact, but this is often based on faulty causal reasoning. For example, the system of TV show ratings was developed in response to a widespread belief that various social ills, particularly among children, resulted from violent or sexually suggestive TV shows. There is little research to substantiate this, but the TV industry implemented a voluntary ratings scheme to preempt federal legislation. In this case, TV ratings systems are the symbolic policies intended to address the perceived problem. By enacting the symbolic policy, various actors can claim to have “done something” about a problem, even when the action taken is more symbolic than anything else. Public versus Private Goods

private goods. Goods that can be provided in the open market without major free riding problems; contrast with public goods.

One of the main ways we distinguish between what should be provided by government and what is better provided by the private sector is by analyzing whether a good is public or private. Again, public goods are those that, once provided for one user, are available to all in a society and cannot be exclusively consumed by a single person or group of people. Private goods are goods that can be used by only the immediate consumer and whose enjoyment is then denied to others. One rationale for government is that it exists to provide public goods that would ordinarily not be provided by the private sector in the normal course of business.

Policies

and

Policy Types

221

Case Study: The Challenges of Policy Typologies: When Is a Symbolic Policy Not Merely Symbolic? When is a policy strictly symbolic, and when does it have important material implications? Many resolutions passed by Congress recognize a particular event, person, or achievement. These resolutions typically do not require any funding or change in government activity. Their purpose is to state for the record that Congress recognizes the significance of the matter. These resolutions are purely symbolic legislation in every sense. Congress passes a great deal of symbolic legislation every year. Much of this is contained in resolutions that can be researched on the THOMAS database (http://thomas.loc.gov). On this site, under Bill Summary and Status, search on the term “commemorating” in the Word/ Phrase field. This leads to a list of things that Congress seeks to commemorate: House resolution 342, for example, “Supporting the National Railroad Hall of Fame, Inc., of Galesburg, Illinois, in its endeavor to erect a monument known as the National Railroad Hall of Fame.” The resolution is sponsored by Rep. Lane Evans, who represents Galesburg in Congress. The bill is almost entirely symbolic, as it commits no funds or anything else of value to the National Railroad Hall of Fame. But it recognizes the community and the people working to create the Hall of Fame and many Americans who like trains may well support this gesture. There are two policies that may appear to be symbolic acts that have important material consequences: the Martin Luther King, Jr., holiday and the attempts to ban desecration of the United States flag. Since 1986, on the third Monday of January every year, Americans have celebrated the birthday of the Rev. Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., the renowned civil rights leader who was murdered in Memphis in 1968. Legislation to create a federal holiday to honor King was signed by President Reagan in 1983. To mark the holiday, federal offices close and, as of 1999, all the states have chosen to close government facilities and public schools on the same day. The main purpose of the holiday is to observe and honor the great civil rights leader and to provide an opportunity for reflection on his legacy and on the civil rights movement in general. Many people may view the King holiday as merely symbolic or just a day off from work in January. But the establishment of a King holiday has created notable controversy among the states over the years. In 1999 New Hampshire was the last of the fifty states to fully observe the holiday. The New Hampshire legislature had passed a law in 1991 declaring the same day in January Civil Rights Day without referring to Dr. King at all.25 For a time Arizona rescinded its observance of the King holiday. Many southern states chose to make the same day “Robert E. Lee Day,” and this designation remains on the books in many of these states. One may argue that holding a King holiday is a material policy because it grants millions of federal workers a paid holiday. This benefit costs the government millions of dollars each year. Yet the primary reason for passing this legislation was not simply to give federal workers another day off, but to elevate Rev. King’s birthday to the level of honor previously reserved for presidents Washington and Lincoln. The second example of a policy that may seem largely symbolic is legislation that seeks to prohibit the burning or desecration of the United States flag. Proper flag etiquette requires burning a worn or dirty flag in an appropriate manner, but many Americans were deeply (continued)

222 Chapter 7

Case Study (continued) disturbed when Gregory Johnson burned a flag in protest at the 1984 Republican National Convention. For this act Johnson was convicted of desecrating the flag in violation of Texas law. In 1989 the Supreme Court affirmed the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals’ ruling that flag burning is a protected form of speech that cannot, under the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, be abridged by the states.26 The dissenting justices in this case, like many Americans, pointed to the long history of reverence for the flag as a justification for affording it greater protection against desecration. Chief Justice Rehnquist quoted liberally from poetry and from the “Star Spangled Banner,” and explicitly noted the extremely evocative image of the Marines planting the flag on Iwo Jima during World War II; later, this image was echoed in the raising of the flag by three firemen over the wreckage of the World Trade Center in 2001. After the Court’s 1989 decision, Congress and the states have sought to protect the flag from desecration but have come up short, usually running up against the First Amendment or against the inherent difficulty involved in amending the Constitution to include a provision prohibiting flag desecration. And, of course, one person’s desecration may be another person’s free speech, or even a fashion statement.27 The question here, though, is whether this symbol—the flag—has deeper material importance and meaning. Justice Rehnquist believed it does, when he wrote, in dissent: The American flag . . . throughout more than 200 years of our history, has come to be the visible symbol embodying our Nation. It does not represent the views of any particular political party, and it does not represent any particular political philosophy. The flag is not simply another “idea” or “point of view” competing for recognition in the marketplace of ideas. Millions and millions of Americans regard it with an almost mystical reverence regardless of what sort of social, political, or philosophical beliefs they may have. I cannot agree that the First Amendment invalidates the Act of Congress, and the laws of 48 of the 50 States, which make criminal the public burning of the flag.

Like other typologies that try to categorize policies, the symbolic versus material policy typology should be viewed as a continuum and not as separate absolute categories. Would you say that the King holiday is more symbolic or material? If a law were passed that led to fines or a jail sentence, such as the Texas flag desecration law, would the law be symbolic or does it have material implications? What do these examples tell us about the advantages and disadvantages of the various policy typologies?

Laws that provide for clean air and water are classic examples of public goods: a decision to clean up the air or water for one person requires that everyone be provided with a better environment. Similarly, it would be difficult to set up a system of police protection in which only those who subscribe to police services receive protection against crime. The public-private goods distinction, like most typologies, is not a fine distinction. There are other factors to take into account besides the consumption of a particular good. For example, the United States Postal Service (USPS) is a quasigovernmental

Policies

and

Policy Types

corporation that provides document and package delivery services. FedEx, United Parcel Service, Airborne, and other firms are also in the same business. Why, then, should the USPS continue in business if private firms can do the job? After all, mail and parcel delivery has all the hallmarks of a private good: the service is consumed individually, when a person decides to send a letter or package. But the USPS exists because of a goal that the private sector firms do not pursue: universal service. A person can send a letter from Key West, Florida, to either Miami (about 150 miles away) or Kotzebue, Alaska (thousands of miles away), for the same postage. Many private firms would not serve Kotzebue, a remote village on the shores of the Arctic Ocean, because it is not profitable. Federal law therefore requires that certain kinds of mail can be carried only by the USPS, because the profits made on easily delivered mail, such as from Manhattan to Queens, cover the costs of delivering remote mail. When categorizing a good as public or private, the system of providing that good may be as important as the good itself. For this reason, some European countries, for example, consider other goods to be public or quasipublic goods, or choose to provide goods through publicly owned corporations. The federal government subsidizes intercity rail service through Amtrak, but there have been almost yearly battles over the nature and future of this mode of transportation. Yet, as our experience in the late 1960s showed, the railroads could or would not provide this service; if it was to be provided at all, it would be provided by government. Most European countries, on the other hand, assume that transport is a public responsibility, and they have owned and subsidized these services. They do so to ensure that service is widely available and to support other policy goals related to industrial development, urban planning, and the like. The United States does not generally view rail transport in this way, and often looks at Amtrak through a private sector lens— “it doesn’t make a profit”—without considering the extent to which other modes of transportation are public goods, such as roads and air traffic control systems, which also are generally unprofitable. Liberal and Conservative Policies This is perhaps the most commonly employed typology in everyday discussion of politics. In fact, to many people, the terms themselves are terms of pride or derision. During the 1980s, the term “liberal” was used by President Reagan and his allies as a term of scorn for the failed social policies of the 1930s and 1960s, while self-described liberals use the term to identify themselves as believing in the power of government to better the lives of everyone, rich or poor. In today’s usage, a conservative is one who believes in the primacy of individual initiative and effort over government action. Conservatives are likely to believe that government is too big, that it tends to be as much or more an instrument of mischief as of progress. Liberals, on the other hand, believe that government can and should work to equalize differences between the wealthy powerful and the poor and less powerful. These terms tend

223

224 Chapter 7 to carry with them positive or negative connotations, and those connotations shift with the tenor of the times. For example, the term “liberal” was in disrepute during the 1980s, the result of a successful effort by the Republican Party to discredit the term “liberalism” by associating it with failed policies. But the term has lost some of its negative connotations during the early months of the Obama administration, when policies associated with “conservatives,” such as light banking regulation, were said to have led to the financial crisis of 2008 and 2009. Of course, this description is written in remarkably broad strokes. Not all conservatives think that government is evil, just as no liberals believe that government is always a force for good. Indeed, when we analyze the sorts of policies that people who self-style themselves as liberal or conservative propose, these distinctions become very blurry. Conservatives prize individual liberty, yet often propose more stringent anticrime measures than liberals. Liberals expect governmental initiatives to solve problems, yet are often the most concerned with government incursions on privacy and liberty. In the end, it is quite hard to characterize a policy as merely liberal or conservative. Conclusion There are many ways to think about how decisions are made to solve a policy problem. Theories of how decisions are made lead explicitly to theories of how decisions should be made. As you study and participate in public policy, it is worthwhile to ask yourself whether the decisions that are being made could be made better. When you do so, however, remember to think carefully about what you mean by “better.” The theorists really do not have an opinion about what a better policy is; a rationalist would argue that the best policy is the policy that is most likely to solve a problem; you might have different goals and values that would make defining the “best” policy as much a political as an analytical problem.

Key Terms Administrative Procedures Act Code of Federal Regulations Competitive regulatory policy Cost-benefit typology Distributive policy Federal Register

Interest group liberalism Policy Private goods Procedural policy Protective regulatory policy Redistributive policy

Street-level bureaucrats Substantive policy Symbolic policy Typology

Policies

and

Policy Types

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. Why is designing a policy within the American system of government such a complex undertaking? Why can’t one just refer to one document to understand a public policy? 2. Why are there agencies that issue regulations, particularly since these agencies are not headed by elected officials? Why doesn’t Congress just draft and apply the rules? How does Congress delegate policy-making responsibility while maintaining some sort of accountability? 3. List and describe Lowi’s three classic policy types. Then think of policies that would fit in each policy type. Is it easy to fit policies within one type, or are you having trouble finding a single category into which a policy will fit? Does Wilson’s cost-benefit typology make this task of categorizing policies any easier? Why do we use these typologies at all? 4. We make a distinction between procedural policies, which set the rules for making other policies, and substantive policies, which are about particular policy areas (such as health policy or education policy). But does procedural policy have substantive meaning in the policy process? Does it matter what the rules to the game are? Why do you think we have the Administrative Procedure Act? What would policy look like if agencies didn’t have to first announce rules and regulations in the Federal Register before they are published in the Code of Federal Regulations? 5. Why is clean air considered a public good? Can you think of any ways to make clean air a private good that would be traded in a market? Are there other goods that were once considered public goods that are now broadly considered private goods, or vice versa? 6. Is the conservative/liberal policy typology a useful way to describe and analyze policy? Why or why not? What are the benefits and shortcomings of labeling an idea, organization, or person as a liberal or a conservative? 7. Give examples of material and symbolic policies. Then consider the debates over these policies. Why do you think that some debates over symbolic policies, which don’t really provide any tangible product or service, are among the most contentious and emotional in politics and policy making? 8. Think of an issue you care deeply about, such as welfare reform policy, environmental policy, or health care. Using the tools available in your library, such as LexisNexis, or via the Internet (http://www.gpoaccess.gov/fr/ index.html), search the Federal Register to see whether there is any current regulatory activity in your area of interest. In particular, you may wish to look at notices of proposed rulemaking (NPRMs), to see what sort of rules government regulators are thinking about implementing. What did you find? Are the rules highly technical or are they in language that you, your friends, your family, or other like-minded people could understand? Do you feel

225

226 Chapter 7 qualified to submit comments to the regulatory agency regarding the NPRM you found? Based on what you see, why do you think that comments come mostly from regulated interests and technical experts, rather than from the general public? â•… This project would work best with a group of people in your class. Gather a group of between four to six people. Then develop a list of about ten to twelve different policies (either specific laws, such as the No Child Left Behind Act, or general policy areas, such as “education policy”) and attempt to place them within Lowi’s distributive-redistributive-regulatory typology. Do you find that some policies fit into more than one category? Then repeat the process using Wilson’s focused-diffused cost-benefit typology. Which typology do you find is more usable? Which is most useful in helping us to understand how the types of policies can influence politics? Additional Reading Clearly, in a discussion of policy types the place to start reading is at the beginning of the efforts to create policy typologies: Theodore Lowi, “American Business, Public Policy, Case Studies, and Political Theory,” World Politics 16 (July 1964): 667–715. Randall Ripley and Grace Franklin made good use of Lowi’s typology to explain policy making in Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy, 5th ed. (Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks-Cole, 1991), which adopts and extends Lowi’s distributiveredistributive-regulatory policy typology to illustrate the relationships among Congress, the bureaucracy, and interest groups in the policy process. An alternative to the Lowi typology is provided by James Q. Wilson in Political Organizations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), in which Wilson more carefully discusses his concentrated-diffuse cost-benefit typology of public policies. Notes 1. Or three-quarters of state conventions, called to consider the proposed change, must ratify the amendment. This was undertaken once, with the ratification of the Twenty-First Amendment, which repealed the prohibition of alcohol in the United States (the Eighteenth Amendment). All amendment provisions are laid out in Article V of the Constitution. 2. The United States Code is available through many online sources. I prefer the site maintained by the Legal Information Institute at Cornell University: http://www.law.cornell.edu/uscode/. Findlaw.com’s Web site, while rather difficult for novices to navigate, has powerful search features for federal and state law: http://www.findlaw. com/casecode/. 3. See, for example, Milton Friedman, “Freedom’s Friend,” Wall Street Journal, June 11, 2004, http://online. wsj.com/article/SB108691016978034663-email.html (accessed February 15, 2010). 4. 367 U.S. 643 (1961). 5. Dean J. Champion, Police Misconduct in America: A Reference Handbook (Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-CLIO, 2001), 49. The study on which this is based was published in “Effect of Mapp v. Ohio on Police Search and Seizure Practices in Narcotics Cases,” Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems 4 (1968): 87. 6. Specifically, they were codified as 14 CFR 25.855 et seq., and 14 CFR 121.314 et seq.

Policies

and

Policy Types

227

7. Theodore J. Lowi, “American Business, Public Policy, Case Studies, and Political Theory,” World Politics 16 (July 1964): 667–715. 8. Randall Ripley and Grace Franklin, Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy, 5th ed. (Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks-Cole, 1991). 9. While budgeting is a very important element of the policy process, it is also somewhat technical and is not taken up in this book. James Anderson’s Public Policymaking, 5th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2002) contains an excellent introduction to the federal budget process. There are also specialized texts on budgeting, such as Aaron Wildavsky and Naomi Caiden, The New Politics of the Budgetary Process, 4th ed. (New York: HarperCollins, 2000); John Cranford, Budgeting for America (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 1989); and John F. Cogan, The Budget Puzzle: Understanding Federal Spending (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994). 10. Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States, 2d ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 1979). 11. Ripley and Franklin, Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy, 20. 12. Ibid., 21. 13. See, for example, Kevin P. Phillips, The Politics of Rich and Poor: Wealth and the American Electorate in the Reagan Aftermath (New York: Random House, 1990). 14. PL 104-193. 15. These figures are derived from Brian W. Cashell, “Who Are The “Middle Class?” in CRS Report for Congress (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2008), http://digitalcommons.ilr.cornell.edu/cgi/viewcontent. cgi?article=1557&context=key_workplace (accessed January 2, 2010). 16. Gretechen Morgenson, “Home Builders (You Heard That Right) Get a Gift,” The New York Times, November 14, 2009, http://www.nytimes.com/2009/11/15/business/economy/15gret.html (accessed February 15, 2010). 17. James Q. Wilson, Bureaucracy (New York: Basic Books, 1989), 79. Many of the examples in this discussion are drawn from this book. See also James Q. Wilson, Political Organizations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), chapter 16. 18. Richard J. Stillman, The American Bureaucracy (Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1996), 135–36. 19. Lowi, “American Business,” 707. 20. Peter J. Steinberger, “Typologies of Public Policy: Meaning Construction and the Policy Process,” Social Science Quarterly 61 (September 1980): 185–97. 21. The following section on different policy types relies largely on Anderson, Public Policymaking, chapter 1. 22. For a general discussion of the rule-making process under the APA, see Charles H. Levine, B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson, Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences (Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman/Little Brown, 1990), 169–170. 23. Stuart W. Shulman, “The Case Against Mass E-mails: Perverse Incentives and Low Quality Public Participation in U.S. Federal Rulemaking,” Policy & Internet 1(1) (2009), http://www.psocommons.org/policyandinternet/ vol1/iss1/art2. 24. 491 U.S. 397 (1989). 25. Carey Goldberg, “Contrarian New Hampshire To Honor Dr. King, at Last,” The New York Times, May 26, 1999, Section A, p. 24. 26. Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989). 27. Steven Heller, “Separated at Birth: Capture the Flag,” Print, September/October 2004, 10.

Policy Design, Policy Tools, and Decisions

8

CHAPTER

Chapter at a Glance Some General Concepts Preparing to Design Policies Problems Goals Ambiguity and Goal Conflict Case Study: The USA Patriot Act and Airport Screening: â•… Liberty versus Security Proper Causal Theory Policy Tools Types of Policy Tools Other Categories of Policy Tools Tools and Choices in Policy Design Decisions Rational Comprehensive Decision Making Bounded Rationality and Incrementalism Other Models of Decision Making Conclusion Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

policy design. The process by which policies are designed, both through technical analysis and the political process, to achieve a particular goal.

Once a problem has been identified and decision makers place the issue on the agenda for active consideration, there is still more to do to move an idea from a successful contestant on the agenda to a fleshed-out policy. This chapter reviews two more aspects of the policy process. The first is what policy scholars call policy design, which is the process by which policies are designed, both through technical analysis and through the political process, to achieve a particular goal. After the policy is designed, it is enacted and then implemented, at which point the administrative agencies translate the will of the executive and legislative branches into actual policy outcomes. The second aspect is the decision-making process. This chapter includes some key theories of how people and organizations make decisions. As in many analyses

228

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

of the policy process, this description is greatly simplified so it is helpful in understanding the process without being bogged down in theoretical detail. Chapter 9 focuses on policy implementation. In reading about implementation it is important to note that it is impossible to separate the process of designing policies from their implementation—much as all the stages of the policy process are hard to separate. Design and implementation are very closely related because the choices made in the design of a policy will profoundly influence the way a policy is implemented, which then influences the outcomes of these policies. In fact, policy designers often base their policy designs on experience with similar policies that have already been implemented. Another reason that design and implementation are hard to separate from the rest of the policy process is that the policy design process continues during design and implementation. Congress’s enactment of law does not result in a simple translation from Congress’s will to actual action on the part of government agencies, or actual compliance on the part of the people whose behavior the policy seeks to change. Agencies must take what Congress has passed and figure out what it requires or allows them to do. The process of translating vague legislative commands into rules and regulations can be among the most contentious and difficult activities in the entire policy process. Once policies are implemented, experience with it and with similar policies will often change the policy design, even when the policy and goals are supposedly in place and operating. For example, targeted federal spending on particular urban problems was once granted based on focused federal goals and specific programmatic interests. This policy changed because, to a considerable extent, implementation was not as successful as had been hoped. The targeted policy was replaced by block grants, in which state and local governments are freer to make choices about how the money is spent, provided that relatively broad federal goals are met. Some General Concepts As described in chapter 2, systems models of the policy process call laws, decisions, regulations, and the like outputs of the policy system. Policies regulating environmental health or national security are one type of output; the actual services provided by the government in monitoring pollution or in securing airplanes are also outputs. Outputs are generally easily understood, both conceptually and in concrete form. It is much harder to measure the outcomes of all this effort. Both outputs and outcomes are important to measure, but for different reasons. Outputs allow one to figure out how to link resources to the output of an organization. Consider the college or university you attend. How do we measure the performance of the university? Through factors such as number of students graduated, the graduation rate, time to completion of degrees, and so on. But these figures are outputs, not outcomes. Outcomes are the result of what happens when your college or university gradu-

229

outcomes. The substantive results of the implementation of a policy. Outcomes can be intended or unintended, positive or negative. This differs from outputs, which are laws, regulations, rules, and the like; or the effort that government expends to address problems. For example, more teaching hours provided by a school district is an output; the outcome would be, one hopes, an improvement in students’ educational achievement.

230 Chapter 8 ates all these students and they enter the world. Are students prepared for the job market? Will they be able to compete with others on the job market? Will they make significant contributions to society through artistic expression, scientific discovery, or excellent business management or entrepreneurial enterprise? These kinds of things are often very hard to measure, because they are very difficult to quantify. We in higher education say that education makes people better people. But how? Are educated people smarter? More compassionate? Better able to earn a living? These outcomes are often hard to measure because the concepts easy to measure are or would be prohibitively expensive to study. How do we measure whether someone is “well rounded?” Keeping track of the career path of every alumnus is quite complicated. Teachers, in particular, object greatly to outcome measures of their performance as teachers, such as test scores, because the data may not really measure what we want to know—the so-called validity problem—and because there are so many variables influencing student outcomes outside of the teacher’s control. With this in mind, it may be easy to understand why many agencies measure outputs; that is, they measure what they do, not their impact on particular problems.1 It is possible, with some care, to link actual outcomes to results. This requires a good causal model of a policy, that is, a model of how the effort expended causes a particular outcome. Preparing to Design Policies At some point (preferably early) in the policy design process, decision makers must explicitly consider five elements of policy design, as listed in Table 8.1. Problems As noted in chapter 6, there is a substantial difference between a condition, about which little or nothing can be done, and a problem, about which some sort of private or public action can be taken. The initial debate over policy is, therefore, about whether something really is a problem, to what extent it is a problem, who it affects, and so on. The definition of the problem, as E.E. Schattschneider noted, often shapes the way the problem is treated throughout the policy process. For example, was Hurricane Katrina an “act of God,” about which little or nothing could have been done before the event, or was the hurricane less a meteorological phenomenon and more a focusing event that worsened and called attention to social and technological problems that can be mitigated or avoided through appropriate public policy? The post-Katrina debate seems to have adopted the latter interpretation, yet, in the past— and even in many places today—the “act of God” interpretation is powerful. We generally know about public problems through two mechanisms. In one, we learn about problems through changes in the indicators of a problem over time, rather than all of a sudden. For example, in 2009 swine flu (technically, the H1N1 pandemic)

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

231

Table 8.1 Elements of Policy Design Element

Questions to ask

The goals of the policy

What are the goals of the policy? To eliminate a problem? To alleviate a problem but not entirely eliminate it? To keep a problem from getting worse?

The causal model

What is the causal model? Do we know that, if we do X, Y will result? How do we know this? If we don’t know, how can we find out?

The tools of the policy

What tools or instruments will be used to put the policy into effect? Will they be more or less coercive? Will they rely more on incentives, persuasion, or information? Capacity building?

The targets of the policy

Whose behavior is supposed to change? Are there direct and indirect targets? Are design choices predicated on our social construction of the target population?

The implementation of the policy

How will the program be implemented? Who will lay out the implementation system? Will a top-down or bottom-up design be selected? Why?

gained attention as a public policy problem when it first came to light in cases in Mexico, whereupon it spread to the United States and then worldwide. The flu did not strike all at once; rather, the sort of data that is routinely gathered by hospitals and health care workers began to accumulate as public health professionals and, later, elected and other appointed officials and the general public became aware of the problem. Other problems become evident through focusing events, which are sudden events such as earthquakes, terrorist attacks, or industrial accidents. Another class of focusing event is the kind of event that affects a particularly influential member of a policy community. It is well known that when famous people contract diseases, or when a member of Congress or his or her family members have or contract a disease, more attention is paid to the problem than would ordinarily be paid. This discussion sounds like the agenda-setting discussion in chapter 6. But it is essential to understand that problems don’t merely “exist” in the world in a selfevident way. For example, one can argue that childhood obesity is caused by the proliferation of junk food, fast food restaurants, and television and video games, all of which lead to poor diets and sedentary lifestyles. Others argue that the problem is caused by a lack of open space and by poor urban design, which makes people less likely to walk or play outside and more likely to go about in cars. Some people believe that childhood obesity may simply be a matter of poor parenting, poor selfcontrol, and laziness. Nearly all the other aspects of policy design will flow from this definition of the problem—one can imagine policies that are intended to regulate junk food and video entertainment to cause kids to be more active, or policies that encourage activity through better urban form, or through public education activities to persuade or shame people into ensuring that kids need to be more active. Each of these policies assumes different causal theories and therefore will suggest different policy tools.

232 Chapter 8 Goals Policies are made because someone has persuaded enough of us (i.e., citizens, elected officials, or both) that something needs to be done about a problem. Policies are created to meet or at least to make progress toward these goals: policies to fund research on vaccines and to mandate their use by children; policies meant to desegregate schools, public facilities, and workplaces; policies to provide a “social safety net” for the poor and others hit by economic downturns; and policies to create jobs. All of these policies are linked to perceived problems and goals. There are many ways to think about and categorize goals. A particularly useful way of thinking about goals is found in Deborah Stone’s Policy Paradox. Stone lists four major categories of goals: equity, efficiency, security, and liberty. In many cases, Stone argues, these goals clash: most prominently, security often conflicts with liberty, and some political systems have tended to favor various forms of security while curtailing liberty. Efficiency can conflict with all these goals. Indeed, these conflicts are intensified by the many different definitions of goals. Stone helps us to understand this by listing eight different ways of defining “equality.” She uses the example of dividing a large chocolate cake among the members of a class. One might argue that the most equitable division is to simply count the number of people in the room and divide the cake into that number of pieces. But Stone argues that one can divide the cake a number of different ways—by the rank of the people in the room (professor, graduate students, undergraduates, for example); or by athletic or physical prowess; or by gender—and still justify the decision for dividing resources as “equal.”2 If this seems fanciful to you, consider traditional American notions of equality, in which we claim that we believe that everyone should have equal opportunity for success but no guarantee of equal outcomes—particularly when the opportunities themselves are not equal. Other nations, such as the Scandinavian countries, are more serious about coming closer to equality of outcome. Others will argue that, by right, some people simply shouldn’t be equal to others in particular ways. Before women were given the vote and other civil rights, men (and some women) argued that women were the “fairer sex” who were unsuited to physical labor or even rigorous intellectual pursuits; they were deemed best at homemaking. Blacks were considered nonpersons—and therefore unsuited for anything like equality—in the infamous Dredd Scott decision; and today, gays and lesbians are considered sufficiently different from others that they are unable to marry or, in some jurisdictions, to establish families and to share health insurance and other workplace benefits. Stone notes, indeed, that arguments that seek to exclude people from the recognized boundaries of a community are often invoked to deny some form of equality to these people. The current red-hot debate in the United States over the treatment of illegal immigrants is a case in point.

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

233

Defining Efficiency Deborah Stone argues that efficiency is more a means to a goal rather than a goal itself, but she treats efficiency as a goal category because many policy advocates tout their ideas on purported improvements in efficiency. Efficiency is a particularly important aspect of policy making in the United States, given our emphasis on limited government and individual initiative and in the context of calls for the government to run “more like a business.” An economist might define efficiency as gaining the most output for a given level of input, which means, in layman’s terms, more bang for the buck. It also means the same bang for fewer bucks. If the efficiency of a program improves by 10 percent, spending on the program could be reduced by 10 percent without a loss of benefits. This sort of thinking is commonplace, particularly among those who support smaller government or who wish to shift resources to other programs. Spending cuts or budget reallocations are often justified by the belief that one can gain considerable resources by simply cutting the “waste, fraud, and abuse” from programs. This thinking in government tends to overlook important issues. First, the public sector may not be any more or less efficient in some ways than large private sector firms, such as IBM or General Motors. The private sector tends to have fewer formal controls over such waste than the public sector, although accounting practices in the private sector will certainly reveal decreasing profitability or diminishing assets. It is of course highly desirable to reduce or eliminate waste, fraud, or abuse in both the public and private sectors. However, there may not be as much waste, fraud, and abuse in government as there are decisions to provide benefits to narrower interests at the expense of the majority, as we learned in chapter 6. People who oppose certain programs will often do so because they disagree with the substance of the policy, but find the waste, fraud, and abuse argument more successful than arguing the program on its merits, particularly because no one, including most proponents of policy, favors waste. There are many different ways of understanding efficiency, depending on how we describe inputs and outputs. Stone argues that governmental activities provide inputs and outputs. She cites an example of how we might define efficiency in a public library system. While librarians’ salaries can be seen as inputs, their earnings have a small but discernible impact on the community and therefore also serve as outputs. Beyond this simple example, Stone uses a theme that extends our thinking about policy beyond economics. She posits that society can be viewed as a market or as the polis. The latter term refers to the “essential political society,” or what I take to mean the community as a whole. The decisions we make to address our common problems are usually political (cooperation, negotiation, common or public interests) rather than market based (voluntary exchanges between just two parties intended to increase both parties’ welfare). Clearly, if more people and interests are taken into

efficiency. Gaining the most output for a given level of input, or getting “more bang for the buck.” Efficiency is often thought of as getting the same output for less of a particular input, or getting more of something for a constant input.

polis. In Deborah Stone’s book Policy Paradox, the polis is the political community, and is contrasted with the market as a way of describing human organization and interaction.

234 Chapter 8 account in the polis than in the market, we could reasonably argue that the “polis model” is more complex than a simple market model. If this is true, then efficiency in political terms is quite complex, as hard to define in just one way as equity is. For example, it is traditional to think about governmental administrative costs as wasted or “overhead” expenses that take resources away from more useful activity. As Stone argues, however, “merely calling something ‘administrative’ as opposed to ‘productive’ is a way of prejudicing the argument.”3 But how do we distinguish core instructional activities from administrative activities? Stone cites the example of a New Jersey plan to cut administrative costs by imposing penalties on schools with excessive “administrative” costs; the plan would categorize “school librarians, nurses, and guidance counselors as ‘administrative.’” By categorizing these positions as administrative, New Jersey was sending a signal that the responsibilities of these positions do not contribute to the goals of a school. What might the librarians, school nurses, and counselors think of this argument? What if the custodian were considered an “administrative” position, even if we assume that the custodian keeps the school in good working order so that teachers and students have a proper place to work? Perhaps these “administrators” would mobilize to show how their activities contribute to the goals of the school or simply make schools better places in which to spend the better part of the day. In any case, classifying these activities as “administrative” in order to achieve some level of “efficiency” is more a political decision than an objective economic or accounting decision. Because it is a political decision (in the “who gets what” sense), one then can use political rhetoric (argument and persuasion) to counter the proposal. This is not to say that one cannot or should not use economic or accounting data to make a case for or against moves to create efficiency. Rather, such arguments are likely only a part of a broader political argument regarding the desirability of programs. Such evidence is thus part of the advocacy process, not the be-all and end-all of the argument. Conflicting Goals: Security and Liberty Two other goals that seem to conflict are security and liberty. Clearly, there are significant conflicts between these two goals: the more security one desires from the government, the more liberty one must be willing to surrender. This dilemma and the solutions to it go back at least as far as Thomas Hobbes’s famous work of political theory, Leviathan, first published in 1651. Hobbes argues that people are naturally aggressive and that they want to acquire things for themselves: they will, therefore, in the “state of nature” (that is, the state of humankind without civil government), seek to deny those things to or take them from other people. Thus, people in the “state of nature” will fight with each other for wealth and power, and this constant striving will yield constant “war of man against man,” resulting in a society in which life is “solitary, nasty, brutish, and short.” To prevent this conflict,

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

Hobbes argues, all of us in civil society have surrendered a considerable number of our liberties to the state, which holds the most coercive power in our name to prevent us from engaging in this war against all. If we take Hobbes at his word, we might create an authoritarian or totalitarian system to protect ourselves from each other. Instead, the United States followed a path laid out by John Locke and extended by the founders of our Constitution, who believed that political power comes from our consent; thus, we surrender to the government or “leviathan” only those things that we believe government should manage to create and maintain a civil society. Under such a system, citizens retain considerable rights and privileges of citizenship until they have breached the laws of civil society, in which case individual liberties can be taken from the individual in order to make all of us more secure. The obvious example is criminals, who are largely free to act until they commit a crime, an affront to civil society, whereupon we restrict the liberties of criminals by imprisoning them, or, in extreme cases, by denying them life itself. The problem with this trade-off is that greater security for some or all of us comes at the expense of a loss of liberty to some or all of us. Let’s consider some contemporary examples. First, consider this: Would you be willing to surrender some of your rights—your Fifth Amendment right not to be forced to incriminate yourself or your Fourth Amendment right to “be secure in [your] persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures”—in exchange for more aggressive law enforcement against vandals, murderers, and drug dealers? Your decision may presume that the constitutional protections against unfair criminal procedure apply only to actual criminals, not suspects and certainly not private citizens. However, the founders believed that the protections contained in the first eight amendments protect all of us against a heavy-handed central government. Nearly every protection provided under the Bill of Rights has its historical roots in the colonial experience, when the British government routinely violated what we now call “due process of law.” Yet, at the same time, many people argue that criminals have too many “rights” and that the victims of crimes are afforded no constitutional rights. While one can reply that the Bill of Rights is at least as valuable as a set of restraints against government as it is a set of protections of “criminals” (actually, suspects), the niceties of political theory and constitutional law are not always observed in policy debates. And one can argue that crime is prosecuted by the state because crime is an offense against the entire community—the polis—and not against individuals. But the pain of crime is clearly most heavily borne by the victims. Now, let us imagine that the police search your house without a search warrant. Such a search is a violation of the Fourth Amendment that guarantees against warrantless searches. But what if the search yields evidence that you or someone in your house (a relative or a roommate, maybe) committed a crime? (Remember the case study from chapter 7 on “dropsy” evidence.) Then the evidence is what lawyers call “probative” in that it shows that the individual may have committed a crime for

235

236 Chapter 8 which he or she should be punished. In such a case, should the evidence be admitted at trial because it is proof of guilt? Or should it be excluded because it was seized in violation of your constitutional rights? What if excluding the evidence allows you to go free, even if the evidence very strongly suggests your guilt? These questions are not easily and definitely answered, because they are important political questions that both influence and reflect the nature of the political community involved and the nature of the information available to people when they make these decisions about liberty. For example, early in the year 2000, the economy was sound, unemployment was at historic lows, inflation was low compared with the high rates in the 1970s and early 1980s, and people were freely spending money on houses, cars, computers, and other accoutrements of the good life, twenty-firstcentury style. At the same time, crime was also at a historic low and drug-related crime in particular had been substantially reduced. In such an environment, people may be more willing to take risks and to seek greater liberty because they feel more secure. But when the economy is performing poorly, terrorism seems to continue unabated, and the future prosperity and quality of life are in doubt, people may find that their interests shift to greater security, as reflected in the case study that follows. Thus, there is no one answer to what the appropriate balance of these goals should be; rather, what is important to examine is the extent to which conflicts exist and how they are resolved. Ambiguity and Goal Conflict

policy goal. A desired outcome of a policy; these goals can be explicitly stated or implicit in the policy and other factors found in its legislative history.

Beyond the different ways of thinking about goals, policy design can also reveal conflict over policy goals. Because policies and their goals are often vague when they are originally established, it is sometimes difficult for the agencies charged with implementation to satisfy the demands of everyone involved in formulating and approving the broad policy. For example, Congress could mandate that the secretary of the Department of Health and Human Services create a program to reduce the teen pregnancy rate. The goal and how attainment is measured are clear: reduce the pregnancy rate. There may be other goals, such as reducing welfare dependency, increasing educational attainment, promoting morality, and other benefits that derive from this, but the main goal is to reduce the teen pregnancy rate. There are multiple ways to reduce teen pregnancies. Two commonly cited methods are to provide family planning services, particularly birth control, to teens, particularly teen girls, or to stress abstinence to teens through schools, public education campaigns, and the like. Clearly, the choice of one or the other of these methods to reach the goal will raise controversy. Some will argue that providing family planning services will encourage rather than discourage promiscuity and will result in more pregnancy and moral decay. Others may argue that abstinence relies too heavily on a mistaken causal theory; in particular, they would argue that appeals for abstinence would be ignored or even mocked by teens rather than thoughtfully and respectfully

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

237

Case Study: The USA Patriot Act and Airport Screening: Liberty versus Security In the heat of the moment after the September 11, 2001 terrorist attacks, and in the midst of the frightening anthrax attacks on Congress and on major media figures, the Congress quickly passed a law awkwardly titled the “Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism Act,” better known as the USA Patriot Act. President George W. Bush signed it into law on October 26, 2001. The goal of this act was to greatly increase government powers to fight terrorism and related crimes. The act consisted of ten Titles: TITLE I: Enhancing Domestic Security against Terrorism TITLE II: Enhanced Surveillance Procedures TITLE III: International Money Laundering Abatement and Anti-Terrorist Financing Act of 2001 TITLE IV: Protecting the Border TITLE V: Removing Obstacles to Investigating Terrorism TITLE VI: Providing for Victims of Terrorism, Public Safety Officers and Their Families TITLE VII: Increased Information Sharing for Critical Infrastructure Protection TITLE VIII: Strengthening the Criminal Laws against Terrorism TITLE IX: Improved Intelligence TITLE X: Miscellaneous It would be a mistake to argue that this law sprung from thin air after the September 11 attacks. Many of the provisions of the act were long known to be among conservative policy makers’ preferred policies. Many of the provisions of the Patriot Act were relatively noncontroversial, such as the money laundering aspects in Title III, or the support for victims in Title VI. The most controversial provisions were contained in Titles II and Title IX. In particular, Title II of the Patriot Act allows any federal district court to issue warrants for electronic surveillance outside of that court’s district, under Section 219. It allows the federal government to demand records of electronic communications from Internet service providers (ISPs; but not necessarily the contents of the messages themselves) under Section 215, and makes it illegal for any ISP or organization so ordered to disclose the fact of that request. A particularly important provision is found in Section 209, which allows for the seizure of voice mail with only a search warrant, rather than under the old rules, which required a wiretap order which is more difficult to get. Another extremely important section of the act is section 206, which allows the government to tap communications of suspects regardless of their location or of the device or instrument used in communication; this makes it easier for the government to collect information on those using e-mail and cell phones, particularly the prepaid cell phones popular with terrorists and criminals. The ultimate goal of the law is to provide government broader powers to fight terrorism. Operationally, the FBI focuses on gathering domestic intelligence. The CIA is empowered to direct FBI domestic surveillance operations for the first time, while the U.S. Treasury Department is required to establish a financial monitoring system that the CIA may access (much of which is contained in Title III). The CIA also now has the power to acquire evidence obtained by criminal (continued)

238 Chapter 8

Case Study (continued) wiretaps and federal grand juries (section 218).4 While many of these provisions were due to expire under various sunset provisions in the original Patriot Act, most of these sections—or the substantive policies contained in the policies—remain in force, having been extended by legislative action in 2005 (PL 109–177, USA Patriot Improvement and Reauthorization Act). Interestingly, this bill was overwhelmingly passed in the wake of the 2005 London bus and subway bombings.5 The main provisions that were not permanently extended were set to sunset on December 31, 2009; while Congress has enacted short-term extensions of the law, the long-term extension of these provisions has not been taken up by Congress, due in part to increasing political opposition to many Patriot Act provisions. This opposition is made possible by, one might argue, the amount time that has passed since the attacks. Critics of the Patriot Act argue that it erodes the liberties guaranteed under the Constitution, and that the law was made hastily in a climate of great fear. This view holds that the Patriot Act places security higher than liberty—the very freedoms that define America. While they believe that liberty and security involve a balancing act between these two goals, opponents of the Patriot Act maintain that it has gone too far toward promoting security at the expense of liberty. According to this position, the act is open to abuse by overly aggressive law enforcement and intelligence agencies. Despite these concerns, and because of the tenor of the times during which the law passed with an overwhelming vote by Congress (357–66 in the House, and 98 to 1 in the Senate), and with the strong backing of President Bush, the law has not been significantly altered since its enactment. An important architect of the Patriot Act, former U.S. Assistant Attorney General Viet Dinh, defended the Patriot Act on the grounds that it enhances liberty and security. Dinh states that “[s]ecurity is the means by which we achieve our fundamental freedoms.”6 Supporters of the Patriot Act believe that that the September 11 attacks so fundamentally changed our notions of national security that the government must take strong action at home to prevent an even more deadly attack, possibly one involving weapons of mass destruction such as nuclear, biological, or chemical weapons. And these supporters would concede that it may be more important to curtail some constitutional liberties so that the republic may survive. They often cite a famous 1810 letter from Thomas Jefferson to John B. Colvin of Maryland, in which Jefferson argued that “A strict observance of the written laws is doubtless one of the high duties of a good citizen, but it is not the highest. The laws of necessity, of self-preservation, of saving our country when in danger, are of higher obligation. To lose our country by a scrupulous adherence to written law, would be to lose the law itself, with life, liberty, property and all those who are enjoying them with us; thus absurdly sacrificing the end to the means.” Jefferson appears to argue in this passage that some restrictions on liberty are justified if they make the nation more secure. The controversy that the Patriot Act generates is not whether the United States should defend itself against terrorism. The controversy is whether the act goes so far in the name of security— whether it really promotes it or not—that the very liberties on which the nation was founded are undermined. The Patriot Act includes a wide variety of provisions to empower intelligence and law enforcement agencies to pursue suspected terrorists, which have sparked fierce controversy.

sunset provisions. The parts of laws that require that the law will expire unless the legislature explicitly renews the legislation.

(continued)

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

Case Study (continued) Under the act, the FBI and the U.S. Justice Department sent out letters to college and university officials requesting information on foreign students to compare it with information on suspected or known terrorists. Academics strongly objected, stating that it violated privacy laws.7 It requires various financial institutions, including money-services businesses, securities firms, broker dealers, mutual funds, credit card companies, and other types of financial institutions to both monitor suspicious transactions and to establish anti-money-laundering programs (Title III).8 And librarians and booksellers have complained strongly about Patriot Act provisions (in section 215) that appeared to allow intelligence agencies to monitor a person’s library borrowing and book buying,9 although it is unclear how many times this power has been used in an investigation.10 However, the expanded Patriot Act provisions were used to prosecute the biggest Las Vegas strip club owner and several local government officials in a sting operation for money-laundering and bribery, none of which had anything to do with terrorism.11 Indeed, it may well be that the September 11 attacks were an opportunity to advance long sought-after changes to the criminal law that enhanced governmental powers. Roger Pilon, vice president for legal affairs at the Cato Institute, the libertarian research group, claimed that “[The administration is] taking language off the shelf that’s been ready to go into any vehicle.”.12 This “coupling” of ideas with events is a staple of agenda setting and alternative selection in the public policy process.13 After some time had passed, and the implications of the hastily assembled and passed Patriot Act were considered, political opposition to the act from both the left and the right emerged. The House of Representatives very nearly repealed the library and book-buying provisions of the Patriot Act in 2004.14 And many cities and counties have passed resolutions indicating their opposition to portions of the law,15 such as the library provisions.16 Amid all the controversy over whether the Patriot Act erodes constitutional liberties, one must consider the most basic question: Does the Patriot Act make us more secure? In other words, has the act been successful in the war on terrorism? In a 2004 report, the U.S. Department of Justice argued that it “has charged 310 defendants with criminal offenses as a result of terrorism investigations since the attacks of September 11, 2001, and 179 of those defendants have already been convicted.” The department’s report argues that the Patriot Act has been central to these efforts, and that it is providing the necessary tools to prosecute terrorism without undue limitations on individual liberty. Indeed, the department argued that “Security and liberty are interrelated and mutually reinforcing, not conflicting, goals. Under the leadership of the President and the Attorney General, the Department of Justice has been, and remains, dedicated to using the USA Patriot Act in service of both aims.”17 Do you agree with Dinh and the justice department that the Patriot Act protects liberty by promoting security? In other words, do you agree that one need not sacrifice a great deal of liberty to gain a great deal of security? Or do you believe that the Patriot Act was a rapid reaction to a sudden shocking event that may, in the long run, erode liberty to achieve security? Do you agree with Jefferson’s claim that some restrictions on liberty may be necessary to preserve the republic and the remaining liberties that exist? Or do you agree more with Benjamin Franklin, who said: “Any society that would give up a little liberty to gain a little security will deserve neither and lose both”?

239

240 Chapter 8 heeded. Others might argue that the abstinence-only policy, while well intentioned, simply does not yield the outcomes the policy’s proponents believe it will.18 We might call this conflict an agreement on ends, but not on means. The reason for the agreement on the ends in the first place is due to contending groups’ interests in attaining their own goals. Socially conservative groups may see the reduction of teen pregnancies as meeting a moral goal, while liberal groups may view the same result as a step toward particular social goals. The goal of reducing teen pregnancy is used because both groups can agree to it while feeling that their own interests—either social or moral goals—are thereby promoted. The disagreement comes later, when the decision is implemented; that is, when an agency takes specific steps to lower teen pregnancy rates, such as distributing contraception or promoting abstinence. When the goals themselves are in dispute, or when Congress or other legislatures have specified the method for implementing a program, these post-enactment goal conflicts are less likely, because they would have been explicitly stated in the legislation or at least strongly embedded in the policy design. Nevertheless, because legislation is usually the product of compromise, sometimes the means are unspecified and the ends are fuzzy until the policy takes shape during the design phase. Some goals can conflict with other goals in other policy areas, as well. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann argue that one can claim that, because the United States has so many illegal aliens living within its borders, its immigration policies have failed. This is true if the goal is to control the number of immigrants entering the United States. What about other, perhaps more important goals? One example, Ingram and Mann argue, is the desire to maintain friendly relations with Mexico, the source of most of our illegal aliens. A crackdown on illegal immigration may create social, economic, and political problems in a nation whose cooperation we hope to cultivate. Another goal is to keep food prices down; many argue that illegal immigrants, because they accept lower wages for farm work that legal citizens choose not to do, help keep food prices low.19 Whether one agrees that these are important goals is less important than a realization that a policy can conflict externally with other policies. For example, sociologists Edward Laumann and David Knoke tell the story of an oil exploration executive who read in the Federal Register that the Federal Aviation Administration (FAA) was proposing to require pilots of small airplanes to file flight plans for nearly all flights, regardless of the flight’s length or whether the pilot planned to fly visually or on instruments. While the goal here was to promote and improve aviation safety, the oil executive opposed the new rule because it could reveal where aircraft owned by oil companies fly when they do aerial surveys of potentially oil- and gas-rich areas. Thus, the goal of encouraging the development of our energy resources was hindered by an entirely unrelated program and goal.20 The point of this review of goals is not to lead you to believe that all policy is hopelessly complex or that goals are never set and attempted. Rather, my aim is to simply highlight how difficult it is to set and reach goals in a complex policy envi-

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

241

ronment. Often, once conflicts are resolved and the means for achieving goals are developed, one is able, through a review of the record surrounding the enactment of a policy, to isolate the important goal or goals and assess the extent to which they are met or believed to have been met. This is sometimes difficult when many other activities are taking place simultaneously. Adding to the complexity of goals is the fact that there are different types of goals. One must ask a series of questions about goals to fully understand what the policy is intended to achieve. One must ask whether the goal is to eliminate a problem, hold steady in the face of a growing problem, or reduce a problem to some better level. For example, the Clean Water Act’s goal that the nation’s waters be “drinkable, swimmable and fishable by 1985” seeks not to eliminate all pollution, but rather the level of pollution that renders our waters unusable for these purposes. Similarly, national economic policy makers tend not to believe they can get rid of unemployment entirely, but they do work to bring down the level of unemployment to 4 percent, the goal specified in the Full Employment and Balanced Growth Act of 1978, also known as the Humphrey-Hawkins Act after its sponsors.21 On the other hand, in 1995 the FAA and the NTSB announced their goal of zero fatal accidents in American commercial aviation; this is an absolute goal to eliminate deaths from air disasters. The type of goal may reveal a great deal about what the policy designers believe is possible to do given current techniques for solving or alleviating problems. Proper Causal Theory If the participants in policy making can at least approximate goal consensus, then the next thing they must do is understand the causal theory that underlies the policy to be implemented. A causal theory is a theory about what causes the problem and what intervention (i.e., what policy response to the problem) would alleviate that problem. Without good causal theory, it is unlikely that a policy design will be able to deliver the desired outcomes. Rather, performance measurement will remain focused on effort, because implementers and researchers will find the connection between effort and outcome so difficult to make. If the laws made by the legislature are vague or if the legislature defers to the expertise of agency officials, then developing the best causal theory and then settling on the policy design are the responsibility of the agency staff. But if Congress specifies a particular solution or set of solutions to a problem, then the causal theory is implicit in the legislation. For example, after the Exxon Valdez oil spill in 1990, Congress passed the Oil Pollution Act of 1990, which contained two key provisions: a requirement that oil tankers have double hulls by a certain date and an increase in the monetary liability limit for ship owners whose tankers spill oil. The explicit theories here are, first, that single-hull tankers leak more oil than double-hull tankers and, second, that an increase in liability will deter companies from recklessly moving oil in U.S. waters.

causal theory. A theory about what causes a problem and how particular responses would alleviate that problem.

242 Chapter 8 Because social problems are very complex, it is not surprising that developing causal theories about how the social world works is very difficult. If one develops the wrong causal theory, no policy, no matter how well crafted, is likely to have a positive impact on the problem under consideration. Deborah Stone has found the issue of causes so important that she devotes an entire chapter of Policy Paradox and an article in Political Science Quarterly to this element of policy making.22 You may have correctly guessed that Stone finds that isolating the causes of problems is much more complex than opposing camps might believe at first glance. After all, as Stone argues, we can distinguish between cause and effect in the natural world and in the social world: “The natural world is the realm of fate and accident, and we believe we have an adequate understanding of causation when we can describe the sequence of events by which one thing leads to another.”23 On the other hand, “in the social world we understand events to be the result of will, usually human but perhaps animal. The social world is the realm of control and intent. We usually think we have an adequate understanding of causation when we can identify the purposes or motives of a person or group and link those purposes to their actions” (p. 189). Because of these different ways of understanding causation, Stone argues, we can do things to change the outcomes of human, purposive action, while few interventions will change natural phenomena such as the weather, tides, or earthquakes. Thus, an important way of understanding how people argue about causes is to look at whether they attribute a problem to an act of God or to acts of human causation, either purposive or negligent. For example, one can argue that when a hurricane damages a city, it is an act of God that we cannot avoid and we should simply feel compassion for victims, give aid to recover from the disaster, and move on. Another view is that hurricanes (or earthquakes, or floods, or other disasters, for that matter) do not cause anything but high winds, heavy rains, too much water, or shaking ground. It is the presence of human activity and the consequence of human activities that cause the damages, such as building houses too close to rivers or beaches or in such a way that they do not stand up to shaking ground or high winds. The choice to build in such places and in such ways is a human decision that can be altered by changing policy to induce “better” decisions that help reduce the damage from such events. Stone argues that we can take this analysis further and, considering actions and consequences, identify four types of causal theories, as discussed in chapter 6 and as shown in Table 6.1 on page 190. This chart helps us to understand how groups compete in telling causal stories about policy problems. These stories include depictions of intended and unintended consequences. For example, environmental groups often portray environmental disasters—chemical leaks, oil spills, or leaking toxic waste dumps—as the result of carelessness (corner cutting, perhaps) or omission (failure to perform a task that would prevent an accident). The owner of the industrial facility in question will attempt to move the discussion from the realm of

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

243

inadvertence, which implies liability and carelessness, to a causal theory implying that the accident was caused by weather or a completely unforeseeable event that Stone calls “machines that run amok.” This move between explanations is important because the causal theory strongly implies the appropriate actions that government and society might take and that may be codified in public policy. A causal theory that a problem is caused by carelessness and omission means that policies are likely to be adopted that more strictly regulate the activities in question, to prevent or at least penalize these actions. But a causal theory that undesirable effects are caused by accidents implies a much different set of policies, which may emphasize self-regulation over governmental action, particularly if one can make the claim that accidents are random, without any pattern that is somehow caused or worsened by the industry’s action or inaction. In these ways and others, debates over policy are debates over causes and effects, with each side trying to tell a story that leads to its own most desired result. These causal theories also imply what sorts of policy tools will be used to address the problems. Policy Tools Closely related to the causal theory is the choice of policy tools, or policy instruments, which can be used to create a desired outcome. Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram define policy tools as “elements in policy design that cause agents or targets to do something they would not do otherwise or with the intention of modifying behavior to solve public problems or attain policy goals.”24 James Anderson calls policy instruments or tools “techniques of control” that are “by one means or another, overtly or subtly, . . . designed to cause people to do things, refrain from doing things, or continue doing things that they would otherwise not do.”25 Lester Salamon and Michael Lund provide a particularly simple and useful definition of a policy tool as “a method through which government seeks a policy objective.”26 Types of Policy Tools We create categories of tools because while there are many different government policies, there should be relatively few types of tools used to achieve the goals set out in policy.27 We can then learn more about how government works to achieve its goals by carefully thinking about the broad types of tools and how government uses them to achieve certain ends. Thinking about the tools of government is important because, according to Salamon, the nature of the world and the nature of government have changed. Salamon notes that in recent years there has developed “a set of theories that portrays government agencies as tightly structured hierarchies insulated from market forces and from effective citizen pressure and therefore free to serve the personal and institutional interests of bureaucrats instead.”28 Salamon continues that governments

policy tool. According to Lester Salamon and Michael Lund, “a method through which government seeks a policy objective.”

244 Chapter 8 have already begun to restructure to take into account the reform theories intended to make government more nimble and responsive to modern needs. As a result of this restructuring, a massive proliferation has occurred in the tools of public action, in the instruments or means used to address public problems. Whereas earlier government activity was largely restricted to the direct delivery of goods or services by government bureaucrats, it now embraces a dizzying array of loans, loan guarantees, grants, contracts, social regulation, economic regulation, insurance, tax expenditures, vouchers, and more.29

The balance of Salamon’s edited volume is a rich and nearly exhaustive discussion of all these tools. The challenge for the student of public policy is to understand what these tools are, the assumptions underlying how they work, and, in particular, how we might categorize these tools. Thinking about tools is particularly useful because, as Salamon and Lund argue, there are “central characteristics” of tools that distinguish some tools from others. The key would then be to find the central characteristic of the various tools. One can do so by looking at four dimensions of tools. The first is “the nature of the activity in which government is engaged.” Examining this dimension gives us a general sense of what it is that the government is doing to achieve a goal. There are, say Salamon and Lund, four broad categories of such activities: “outright money payments . . . provision of goods and services, including information . . . legal protections, such as monopolies or guarantees . . . [and] restrictions/penalties,” such as regulation or criminal laws. The next dimension is the “structure of the delivery system.” The delivery system reflects the extent to which implementation is likely to be more or less complex. Salamon and Lund broadly categorize delivery systems as “direct” and “indirect.” Direct service delivery involves systems in which the federal government is the sole actor in the delivery of a service. Salamon and Lund cite Social Security as one such example; others would be air traffic control, provided by the FAA, and regulation of broadcasting through the Federal Communications Commission. Indirect service provision involves the delivery of service through an intermediary, such as another level of government, or a private actor, such as a business or nonprofit agency. Examples of these types of programs include Community Development Block Grant programs, which go to local governments, loan guarantees, which are given to banks to encourage lending at lower rates or to riskier borrowers, and research grants, which are given to nonprofit universities or research institutes. Related to but not exactly the same as the structure of the delivery system is what Salamon and Lund call the “degree of centralization.” In general, we can be fairly certain that the more directly service is provided, the more the administration of the program is centralized. The management of Social Security is centralized in Washington because the federal government, without the assistance or participation of intermediaries, directly administers it. However, some federally provided services

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

are also relatively decentralized. For example, the activities of the U.S. National Park Service (a unit of the Department of the Interior) and the Forest Service (a unit of the Department of Agriculture) are managed both by central offices in Washington and by expert staff in the field, who have some managerial and programmatic latitude because they need to respond effectively to local conditions. Finally, Salamon and Lund describe the “degree of automaticity” of a policy tool, or, in other words, “the degree to which [programs] require detailed administrative action.” Tax incentives, they argue, are largely self-executing because individuals will seek them out, thereby promoting the goals of the policy. The mortgage tax deduction is a virtually effortless way for the government to promote home ownership, because homeowners know that they can take the deduction and actively wish to do so. On the other hand, welfare programs that rely on a determination of eligibility “require almost case-by-case administrative decision making” that requires a substantial degree of management effort. Other Categories of Policy Tools Salamon and Lund provide a particularly well-developed system of thinking about policy tools, but many other scholars have also sought useful tool typologies. Howlett and Ramesh provide two broad categories of policy tools: “economic models” and “political models.”30 Economic models of policy tools focus on individual freedom, initiative, and choice, therefore tending to value noncoercive tools over those that are more coercive. Howlett and Ramesh do note, however, that welfare economists, whose focus is on overall societal well-being rather than the aggregation of individual well-being (the focus of neoclassical economists), do acknowledge the need for more coercive tools (such as an income tax) to correct some of the flaws of laissez-faire economics. In both cases, however, economists look at the selection of a policy tool as a positive, technical question in which the problem to be solved, the agent to solve it (government, private sector, or some combination), and the nature of the tools themselves are matched with each other to find the best possible solution to a problem. By contrast, those who look at policy tool choice from a more political perspective tend to follow this precept: “Any instrument [or tool] can theoretically accomplish any chosen aim, but governments prefer less coercive instruments unless forced by either recalcitrance on the part of the subject and/or continued social pressure for change to utilize more coercive instruments.”31 Clearly this is not merely a technical matter: If the selection of how to deal with a problem is at least partially a function of societal pressures to favor one policy tool or another, then “politics” is involved not only in the understanding of the problem but also in the ways we choose to solve it. For example, the decision to treat as adults young people who commit violent crimes, thereby leading to much more stringent sentences, is not a technical decision based on an economic and criminological analysis of these

245

246 Chapter 8 crimes and their perpetrators. Rather, it is a response to a society that seeks to “get tough on crime.” Still, there are important shortcomings to thinking about instruments from a solely politically perspective. First, as Howlett and Ramesh note explicitly, the matter of substitutability of one tool for another is not so simple, because political systems are constrained in their choice of tools, both ideologically and legally. On the legal side, for example, federal policy making on any number of issues, most notably civil rights, is predicated on the notion that government could regulate a wide range of activities under the commerce clause of the Constitution. These efforts have historically been successful; so successful, in fact, that Congress, in passing federal legislation making it a federal offense to have a gun within 1,000 yards of a school, justified its action in terms of the commerce clause, saying that school violence hinders interstate commerce. The Supreme Court, however, disagreed, noting that the connection between the goal and the commerce clause was so tenuous that the law was unconstitutional on federalism grounds.32 It is unclear whether this case went beyond the Court’s sense of the appropriate application of the commerce clause, or if this signals a new era of legal doctrine surrounding the clause. In any case, this is an obvious constraint on various policy tools. A potential problem with the economic way of thinking is that economics often makes too many assumptions about what is possible in policy making, on two levels. First, it assumes we really know what the problem is. In the give-and-take of policy making, an agreement to do something about a problem is often easier to achieve than an agreement on what precisely has to be done. This challenge is faced by those who write regulations and seek to implement government policies without creating controversy and disagreement over the means to the ends specified by the policy makers. Second, the economic perspective assumes that we have reasonably reliable information on how policy tools work. As with much of politics and policy making, it is very hard to know the causal connections in any policy system. While we may start with a causal theory, these theories are often flawed. Given these two ways of thinking about tools, let us turn to a discussion of some of the current ways policy scholars categorize tools, as summarized in Table 8.2 on pp. 248–50. I have sought to show where the names and concepts overlap, but, as you can see in Table 8.2, there are many different terms, from the more general to the more specific, that we can use to arrange policy tools. Perhaps the most useful way to think about tools is the extent to which they are coercive or noncoercive. The more coercive a policy, the more likely compliance with the policy can be achieved, but the more likely it is that considerable resources will have to be devoted to providing the coercion needed to create compliance. Noncoercive policies like incentives and hortatory policies are much easier to administer by virtue of their design and of the assumptions we make about how people will behave, but the likelihood of success is highly variable. In the end, while the categories of tools are useful descriptors of the types of tools

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

that one can use to achieve a set of goals, they do not tell us much about the relative strengths and weaknesses of these techniques. Levine, Peters, and Thompson provide a scheme for assessing the strengths and weaknesses of each tool.33 They acknowledge the tentative nature of these criteria, given what we know and do not know about how government works, but they are helpful in thinking about what tools might be best for particular goals. The scheme of Levine and colleagues is adapted and shown in Table 8.3 on p. 251. Tools and Choices in Policy Design Policy designers must consider a number of elements when selecting a policy tool. One of these elements is political feasibility. Because policy making is at least as much a political process as it is a technical process, even technically superior policy tools may not be adopted because they are politically unpopular. For example, the United States has an all-volunteer military and relies heavily on the military reserves for personnel, such as during the wars in Iraq and Afghanistan. An allvolunteer military is a more politically feasible way of meeting personnel needs than the draft, which was very controversial during the Vietnam War and would be very controversial today, given Americans’ historic opposition to conscription. Other countries with different needs and political cultures, such as Israel, require compulsory military service; clearly, the political and security dynamics in Israel are different from those in the United States. A second factor in the policy tool choice is the resources available to implement policy. For example, there may be two ways to battle the problem of forest fires: post thousands of lookouts and firefighters in the forests or employ a public education program to tell people that only they can prevent forest fires. Smokey the Bear is the well known symbol of fire prevention efforts. The U.S. Forest Service slogan is now “only you can prevent wildfires” to address the broader fire hazard.

...

r be

em

On

ly

em

R

Pr

ev

en

t

yo

u

rest

fi Wild

Courtesy of the USDA Forest Service, Fire & Aviation Management

247

Law and regulation

Direct provision of services or goods

Transfer payments

Law

Services

Money

Contracting out

Intergovernmental grants

Levine, Peters, Thompson

Peters Authority tools

Schneider and Ingram

Types of Policy Tools or Instruments

Table 8.2

Description

Market and proprietary operations

Government activities that have private counterparts, and that have economic and policy consequences.

Public corporations such as Tennessee Valley Authority (electrical power generation), market activities of the Federal Reserve Bank (interest rate setting, buying, and selling securities to influence the market.)

General spending done by the government Personnel costs, supplies, every day on the people, goods, and services utilities, etc. (Government it needs to function. spending on these items has a substantial national and local economic effect.)

General Expenditures

Contracts to run prisons, hospitals; contracts to supply complex goods to government, such as military equipment, computers, space vehicles.

Social Security, food stamps, veterans’ benefits.

Postal services, air traffic control, weather forecasting.

Contracts with private firms to provide goods or services.

“Transfer” of money from government to various interests.

Services provided directly by the government to users.

Criminal law, environmental regulations, anti-trust law.

Examples

Contracts

Benefits

Services

Directive power Pronouncements of policy that carry the force of law; that is, they compel particular behaviors and compliance.

Anderson

248

The tax system (tax expenditures)

Suasion

Insurance

Other Loans and loan economic guarantees instruments

Taxes

Capacitybuilding tools

Inducements and sanctions

Hortatory tools

Sanctions

Payments to ensure the economic viability of an activity, particularly when that activity addresses some broader goals.

Subsidies

“Training, technical assistance, education, and information needed to take policy relevant actions” (Peters) and empower other agencies.

Tools that induce “‘quasi-voluntary or quasicoerced’ actions based on tangible payoffs” (Schneider and Ingram).

Attempts to persuade people to engage in desirable behaviors or to avoid engaging in undesirable behaviors.

Provision of insurance where it is not gener� ally available in the private insurance market.

Loans to induce economic activity or other desirable activity.

Policies intended to alter behavior by making some activities more or less economically desirable.

Loans

Taxes

(continued)

Technology transfer, training, the provision of information products to local government; cash transfers to hire more staff.

Fines for violating regulations; bonus payments for timely completion of contracts.

Public campaigns to discourage smoking or drinking, antidrug campaigns, pro-exercise campaigns.

Flood insurance, federal deposit insurance.

Farm subsidies; subsidies to sports franchises; subsidies to business to locate in particular communities.

Small Business Administration (SBA) loans, student loans.

Tax credits (such as for student loan interest), tax deductions (mortgage tax deduction, medical expenses), taxes on tobacco and alcohol, called “sin taxes,” to raise revenue and discourage consumption. Tax policies to encourage economic development in particular areas, such as Urban Enterprise Zones.

249

Levine, Peters, Thompson Learning tools

Schneider and Ingram

Examples

Procedures not specified in law or regulation to resolve problems.

Informal procedures

Exchange of correspondence between taxpayers and IRS to resolve disputes; plea-bargaining in criminal process.

Government authority to engage in an activity Driver’s licenses, professional that is prohibited without such a license. licensing (physicians, lawyers, engineers, and the like). Licensing of hospitals, permits, corporate charters (Anderson).

Tools to help understand the relevant aspects Focus groups, opinion polls, of policy problems. censuses, basic and applied research [for example, National Institutes of Health (NIH), National Science Foundation (NSF)].

Description

Licensing

Inspection

Anderson

Sources: B. Guy Peters, American Public Policy: Promise and Performance (Chappaqua, NY: Chatham House/Seven Rivers, 1999), pp. 6–13; Charles H. Levine, B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson, Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences (Glenview, IL.: Scott, Foresman/Little Brown, 1990), pp. 64–73; Anne Larason Schneider and Helen Ingram, Policy Design for Democracy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997), pp. 93–97; James E. Anderson, Public Policymaking, 4th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2000), pp. 233–44.

Peters

Table 8.2 (continued)

250

Certainty

— — + —

— — —

+ —

+

+ + —

+

+ — +

— —

+ — — + — + — — — — — + —

Ease with which the tool can be altered to changing needs and circumstances.

Effectiveness Flexibility Extent to which the tool is likely to achieve its goals.



Efficiency Extent to which the tool creates maximum outputs for a given input.

Less Cost Expense of the tool.

Timeliness Extent to which the tool works quickly.

+

Certainty of the administrative process and the compliance of targets.

Visibility

+



+ — — —

+

The extent to which the program is well known or less well known (sometimes invisibility is an important goal). +

— — —

— + — + — — —

+

+

+ + + — + + +



Degree of citizen choice afforded by the policy.

Accountability Choice Extent to which implementers are accountable for their actions.

Source: From Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences by Charles H. Levine, B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson. Reprinted by permission of Addison-Wesley Educational Publishers, Inc. Note: Plus signs indicate the presence of an attribute; minus signs indicate the absence of that attribute.

Direct service provision Transfers Grants Tax expenditures Regulations Loans Insurance Contracts Licensing Informal procedures Capacity building Inducements Sanctions Hortatory tools

Explanation

Characteristics of Policy Instruments

Table 8.3

251

252 Chapter 8 The U.S. Forest Service emphasizes the hortatory tool—educating the public about fires—because it is much less expensive than more aggressive efforts to detect and prevent fires caused by carelessness. Of course, the public education campaign may not be fully effective in addressing the forest fire risk, and many fires are still started by carelessness, but this campaign and others, such as encouraging people to stop smoking and to wear seat belts, was successful in inducing behavioral change among a large enough proportion of the population to justify its costs. Such campaigns can also become problematic in the face of newer science. We now know that occasional fires are necessary for the forest ecosystem, that routine fire actually burns accumulated fuel—dead wood—without damaging live trees, and aggressive fire suppression techniques can often make more fuel accumulate, thereby making big fires worse. This is the persistent danger of public education tools—the difficulties involved in altering public behavior or attitudes when new information becomes available. The resource question actually falls within a broader category Salamon and Lund call “administrative feasibility,” or “the degree of ease or difficulty involved in establishing and operating a program.”34 Clearly, operating any public program is likely to be much more difficult if adequate resources are lacking. A third element of policy tool choice is based on the behavioral assumptions about the target populations. Policy targets are the entities—people or organizations—whose behavior the policy seeks to alter. The choice of the policy tool is a function of the assumed behavior of the policy target. The choice of a coercive tool reveals something about the assumed behavior of the targets that the choice of a set of incentives would not. This link between the policy target and the policy tool falls under a broader category that Salamon and Lund call “effectiveness,” which can be assessed on two levels: the “supply effectiveness” of the program in providing a necessary level of output to induce changes in the target population, and the “targeting effectiveness” of the program in altering policy targets’ behaviors. This discussion tends to suggest that policy tools are sometimes used in isolation. Yet there is nothing to suggest that multiple policy tools are not used, and, indeed, it is often true that multiple policy tools are used to address a problem. For example, in drug policy, we have stiffened punishment for drug dealing, have attempted to seize drugs before they enter the country, and experimented with public education programs, such as the Just Say No campaign, the DARE program, and current efforts by the Partnership for a Drug-Free America to promote better parental knowledge of what their kids are doing and with whom they are socializing. The tendency to “bundle” policy tools into packages of tools that are all intended to achieve similar goals is noted in recent research, which shows that certain types of local economic development tools are likely to be bundled into an overall strategy.35

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

Decisions Once a tool or set of policy tools has been narrowed down, policy makers need to decide which policy tool or set of tools to use—someone or some institution in the policy process has to make a decision. Decisions can be about matters as complex as President Kennedy’s decision, in 1961, that the United States should send an astronaut to the moon and back by 1970. Or they can be as simple as the decision by a police officer to give a motorist a warning rather than a speeding ticket. The decision not to do something is as important as the decision to do something, and a nondecision is also a policy output. In the moon flight example, a considerable amount of momentum had built behind the space program for various reasons, so the decision to not go to the moon, or to mount a more modest space program, would have had a profound influence on future developments in aerospace.36 At about the same time, the decision to not pursue the supersonic transport (SST) airplane program in the late 1960s had profound influence on the aviation and aerospace industries. Our historical decisions not to create a system of national health insurance (something that the Obama administration’s health care reforms do not do) have as profound an effect on our national health system as would a decision to create such a system. Indeed, our constitutional system is structured in a way that often prevents decisions from being made. The numerous points that bills must pass before they become laws, that proposed regulations must pass before they become actual regulations, and that laws must pass before they are effectively implemented make any sort of final and authoritative decision very difficult to reach. Thus, when analyzing policies, it is as important to specify what has not been done as it is to specify what has been done. In this section, I briefly explain some key concepts in the study of how decisions are made about what to do, once the decision has been reached that something is to be done. While public policy is as much about what government chooses not to do as it is about what government actually does, for illustrative purposes I will focus primarily on how decisions to do something are reached. And, as is true throughout this book, when I discuss Congress or the presidency, we can apply same ideas to the state legislatures and governors. For simplicity’s sake, we can say that the decision-making process begins after an issue or problem is placed on the agenda and makes its way through the legislative process until it comes close to the decision agenda. The decision agenda is that relatively small collection of things about which an organization must make decisions. In Congress’s case, the process usually begins by winnowing down a set of alternatives that are, for the most part, debated and formulated in the committees. The goal is to link potential problems to potential solutions. Many of the models of decision making presented here are both positive models (that is, neutral explanations of how a system works) and normative models

253

254 Chapter 8 (explanations of how decisions should be made). I will not delve deeply into the normative dimensions of these issues; that is, I will not spend much time on whether the rational comprehensive decision-making model is superior or should be used in making governmental decisions. This is a task for you, the reader, to decide as you weigh the relative merits of these perspectives both as normative models and as reasonable models of how the policy process works. What’s more, like so much in public policy studies, it is difficult to argue that any model or perspective holds true across all time and circumstances. Rational Comprehensive Decision Making rational comprehensive decision making. A model of decision making in which it is assumed that decision makers have nearly all information about a problem, its causes, and its solutions at their disposal, whereupon a large number of alternatives can be weighted and the best one selected. Contrast with incrementalism and bounded rationality.

Most discussions of decision making begin with a discussion of the “rational comprehensive” or “rational actor” as an ideal type of decision making that is rarely, if ever, achieved.37 Yet for years the rational actor model was widely assumed to be a primary method of decision making in public and private organizations, and the quest for this sort of rationality persists today. After all, wouldn’t it be best if all our decisions were made rationally, based on the best information we have available? There are several assumptions that underlie the rational model.38 Decision makers are presented with a problem and a goal (involving solving or ameliorating the problem) and are set to the task of solving or addressing, to the extent possible, the problem. In so doing, decision makers gather all the possible information they can on the problem—its societal and economic costs, for example—and on possible solutions to the problem. Multiple options are analyzed, including the option to take no action at all. The goal, Dye argues, is to achieve “maximum social gain” through the agreed-upon policy. This model is often set up as a straw man against which other models of decision making are compared; an example of this straw man is Model I (the rational actor model) in Graham Allison’s Essence of Decision.39 The reason why the ideal rational model is a straw man is simple: several features of the rational model render it an unrealistic model of decision making. First is the problem of goal consensus. Often, when a problem is identified, it is hard to understand what goals the various proponents of policies have in mind. Often, goals are left purposefully ambiguous so that legislation can gain passage; it is then left to the implementers to try to figure out what the most important goals are. Because solutions are so often tied to goals, some solutions to a problem will foster political conflict, even if the solution seems the most “rational.” For example, liberals might see welfare as a form of societal compassion to help less fortunate people overcome the conditions that lead to poverty. Conservatives, on the other hand, may view welfare as a temporary boost to help people while they look for employment; the conservatives’ support is based more on economics than compassion. Thus, the same problem can be seen as having two rather different goals. Another problem with the rational model is that the information-processing

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

demands are too great for human minds in human institutions. It is impossible to gather all the information about a particular problem; one could spend a lifetime and not find a final answer. Even with today’s vastly improved information storage and retrieval systems, it is very difficult for decision makers, confronted as they are with significant resource constraints and time pressure, to gather all the information needed, weigh the information, and make a decision. An additional problem with attempts at highly rational decision making comes with the nature of information itself. Because decision makers deal with social phenomena, and social phenomena are notoriously difficult to track and analyze, it is difficult to find the proper information about goals, values, costs, and benefits needed to make a rational decision. This is one of the key criticisms of cost-benefit analysis (CBA). In CBA, the analyst tries to count up, often in monetary terms, the cost of pursuing a certain policy and the benefits to be derived from it. The problem is that the costs of an action are sometimes easier to count up than are the benefits. For example, we might know that the cost of cleaning up a toxic waste site is $50 million, and the result is that we might reduce the rate of cancers and other illnesses by somewhere between 2 and 10 percent. What is the benefit, in dollar terms, of this reduction? How can we make this reduction more certain? This depends on our calculation of how much each life is worth, which is very difficult to calculate. Again, this does not mean we should not try to use CBA. And, as Dye makes quite clear, we should not forget that rational analysis is also about values and preferences, not simply about dollar costs and benefits.40 Many of the critiques of the rational actor model suggest that rationality is so difficult, or nearly impossible, that other models of decision making are more accurate. But it is important to keep rationality in mind as, at least, a goal, if not the realistic end. After all, if complete rationality were possible—that is, if we had complete (or very nearly complete) access to all relevant information and that information was adequate—we would be able to make better decisions. This is why people continue to develop information systems and analytic techniques: to move us toward improved, more rational decision making. Bounded Rationality and Incrementalism James March and Herbert Simon provide us with a way of thinking about rationality that recognizes the limits on resources and human abilities to process information. This concept is called bounded rationality.41 To be boundedly rational means that one behaves as rationally as one can within certain bounds or limits, including limited time, limited information, and our limited human ability to recognize every feature and pattern of every problem; we can try to enhance these skills, but they are still inherently limited. Charles Lindblom applied these ideas in a now-classic article, “The Science of ‘Muddling Through,’” which appeared in Public Administration Review in 1959.42 In

255

cost-benefit analysis. Sometimes called cost-benefitrisk analysis, a technique of policy analysis that seeks to understand the costs of a course of action and its benefits. When risk is introduced, the risk of something bad happening is also taken into account.

bounded rationality. A term, used most prominently by James March and Herbert Simon, that describes how decision makers seek to act as rationally as possible within certain bounds or limits; these limits include limited time, limited information, and our limited human ability to recognize every feature and pattern of every problem.

256 Chapter 8 incrementalism. A model of decision making in which policy change is accomplished through small, incremental steps that allow decision makers to adjust policies as they learn from their successes and failures.

this article, Lindblom argued that people make decisions in relatively small increments, rather than in big leaps. They do so because key sources of information include what we know about the current nature of an existing problem, our accumulated knowledge about what steps have been taken before, if any, to address the problem, and whether those steps appeared to be successes or failures. This description of the policy process, known as incrementalism, is both a model of how decisions are made and a description of how contending interests behave in making policy. (Table 8.4). Lindblom calls the rational comprehensive method of decision making the “root” method, because decisions start from the “root” of the issue or problem; incrementalism is the “branch,” he argues, because it uses and builds on what is already known, without relying on reanalyzing everything about what is currently being done. In this way, the incremental method allows the decision maker to take a fair number of shortcuts: it eliminates the need to explicitly separate means from ends, to pick the analytically “best” policy, and to rely heavily on theories that the decision maker may have neither the time nor the inclination to use. Two major problems with the theory (and to some extent the practice) of incrementalism are, first, that some problems demand bold decisions and, second, that some goals simply cannot be met with incremental steps. For example, President Franklin Roosevelt was elected on a pledge to tackle the grave social and economic problems associated with the Great Depression. His flurry of activity—the banking holiday, new banking and finance laws, the promotion of various measures such as the National Industrial Recovery Act—was a rather sharp departure from prior governmental practice. These innovations were occasioned, in large part, by the public’s demand that the government do something; the gravity of the Depression was such that aggressive measures needed to be adopted. A second example starts with President Kennedy’s address to Congress in 1961, in which he urged that the United States put an astronaut on the moon and safely return him to Earth before 1970. Paul Schulman calls this a “major national commitment,” and the federal government, after some years of organizational and political confusion, responded to Kennedy’s challenge by appropriating money and causing the rapid growth of the National Aeronautics and Space Administration (NASA) and other agencies to meet the goal.43 Because this task—putting someone on the moon—was undertaken even before the first American astronaut had simply orbited the earth, the space program serves as an example of a nonincremental, all-ornothing decision. While the landing on the moon might have resulted from a more incrementalist space policy, it is likely that it would have taken longer and would have been achieved rather differently than it was. Another example of sudden, nonincremental policy is the decision to mobilize for all-out war. Before the United States was drawn into World War II, it pursued an incremental policy of pressure on Japan to halt its expansionism and on Germany to protect shipments of war material to Great Britain. When Japan attacked Pearl Harbor in December 1941, and Germany and Italy declared war, the United States had to move

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

257

Table 8.4 Rational Comprehensive Decision Making and Bounded Rationality (incremental decision making) Rational comprehensive

Bounded rationality

1a. Clarification of values or objectives distinct 1b. Selection of value goals and empirical analysis of the needed from and usually prerequisite to empirical action are not distinct from one another but are closely intertwined. analysis of alternative policies. 2a. Policy formulation is therefore approached 2b. Since means and ends are not distinct, means-end analysis is through means-end analysis: First the ends often inappropriate or limited. are isolated, then the means to achieve them are sought. 3a. The gist of a “good” policy is that it can be 3b. The test of a “good” policy is typically that various analysts find shown to be the most appropriate means to themselves directly agreeing on a policy (without their agreeing that desired ends. it is the most appropriate means to an agreed objective). 4a. Analysis is comprehensive; every 4b. Analysis is drastically limited: (i) Important possible outcomes important relevant factor is taken into account. are neglected; (ii) Important alternative potential policies are neglected; (iii) Important affected values are neglected. 5a. Theory is often heavily relied upon.

5b. A succession of comparisons greatly reduces or eliminates reliance on theory.

Source: Reprinted with permission from Public Administration Review. Copyright © by the American Society for Public Administration (ASPA), 1120 G Street NW, Suite 700, Washington, DC 20005. All rights reserved.

from incrementalist economic and diplomatic policies to a very sudden commitment to build a large military to win a two-front war. Of course, some military commitments are incremental, such as the slowly building American involvement in Vietnam in the 1960s, followed by the slow disengagement from Vietnam in the early 1970s. Other Models of Decision Making The rational comprehensive and incrementalist models of decision making are perhaps the two most commonly reviewed models in public policy, but other models, borrowing from these and other theories, help explain how decisions are made. Michael Cohen, James March, and Johan Olsen developed the garbage can model to explain decision making in what they call “organized anarchies.”44 They use universities as an example of organized anarchies because, as you may have noticed while at a college or university, institutions of higher learning are not rigidly organized and managed institutions. Indeed, members of the faculty demand and usually receive considerable autonomy in the management of their own work and of their departments. Students enjoy a degree of autonomy in their choices of which courses and majors to take, how to structure living arrangements, and what to do during free time. And administrators must manage the various interests—faculty, alumni, students, and members of the broader community—without violating the traditional prerogatives of any of these groups.

258 Chapter 8 There are three elements or streams in the garbage can model: problems, solutions, and participants. In each of these streams, various elements of decision making float about; what is perhaps most important about this model is the idea that there are solutions looking for problems as much as vice versa, and participants floating about looking for a way to participate in putting together these problems and solutions. Cohen, March, and Olsen call the decision opportunities “garbage cans” in which the three streams are mixed together. For example, the selection of a new dean is an opportunity for participants to come together in a garbage can and use the hiring to link perceived problems in the college with perceived solutions. It is important to note that this is not a model in which a problem is identified, followed by people going out to develop or invent solutions and bring them back. Rather, many solutions already exist, and the role of participants is to advance their solution to a problem, even when it seems that they are simply carrying a solution in search of a problem. For example, Secretary of Housing and Urban Development Jack Kemp, in the George H.W. Bush administration, strongly suggested that urban enterprise zones (UEZs)—zones in which tax laws and other regulations are relaxed to encourage development—be created in cities to provide jobs while slowing urban decay. Kemp promoted other ideas for public housing and job creation as well. In 1992, when Los Angeles exploded in rioting in the wake of the acquittal of police accused of beating a black motorist, Kemp tied the UEZ solution to the problem of urban unrest and alienation. The riots gave Kemp an opportunity to link his potential solutions to the problem of rioting.45 It is important to realize, however, that not all organizations are as anarchic and unmanaged as universities; universities may very well be the extreme example. But John Kingdon’s very successful application of the idea to policy making in the federal system suggests the considerable value of this way of thinking; this streamsand-garbage-cans model will, I hope, be clearer after we review Kingdon’s model of the agenda setting process in chapter 10. Two other models of decision making are considered in Allison’s Essence of Decision. He labels them Organizational Process and Governmental Politics, or Models II and III (Model I is the rational actor model). We might also call Model II the bureaucratic politics model. Model II is a model of organizational process grounded in a notion of bounded rationality. Allison argues that decisions are the result of bureaucrats applying standard operating procedures (SOPs) to problems. The model assumes that such procedures are relatively simple and that outcomes from these models are predictable. In addition, as Jonathan Bendor and Thomas Hammond note,46 the model suggests that SOPs will largely condition behavior in such a way that if we know the SOP we can make relatively good guesses about decision makers’ future behavior. Finally, the model assumes that individuals seek information, that information carries with it relatively high costs, and that reducing the cost of information is therefore an important goal. From this we can conclude that incrementalism is a key feature of this style of decision making, remembering that information deficits make bold steps difficult if not impossible.

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

259

Model III, the governmental politics model, is a model of political conflict. Model III echoes Neustadt’s argument in Presidential Power that the power of any chief executive rests in his or her persuasive abilities.47 Decisions in this model are the product of competition and negotiation among the president, top government executives, bureaucrats, legislators, and other interested parties. American politics is thus characterized by a high degree of fragmentation and competition, and decision making is slow, competitive, and likely to reflect the power of the relative actors more than the ultimate desirability of the decision at hand. One can easily imagine that if the president’s power is mainly limited to persuasion, the power of other actors (who do not have the powers and prestige of the president) will be even more limited. Conclusion This chapter started with a discussion of the things policy makers must consider when designing policies. As has become a recurring theme in this book, this process is much more complex than it might initially appear. Goals conflict with each other or are ambiguous, and policies are often designed without a sound causal theory to help policy makers know whether a particular kind of policy will work. All these aspects of design are important because policy design will have a considerable influence on the choice of tools employed to achieve the stated goals of a policy. Policy tools and implementation are considered together because they are inextricably linked to each other. The choice of policy tools both influences implementation and is influenced by implementation, as we will see in the next chapter. Furthermore, the choices of tools and implementation design reinforce each other throughout the implementation process. As more is learned about the success or failure of various tools and their implementation, policy makers and the various advocacy groups involved in a policy domain will continue to debate not only the underlying rationale for a policy, but the methods by which the policy is put into effect. Key Terms Bounded rationality Causal theory Cost-benefit analysis Efficiency

Incrementalism Outcomes Policy design Policy goal

Policy tool Polis Rational comprehensive decision making Sunset provisions

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. Why is it difficult to separate policy design and implementation? 2. Why do we say there is a difference between the outputs of government and the outcomes of policy?

260 Chapter 8 3. Explain the difference between equal opportunity and equal outcome. Do you believe that there is a real difference between the two? 4. What role does ambiguity play when there are conflicting policy goals? How does ambiguity help promote policy making? How does goal ambiguity make policy design more difficult? 5. Why is it essential for policy makers to have a causal theory when creating a policy design? Can you think of examples of a poor policy design in which it appears that the causal theory is incorrect? How would you redesign such a policy to fit the better causal theory? 6. Why does Deborah Stone argue that efficiency should not be the sole goal of implementing public policy? Are there public policies that exist that are inefficient but that serve other, more important social goals? Does this imply that there are more important goals than efficiency? What are these goals? 7. This may not seem like serious research, but you may find this to be an interesting exercise in policy ambiguity and perceptions of problems. Gather up a group of four to six people; your classmates, perhaps, or friends, roommates, or family. Then think of a public problem that you all agree should be addressed. Once you agree that something is a problem, jot down your responses to these questions: • What causes the problem you have agreed is a bad thing? • What tools or interventions would you use to alleviate the problem you all identified? â•… Discuss what you conclude among yourselves. Are your causal theories different? If so, are your proposed interventions or policy tools different or similar? Why? Additional Reading My thinking about policy goals is greatly influenced by Deborah Stone’s Policy Paradox. She also has a thoughtful section on policy tools, although the terminology she uses is not the same as much of the current scholarship on policy tools. Readers interested in the many ways of thinking of policy tools might browse Lester M. Salamon’s and Odus V. Elliott’s The Tools of Government: A Guide to the New Governance (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002). This book is an encyclopedic treatment of the various methods of government intervention, written by top scholars in the policy sciences. An important book on policy design is Anne Larason Schneider and Helen Ingram, Policy Design for Democracy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997). Additional advanced (and often highly technical) works on policy design include Robert Agranoff and Michael McGuire, Collaborative Public Management: New Strategies for Local Governments (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003); Huib Pellikaan and Robert J. van der Veen, Environmental

Policy Design, Policy Tools,

and

Decisions

261

Dilemmas and Policy Design (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002); and David Edward Michael Sappington, Principles of Regulatory Policy Design (World Bank, Office of the Vice President, 1994). Sound sources on policy tools themselves include Christopher Howard, “Testing the Tools Approach: Tax Expenditures versus Direct Expenditures,” Public Administration Review 55, no. 5 (1995): 439–47; Lester M. Salamon, ed., Beyond Privatization: The Tools of Government Action (Washington, DC: Urban Institute, 1989); and Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram, “Behavioral Assumptions of Policy Tools,” Journal of Politics 52 (May 1990): 510–29. Notes 1. An excellent discussion of the importance of outcomes is provided by Dennis P. Affholter, “Outcome Monitoring,” in Handbook of Practical Program Evaluation, ed. Joseph S. Wholey, Harry P. Hatry, and Kathryn E. Newcomer (San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 1994). 2. Deborah Stone, Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making, rev. ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 2002). 3. Stone, Policy Paradox, 83. 4. Jim McGee, “An Intelligence Giant in the Making; Anti-Terrorism Law Likely to Bring Domestic Apparatus of Unprecedented Scope,” The Washington Post, November 4, 2001, A04. 5. House approves renewal of Patriot Act, CNN.com, http://www.cnn.com/2005/POLITICS/07/21/patriot.act/ (accessed January 4, 2010). 6. Richard Lacayo, “The War Comes Back Home: Can Attorney General John Ashcroft Fight Terrorism on Our Shores without Injuring Our Freedoms?” Time, May 12, 2003. 7. Dan Eggen, “FBI Seeks Data on Foreign Students; Colleges Call Request Illegal,” The Washington Post, December 25, 2002, A1. 8. Robert O’Harrow Jr., “In Terror War, Privacy vs. Security; Search for Illicit Activities Taps Confidential Financial Data,” The Washington Post, June 3, 2002, A1. 9. See, for example, David L. Hudson, Patriot Act, http://www.firstamendmentcenter.org/speech/libraries/topic. aspx?topic=patriot_act (accessed February 15, 2010). 10. The provision in question is contained in Section 215(a)(10) (amending 50 U.S.C. 1861 et seq.). (a)(1) The Director of the Federal Bureau of Investigation or a designee of the Director (whose rank shall be no lower than Assistant Special Agent in Charge) may make an application for an order requiring the production of any tangible things (including books, records, papers, documents, and other items) for an investigation to protect against international terrorism or clandestine intelligence activities, provided that such investigation of a United States person is not conducted solely upon the basis of activities protected by the first amendment to the Constitution.” 11. Michael Isikoff, “Show Me the Money,” Newsweek, 142 (22) (December 1, 2003). 12. Linda M. Greenhouse, “A Penchant for Secrecy,” The New York Times, http://www.nytimes.com/2002/05/05/ weekinreview/05GREE.html (accessed May 11, 2002). 13. John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies, 2d ed. (New York: Harper Collins, 1995). 14. Eric Lichtblau, “Effort to Curb Scope of Antiterrorism Law Falls Short,” The New York Times, July 9, 2004, p. A3. 15. Timothy Egan, “Sensing the Eyes of Big Brother, and Pushing Back,” The New York Times, August 8, 2004, p. 20. 16. Lisa W. Foderaro, “Board Rejects Parts of Patriot Act,” The New York Times, September 19, 2004, Section 14, p. 7. 17. United States Justice Department, “Report from the Field: The USA Patriot Act at Work,” http://www.lifeandliberty.gov/docs/071304_report_from_the_field.pdf (accessed September 29, 2004). 18. On this very point, see Christopher Trenholm, Barbara Devaney, Ken Fortson, Lisa Quay, Justin Wheeler, and Melissa Clark, Impacts of Four Title V Section 510 Abstinence Education Programs, (Princeton, NJ: Mathematica Policy Research, Inc., 2007), http://www.mathematica-mpr.com/publications/PDFs/impactabstinence.pdf (accessed February 15, 2010).

262 Chapter 8 19. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann, “Policy Failure: An Issue Deserving Attention,” in Why Policies Succeed or Fail, ed. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1980). 20. Edward O. Laumann and David Knoke, The Organizational State: Social Choice in National Policy Domains (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987), chapter 1. 21. Frank Reissman, “Full Employment Now?” Social Policy 29, no. 4 (Summer 1999): 4; Jody Lipford, “Twenty Years After Humphrey-Hawkins,” Independent Review 4, no. 1 (Summer 1999): 41–63. 22. Deborah A. Stone, “Causal Stories and the Formation of Policy Agendas,” Political Science Quarterly 104, no. 2 (1989): 281–300. 23. Stone, Policy Paradox, 189. 24. Anne Larason Schneider and Helen Ingram, Policy Design for Democracy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997), 93. 25. James E. Anderson, Public Policymaking, 5th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2002). 26. Lester M. Salamon and Michael S. Lund, “The Tools Approach: Basic Analytics,” in Beyond Privatization: The Tools of Government Action, ed. Lester M. Salamon (Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1989), 29. 27. Salamon and Lund, “The Tools Approach,” 28. 28. Lester M. Salamon, “The New Governance and the Tools of Public Action: An Introduction,” in The Tools of Government: A Guide to the New Governance, ed. Lester M. Salamon (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 1. 29. Salamon, “The New Governance,” 1–2. 30. Michael Howlett and M. Ramesh, Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems (Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1995), 157–163. 31. Howlett and Ramesh, Studying Public Policy, 158. 32. United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995). 33. Charles H. Levine, B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson, Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences (Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman/Little Brown, 1990). 34. Salamon and Lund, “The Tools Approach,” 41. 35. Anthony Kassekert, and Richard Feiock, “Policy Tool Selection: Predicting the Bundling of Economic Development Policy Instruments Using a Multivariate Probit Analysis” Paper presented at the American Political Science Association Annual Meeting, Toronto, ON, September 6, 2009. 36. Walter A. McDougall, The Heavens and the Earth: A Political History of the Space Age (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997). 37. Charles H. Levine, B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson. Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences (Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman/Little Brown, 1990), 82. 38. See, for example, Thomas R. Dye, Understanding Public Policy, 7th ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall, 1992), 33. 39. Graham Allison and Philip Zelikow, Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis, 2d ed. (New York: Addison Wesley Longman, 1999). 40. Dye, Understanding Public Policy. 41. James G. March and Herbert A. Simon, Organizations (New York: John Wiley, 1958). 42. Charles E. Lindblom, “The Science of ‘Muddling Through,’” Public Administration Review 19 (1959): 79–88. His follow-up to this article is Charles Lindblom, “Still Muddling, Not Yet Through,” Public Administration Review 39 (1979): 517–26. 43. Paul R. Schulman, “Nonincremental Policy Making: Notes toward an Alternative Paradigm,” American Political Science Review 69, no. 4 (December 1975): 1354–70. 44. Michael D. Cohen, James G. March, and Johan P. Olsen, “A Garbage Can Model of Organizational Choice,” Administrative Science Quarterly 17 (1972): 1–25. 45. See, for example, William Claiborne, “Kemp Calls on Mayors for ‘Audacious’ Effort; Enterprise Zones, New War on Poverty Urged,” The Washington Post, June 23, 1992, A19; David Lauter, “Administration Again Divided on Urban Aid,” Los Angeles Times, May 25, 1992, A24. 46. Jonathan Bendor and Thomas H. Hammond, “Rethinking Allison’s Models,” American Political Science Review 86, no. 2 (1992): 301–22. 47. Richard E. Neustadt, Presidential Power and the Modern Presidents: The Politics of Leadership from Roosevelt to Reagan (New York: Free Press, 1990).

Policy Implementation, Failure, and Learning

9

CHAPTER

Chapter at a Glance The Implementation of Public Policies Approaches to the Study of Implementation Top-Down Approaches to Implementation Bottom-Up Approaches to Implementation Synthesis: A Third Generation of Implementation Research Policy Failure, and Learning from It Types of Learning Conclusion Case Study: Policy Failure and Learning in Aviation Security, 2000–2010 Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

The Implementation of Public Policies Once the designers of policies have designed their policy tools, the various actors in the policy process turn their attention to the implementation of public policy. The study of “program implementation is concerned with what happens to a policy or program after it has been formulated.”1 Until the late 1960s, there were few studies of policy implementation. Few scholars had sought to systematically study what happens after legislation or some other statement of policy is enacted and then put into effect. Some studies described the implementation process, but had not set out to create a theory of policy implementation. Of course, this description of implementation in the policy process is linear and simplistic. It assumes that policy design and tool selection occur separately from policy implementation. In fact, we know that both aspects are important to the success of public policies. But we can distinguish between the design and tools phase and the implementation phase to the extent that policy implementation relies on the behavior of the implementers and the policy targets. While these behaviors may be anticipated in the design process, one is never sure how policy will actually be

263

implementation. The process by which policies enacted by government are put into effect by the relevant agencies.

264 Chapter 9 implemented once the policy interacts with the various aspects of the policy environment, with the actual implementers, and the policy targets. It is important to understand policy implementation because it is a key feature of the policy process, and learning from the problems encountered in implementation can foster learning about better ways to structure policies to ensure that they have the effects that designers of these policies seek. In addition, perhaps to a greater extent than other elements of the policy process, implementation studies have emphasized advice to policy makers as to how to structure programs to increase the likelihood of implementation success. Thus, when students of policy implementation talk about “top-down” or “bottomup” implementation designs, they are talking about ways of studying policy design and ways of structuring policy implementation to enhance the likelihood of implementation success. In any case, we do know, and have known for some time, that policies are not self-executing, regardless of the hopes and beliefs of policy designers. If the bureaucracy was a strictly neutral institution that, as Woodrow Wilson once argued, simply did what elected officials ordered it to do, then all the problems people have cited about bureaucracy—in particular, the problems of discretion and accountability—would never enter into the discussion of implementation. Because bureaucracies do have discretion in how they implement policies, this section reviews some ways of looking at policy implementation that see bureaucratic discretion as a problem to be overcome by sound choices in policy design. But, to complicate the picture again, even the simplest policy with the most willing bureaucracies involved in implementation confronts implementing agencies with two big questions: what does the legislative branch want done, and how do we do it? Discerning intent, and then figuring out how to meet the implied goals, is extremely challenging. Thus, as Smith and Larimer note, the implementation process replicates, in many ways, all the challenges of the policy process, starting with problems—in this case discerning intent—through designing tools in a way that those further down the implementation change will willingly engage in the desired behavior.2 Approaches to the Study of Implementation As Smith and Larimer note, there are three main eras of policy implementation research. 3 The first era, which emerged in the late 1960s through early 1970s, is characterized by works such as Implementation and New Towns in Town.4 The authors undertook these studies to understand why particular policies, such as the Economic Development Administration’s efforts to relieve poverty in Oakland or the Johnson administration’s “New Towns in Town” efforts, seemed to fall short of their goals. These studies focused on individual case studies and did not create more generalizable theory that could be applied to and tested with other cases. Indeed, many studies of administration and organization discussed matters of policy implementation, even if that term was not well developed or if that aspect was not the centerpiece of the research project.

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

265

A second era of implementation studies, which began in the mid-1970s, sought to create systematic theories of the policy process that were generalizable to many cases, rather than focused on one or a few cases. As this research progressed, one could discern two separate research approaches. The first of these approaches emphasizes a “top-down” perspective on policy implementation. Its proponents claim that one can understand policy implementation by looking at the goals and strategies adopted in the statute or other policy, as structured by the implementers of policy. These studies focus on the gaps between the goals set by a policy’s drafters and the actual implementation and outcomes of the policy. The second approach emphasizes a “bottom-up” perspective, which suggests that implementation is best studied by starting at the lowest levels of the implementation system or “chain” and moving upward to see where implementation is more or less successful. Top-Down Approaches to Implementation Some representative studies in the top-down research tradition include research by Carl Van Horn and Donald Van Meter, as well as Daniel Mazmanian and Paul Sabatier’s studies of the factors that condition successful implementation.5 The top-down approach is based on a set of important assumptions: • Policies contain clearly defined goals against which performance can be measured. As Neal Ryan puts it, “Top-down implementation strategies greatly depend on the capacity of policy objectives to be clearly and consistently defined.”6 • Policies contain clearly defined policy tools for the accomplishment of goals. • The policy is characterized by the existence of a single statute or other authoritative statement of policy. • There is an “implementation chain” that “starts with a policy message at the top and sees implementation as occurring in a chain.”7 • Policy designers have good knowledge of the capacity and commitment of the implementers. Capacity encompasses the availability of resources for an implementing organization to carry out its tasks, including monetary and human resources, legal authority and autonomy, and the knowledge needed to effectively implement policy. Commitment includes the desire of the implementers to carry out the goals of the top-level policy designers; a high level of commitment means that the lower-level implementers, particularly those at the “street level,” such as teachers, police officers, or social workers, share the values and goals of the policy designers. In a top-down model of policy design, the implementer assumes that these features are present or that any problems suggested by these assumptions can be overcome. The focus then is on creating the proper structures and controls to encourage or

top-down approach. A way of studying policy design and implementation that considers the goals of the highest-level policy designers, and traces the design and implementation of the policy through the lowest-level implementers.

266 Chapter 9 compel compliance with the goals set at the top. But there are some substantial weaknesses with this approach that you may recognize from earlier chapters in this book. Perhaps the most problematic feature of top-down models is the emphasis on clear objectives or goals. Without a consensus on what program goals are, it is hard to set a benchmark for program success and failure. For example, in 1973 Congress established the fifty-five-mile-per-hour (mph) speed limit on the nation’s freeways as a method for promoting energy conservation, because, in most cases, driving one’s car at fifty-five mph is more fuel efficient than driving it at seventy mph. Yet most gains in fuel economy between 1973 and the early 1990s were a result of federal policies requiring that a manufacturer’s vehicles achieve an average fuel economy of 27.5 miles per gallon for cars and 20.7 miles per gallon for light trucks. Most manufacturers comply with this standard. However, the fifty-five-mile-per-hour speed limit had a side benefit—it substantially reduced highway fatalities in the early years of its enforcement. On what accomplishment, then, should the fifty-five mph limit be assessed? In terms of motorists’ compliance and state enforcement, the fifty-five mph speed limit was generally unsuccessful, and its widespread unpopularity led to its repeal. In terms of fuel economy, the results were inconclusive, but the safety benefits were substantial. Highway safety advocates fought hard to keep the fifty-five mph limit in place and were successful in this fight until the late 1980s. This is an example of how advocates for a policy will redefine policy goals to justify the continuance of a program and how new groups can enter the debate to highlight new goals and benefits of programs—or to argue that a program has outlived its value. In the case of the fifty-five mph speed limit, by the mid-1980s the safety and fuel efficiency benefits, some argued, were less than they had been because of the aforementioned increase in automobile fuel economy (gains that had been lost to some extent in the late 1990s with the advent of SUVs) and the increased safety of most newer cars. Another example of multiple objectives is found in the management of the nation’s forests by the U.S. Forest Service (USFS), which must administer the forests to serve “multiple uses,” ranging from recreation to logging.8 By what goals should the forest service’s efforts be measured? This is a constant source of conflict for the agency, as environmentalists and recreational users battle logging interests and their local allies over which aspect of forest policy—timber supply or resource conservation and recreation—should be emphasized by the USFS. When policy makers fail to provide one goal or a coherent, mutually compatible set of goals, implementation is likely to be difficult as agencies and people charged with putting policies into effect pursue different goals. Another problem with top-down models is the assumption that there is a single national government that can successfully structure policy implementation and provide for direct delivery of services. But most policies made by the federal government require considerable state and, in many cases, local governmental

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

cooperation. The fifty state governments have constitutionally protected rights and responsibilities, so they are often reluctant to surrender their power and prerogatives to distant agencies headquartered in Washington. One cannot say, then, that the federal government can mandate any policy it sees fit; if it attempts to do so, it may endanger state and local cooperation, and can generate indifference or outright conflict with the states. Even within the federal government itself, this assumption of a strong central government assumes a unitary method of decision making that ignores competing or overlapping agencies and their staffs, and the interest groups that have an interest in these agencies’ work. Indeed, James Anderson notes that legislators, bureaucrats, the courts, pressure groups, and community organizations are all involved in policy implementation.9 While the focus of implementation may be in one agency, several other actors will have an influence on implementation success or failure. Given this dismal account, one might assume that the federal government—the “top”—cannot structure implementation at all. However, Sabatier notes that the top can set guidelines for implementation, if not hard and fast rules,10 provided government actors act carefully and work collaboratively across agencies and with the states and local actors. How do states resist mandates from the federal government? Malcolm Goggin and his colleagues have cited instances of “strategic delay” at the state level, where states seek to slow implementation in order to develop ways to adapt the program to local needs, or to induce the federal government to provide more funding or other incentives.11 However, not all delay is strategic—some delay or outright refusal to implement policy is a reaction to local and state desires to not implement a policy at all. This is sometimes due to local political pressures, such as when some states failed to aggressively enforce the fifty-five mph speed limit. At other times, streetlevel bureaucrats may refuse to implement a policy that comes from the top: the police, for example, may resist changes in policing procedure based on their professional experience, as the “dropsy” evidence case in chapter 7 suggests. Top-down approaches often ignore the relative ease with which many implementers and interest groups can work to subvert the originally established goals. On the other hand, Paul Sabatier rejects the inevitability of “adaptive” implementation in which target groups and street-level bureaucrats subvert the original program’s goals. Sabatier argues that top policy designers do have choices about who implements a policy and what incentives and sanctions to impose for noncompliance and can influence the expectations and needs of target groups so that adaptive compliance should be unnecessary or would be counterproductive.12 Finally, top-down approaches assume that policy is contained in a single statute or other authoritative statement. The fragmented and in some ways incrementalist nature of policy making in the United States means that, when one talks about “environmental policy” or “educational policy” or “health policy,” one is discussing a wide collection of separate and sometimes contradictory policies. This is related to the tendency of top-down approaches to assume a relatively clear division between

267

268 Chapter 9 policy enactment, on the one hand, and policy implementation, on the other. Indeed, many of the studies of implementation from a public administration perspective tend to adopt this distinction, which may be analytically useful but runs the risk of assuming that the same pressures that work to shape policy adoption do not exist in policy implementation. Bottom-Up Approaches to Implementation bottom-up approach. A way of studying policy design and implementation that considers the abilities and motivations of the lowest-level implementers, and tracks policy design from that level to the highest levels of government.

In a reaction to the overly structured top-down research approach—in particular, to dissatisfaction with its ability to explain many unsuccessful outcomes, and in reaction to the flaws of top-down policy design—researchers began to view implementation from the perspective of “street-level bureaucrats.”13 Richard Elmore, the key proponent of the bottom-up approach, calls this “backward mapping,” in which the implementation process and the relevant relationships are mapped backward, from the ultimate implementer to the topmost policy designers.14 This approach is built on a set of assumptions that stand in marked contrast to the implicit assumptions of “forward mapping” or top-down approaches. First, the bottom-up approach recognizes that goals are ambiguous rather than explicit and may conflict not only with other goals in the same policy area, but also with the norms and motivations of the street-level bureaucrats. As Rene Torenvlied notes, “The compliance problem arises when there is a conflict of interest between implementation agencies and politicians.”15 Top-down models are most concerned with compliance, while bottom-up approaches value understanding how conflict can be alleviated by bargaining and sometimes compromise to maximize the likelihood of achieving the policy goals. Second, the bottom-up approach does not require that there be a single defined “policy” in the form of a statute or other form. Rather, policy can be thought of as a set of laws, rules, practices, and norms, such as “energy policy” or “criminal procedure,” that shape the ways in which government and interest groups address these problems. Thus, implementation can be viewed as a continuation of the conflicts and compromises that occur throughout the policy process, not just before it begins and at the point of enactment. This makes for a more realistic depiction of the implementation process, and clearly accommodates the type of policy tool bundling described in chapter 8. This bottom-up approach has a number of features to commend it. In particular, the lack of a focus on a particular program and on a fixed, top-to-bottom implementation chain means that the bottom-up approach can view implementation as working through a network of actors—much like an issue network or policy community— rather than through some rigidly specified process that fails to account for the richness of the policy-making environment. But there are also important shortcomings to consider in the bottom-up approach. Paul Sabatier argues that the bottom-up approach overemphasizes the ability of the

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

street-level bureaucrats to frustrate the goals of the top policy makers. Street-level bureaucrats are not entirely free agents. They are constrained to act in a particular way based on their professional norms and obligations, by the resources available to them, and by legal sanctions that can be applied for noncompliance. Police officers, for example, who use “too much” discretion and thereby ignore procedural rules for handling suspects or evidence can lose their jobs or face criminal charges; teachers who violate professional norms can be demoted or lose their jobs. States that fail to implement key features of federal policy put themselves at risk of losing substantial amounts of federal money, so states and local governments are under pressure to bring their agencies into compliance; the No Child Left Behind Act is a good example. Nor do street-level bureaucrats necessarily have the resources to thwart policy designers; they may be able to delay, but not entirely subvert, implementation. Finally, the tension between bottom-up and top-down approaches may overstate the extent to which local implementers will resist policies handed down from above. In some cases, the street-level bureaucrat may also want to follow the lead of the top-level designers, supporting the goals handed down from higher up, and working as best they can to implement national goals. Bottom-up models of implementation also assume that groups are active participants in the implementation process. This is not always true, however. Peter May argues that some policies can be categorized as “policies without publics,” which are developed and implemented with relatively little public input, particularly when those policy areas are highly technical.16 Along these lines, Sabatier also argues that the bottom-up approach fails to take into account the power differences of the target groups. As Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram note, some target populations are more positively constructed than others, with the result that those with greater power can have a greater influence on the impact of policies that affect them than can other groups.17 Clearly, business interests are going to be treated differently in implementation design than are the poor or prisoners, and these treatments are reflected in the choice of policy tools. The choice of tools is made at the top, based on the desired behavioral change and the nature of the target population itself. While these approaches to implementation have shortcomings, it is worthwhile to consider how these two approaches to implementation contribute to our knowledge of this essential element of public policy. The top-down approach is much more useful when there is a single, dominant program that is being studied. Several times in this book, I have mentioned specific legislative enactments that made important policy changes. It would be appropriate to study the implementation of legislation like No Child Left Behind or the Homeland Security Act from the top down. Much of the policy related to these acts was designed in Congress and the federal executive branch and, regardless of the complexity and span of issues raised in each law, they were structured from the outset to be promoted, managed, and evaluated by top government officials. Sabatier also argues that top-down approaches are appropriate when one has limited resources to “backward map” the implementation of a particular

269

270 Chapter 9 issue. It is considerably easier to look up statutes and other pronouncements issued by top-level policy designers than it is to map all the various interests, agencies, and street-level officials that will carry out a policy. If you are reading this book for a course, you may find that if you choose to write analysis of implementation, it is much more efficient to start from the most visible policy changes rather than from the bottom, where the less visible policies are made. On the other hand, bottom-up modeling makes sense when there is no single dominant program (such as in a state’s penal code, which consists of many policy statements regarding the nature and severity of crimes) and when one is more interested in the local dynamics of implementation than in the broad sweep of design. It is useful to consider the local factors, from both practical and academic perspectives, since local experience with implementation success or failure can yield important lessons for policy implementers. Synthesis: A Third Generation of Implementation Research Because of the relative strengths and weaknesses of the top-down and bottom-up approaches, researchers have sought to combine the benefits of these approaches into one model or synthesis that can address the structuring of policy from the top as well as the likelihood of its subversion or at least its alteration at the point of implementation. Richard Elmore has sought to combine his idea of “backward mapping” with a “forward mapping element.”18 By looking both forward and backward, we can understand that top policy makers can make choices of policy instruments or tools to structure implementation, while realizing that the motivations and needs of lower-level implementers must be taken into account. Paul Sabatier also argues that a conceptual framework should be developed that combines the best of the top-down and bottom-up approaches. Indeed, at the same time that Sabatier was writing, Laurence O’Toole argued that better thinking on implementation was needed precisely to provide policy makers and designers with useful advice.19 The top-down approach is best where there is a dominant program (i.e., law) that is well structured and where the researcher’s resources for studying implementation are limited, as when a student is researching the implementation of a program for a term paper or an implementer needs a quick analysis to investigate how to structure a program. By contrast, the bottom-up approach is best where one is interested in the dynamics of local implementation and where there is no single dominant program. One begins by analyzing diffuse street-level behavior rather than focused, top-down activity. Because of this diffuse behavior, gathering the needed data to tell the implementation story can be challenging, as multiple sources must be consulted and analyzed. Sabatier’s synthesis relies on a framework for studying public policy known as the Advocacy Coalition Framework, or ACF, which is discussed at greater length in chapter 10. In this application of the ACF to implementation, Sabatier’s synthesis

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

starts by adopting the bottom-up perspective, which involves looking at “a whole variety of public and private actors involved with a policy problem—as well as their concerns with understanding the perspectives and strategies of all major categories of actors (not simply program proponents).”20 This contrasts with the top-down focus on the topmost designers of policies. But Sabatier also adopts the top-down perspective by providing a simplified, abstract model of a complex system and by recognizing the importance of the structural features of policy emphasized by the top-down theorists. The primary reason Sabatier uses the ACF to think about implementation is that it reflects the growing sense that implementation does not take place in a one-to-one relationship between the designers, implementers, and targets, but is rather contained within a policy subsystem; the ACF is one way to think about the organization of subsystems. Refining and reconciling the top-down and bottom-up approaches, Goggin and his colleagues21 have devised a theory of policy implementation that relies on the sending of messages between policy makers and implementers. This study takes into account an important feature of most policy design: that implementation is as much a matter of negotiation and communication as it is a matter of command. Even commands are sometimes resisted because they are unclear or inconsistent with the receiver’s expectations. Goggin and his colleagues sum up their argument in two key propositions: • Clear messages sent by credible officials and received by receptive implementers who have or are given sufficient resources and who implement policies supported by affected groups lead to implementation success. • Strategic delay on the part of states, while delaying the implementation of policies, can actually lead to improved implementation of policies through innovation, policy learning, bargaining, and the like. The first of these propositions is a short summary of what has been learned thus far in the study of implementation analysis, but packaged as a matter of communication between various actors. In actual experience, messages are often unclear, officials often lack credibility, and implementers are often not receptive or, if they are, do not receive sufficient resources or are opposed by the affected groups. The second proposition counters some of the gloom that had settled around many policy implementation studies. Goggin and his colleagues found, in certain policy areas, that states that “strategically delayed” implementation—in order to seek clarification of a policy, raise more funds, ensure support of affected groups, and so on—often had better success in implementing a policy than did states that immediately implemented a policy. It seems that it would behoove the analyst to take a longer-term approach to policy studies, since what may at first blush look like delay on the part of a state or local government may in fact be a period of strategic positioning and adaptation of a policy that actually improves the quality of the service being delivered under the policy, as well as enhancing the likelihood of any implementation.

271 Advocacy coalition framework (ACF). A model or framework for understanding the interactions of groups and coalitions of groups called advocacy coalitions. In the framework, typically two to four coalitions form based on shared beliefs on policy issues. Paul Sabatier is the primary developer of the ACF, which has been applied to studies of implementation, policy change, and learning.

272 Chapter 9 The debate continues in policy studies over the best approach to the study of implementation and even whether we should continue studying implementation or focus our attention on other, supposedly more fruitful avenues of research. As long as policies fail or appear to fail, implementation studies will remain important to policy makers and to students of the policy process. Policy Failure and Learning from It For some reason, both journalists and policy scientists like bad news: Journalists will report when the government has lost a lot of money, but will ignore evidence of those instances when the government has saved money through some sort of innovation. At the same time, most books on policy implementation describe policy failures. There are probably simple reasons for our concentration on policy failure. The old saying, “If it ain’t broke, don’t fix it,” may dominate our thinking about government: After all, if a government program is reasonably successful, what need is there to describe how it works when we can learn more from failure? I am not sure that we should take this approach, and I believe we should study and learn from government successes—of which there are many—as well as government failures. Indeed, after the 2001 terrorist attacks, a prominent political scientist, Paul Light, wrote a very useful book on governmental achievements and successes—successes we should celebrate as our own because, as Americans, it is our government and the efforts of thousands and millions of our fellow citizens that help make things work.22 But because there are so many purported policy failures, and so much written about them, it is worth considering the reasons for these claims of failure. No doubt you have asserted, and heard others claim, that a policy has failed. “Our policy against illegal immigrants has failed,” you may argue, “because there are still thousands of people coming across the border illegally every day.” Or you may conclude that aviation security has failed, in part because, in late 2009, a would-be bomber was able to hide a potential bomb in his underwear, even as security was supposed to be much improved after the September 11 attacks. Let us simply assume that these claims are at least partially true. You can then say that the policy has failed to meet its goals: to keep out illegal immigrants and to allow only legal immigrants to come to the country, or to keep bad people off of airplanes. Why might the policy be a failure? You might argue that the border patrol or the airport screeners are incompetent, that the officers are competent but their managers are not, or that the policy was doomed to fail because of resource shortfalls or because the goals of the policy—near-zero illegal immigrants or zero terrorist attacks—are just too difficult to achieve. Sometimes we say that a policy is unsuccessful, if not an outright failure, because the policy does not serve enough people or because resources and services are spread too thin among those it does serve. In other words, we tell causal stories of failure much as we tell causal stories of why problems exist in the first place. The actual idea of “failure” itself is defined implicitly, but

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

not explicitly. In other words, the meaning of “failure” and the context in which it is discussed are never really specified. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann provide us with a number of useful ways to think about policy failure. They argue that, “success and failure are slippery concepts, often highly subjective and reflective of an individual’s goals, perception of need, and perhaps even psychological disposition toward life.”23 In other words, failure is perhaps in the eye of the beholder. And the beholder’s vision is affected by his or her immediate perception of the policy in question: as Ingram and Mann argue, labor and management are likely to have very different perspectives on the necessity of the minimum wage. One person may argue that a policy has failed, while another person might look at it as a tentative first step toward a larger goal, such as some health programs for the poor and elderly: Medicare and Medicaid can be viewed as the first step toward more universal health services. Other reasons for policy failure are listed in Table 9.1, which summarizes Ingram and Mann’s argument. If you are active in politics and policy making or even reasonably attentive to politics, you will recognize these reasons for policy failure. There are many possible reasons for policy failure and many possible problems that can cause or contribute to it. Thus, simple storytelling about policy failure may reflect popular dissatisfaction with a policy in particular, or government in general, but fails to take into account the multiple reasons that policies can at least be perceived as failures. But let’s continue to assume that policies do indeed fail—they either fail to deliver what they promise, or they fail because of unintended or unforeseen consequences of policies, which is a strong probability given that policies are complex and all the variables are not always well known. We might assume that policy failure provides an opportunity to learn from the erroneous or incomplete assumptions of the past. Thus, it is useful to think about how policy failure induces policy change through a learning process. Indeed, many experts and commentators on important public issues claim that certain phenomena can induce organizations to learn from their mistakes. For some time, social scientists, including those who study complex organizations, have been interested in understanding the extent to which organizational learning can take place. This is a major concern of organizations, because those that fail to understand their environment and adapt to it by acting on new information are likely to fall short. Who learns, what is learned, and how learning is employed have been defined differently by various students of the policy process.24 The main controversy in the debate over who learns is whether nonhuman entities such as institutions or organizations can “learn” or whether only individual people learn. One can argue that an organization learns through experience: when it develops and implements policies, the evaluation and feedback processes provide “learning opportunities” for the organization to change its behavior. While people learn by retaining informa-

273

274 Chapter 9 Table 9.1 Explanations for Policy Failure Alternatives to policies tried

Failure needs to be assessed in terms of the option to let present trends continue1, and in terms of the likelihood that other options would have been more or less successful. The impact of changing Changing circumstances can render policies less successful, such as energy policies circumstance that provided price relief before they created dependency on oil and natural gas. Relationships of one Policies are interrelated, and these relationships must be taken into account. For expolicy to another ample, a stricter policy against illegal immigrants may endanger broader policy goals surrounding our relations with Mexico, such as oil supplies or drug interdiction. The boundary question Political boundaries (between states, for example) will influence policy success. Excessive policy demand We may expect too much from policies. Realizable policy expectations Policies sometimes fail when they go beyond what we know we can achieve now. But ambitious policy making can be the result of “speculative argumentation”2 that seeks to induce innovation. The stated purpose of a policy may not be the actual purpose; there may be more symbolic goals than substance. Accurate theory of causation Policy will fail if it is not based on sound causal theory. Choice of effective policy tools The choice of ineffective tools will likely yield failure. But the choice of tools is often a function of compromise or ideological predisposition. The vagaries of implementation The problems inherent in policy implementation can contribute to policy failure. Failure of political institutions “Policy failure is simply a symptom of more profound ailments within our political institutions,” such as the breakdown of political party power, devolution of power from congressional leaders to the committees and subcommittees.

Source: Helen Ingram and Dean Mann, “Policy Failure: An Issue Deserving Attention,” in Why Policies Succeed or Fail, ed. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1980). 1 Sometimes incorrectly called the “do nothing” option. See Eugene Bardachy, A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Effective Problem Solving. 3rd ed. (Washington DC: LQ Press, 2009). 2 This idea is from Charles O. Jones, The Policies and Politics of Pollution Control (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1975).

single-loop learning. Learning about how a policy or process works, and making adjustments to that policy or process without studying or questioning the fundamental assumptions of that policy or process.

tion and experience in their minds, organizations rely on information storage and retrieval and, perhaps more important, on “institutional memory,” which, to a large extent, is a function of the experiences and knowledge of key personnel who have been on the job a long time. This is a somewhat passive definition of organizational learning. Colin Bennett and Michael Howlett note that learning can be a more active and “deliberate attempt to adjust the goals and techniques of policy in the light of the consequences of past policy and new information so as to better attain” the policy goals.25 Indeed, organizations make concerted efforts to improve their learning capacity by creating systems to store and disseminate information.26 Organizations engage in two types of learning: in single-loop learning organizations learn about techniques (tools) that fail and make adjustments to improve them or replace them with techniques that work better. An example of single-loop learning would be the development of new and better tools to prevent would-be bombers from getting on airplanes. The agency in question may switch from using hand searches of passengers and baggage to explosives detectors, metal detectors, bomb-sniffing

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

dogs, or even the controversial “full-body scanners” that can reveal just about anything carried under clothing. The latter tool is being adopted because airlines, airports, and government agencies learned that existing measures did not keep the would-be bomber off the December 2009 flight to Detroit that triggered these critical questions. Double-loop learning is when organizations rethink the fundamental logic and values that support the entire range of actions around a goal. We can say that double-loop learning is learning about single-loop learning, because everything about all the aspects of policies intended to achieve a goal is revisited.27 Thus, in the 2009 bombing scare, some people focused on how to find bombs on would-be terrorists, but others have seized the apparent policy failure as a reason to question and probe all the actions the nation takes to protect against all terrorist threats to aviation, including passengers with bombs, cargo with bombs, and, in particular, the entire information-gathering and storage system that was supposedly reformed after September 11, 2001, to share information that would keep suspicious people off of airplanes. There are some conceptual and methodological problems in thinking of organizations as learning agents; in particular, organizations do not possess the cognitive abilities of people. Thus, in the policy process literature, Paul Sabatier, Peter May, George Busenberg, and others deal with this problem by isolating individuals—agency heads, interest group leaders, academics, journalists, and so on—not institutions, as the unit of analysis in studies of policy making and learning.28 Sabatier provides a more specific definition of “policy-oriented learning” as “relatively enduring alterations of thought or behavioral intentions which result from experience and which are concerned with the attainment (or revision) of policy objectives” (p. 133). Sabatier’s definition, by concentrating on individual actors as members of advocacy coalitions, avoids attributing cognitive processes to organizations, while broadening policy making to include influential actors, such as academics and journalists, that institutionally focused analyses tend to overlook. This focus on the individual as policy actor also overcomes the tendency to think of agencies or institutions as the agents of learning. To summarize, we can think of learning at the organizational and individual levels, but for our purposes it is most useful to consider people as the agents of learning; these people apply what they have learned to in-group policy-making processes. Types of Learning To refine our understanding of learning in the public policy process, Peter May divides learning into three categories: instrumental policy learning, social policy learning, and political learning. In all three types of learning, policy failure—politically and socially defined—provide a stimulus for learning about how to make better policy.

275

double-loop learning. A type of learning that involves not only thinking about how a policy or process works, but also about the fundamental assumptions of that policy. policy learning. As defined by Sabatier, policy learning, or “policyoriented learning,” is “relatively enduring alterations of thought or behavioral intentions which result from experience and which are concerned with the attainment (or revision) of policy objectives.”

276 Chapter 9

instrumental policy learning. Learning about the effectiveness of policy tools and interventions. social policy learning. Learning about the social causes of problems and the possible interventions to solve those problems.

In the ideal case, learning reflects the accumulation and application of knowledge to lead to factually and logically correct conclusions. However, policy makers and their supporters may support policy change that is not objectively related to change in the political environment or the nature of the problem. May calls mimicking or copying policy without assessment or analysis “superstitious instrumental learning.” Lotteries and tax policy to attract additional industrial development are examples of this sort of mimicking, because states believe that if they do not adopt these policies, other states will gain some economic advantage. May’s article lists what he calls prima facie evidence of these various forms of learning. Instrumental policy learning concerns learning about “viability of policy interventions or implementation designs.” This type of learning centers on implementation tools and techniques. When feedback from implementation is analyzed and changes to the design are made that improve its performance, then this suggests that learning has happened and was successful. Social policy learning involves learning about the “social construction of a policy or program.” This type of learning goes beyond simple adjustments of program management to the heart of the problem itself, including attitudes toward program goals and the nature and appropriateness of government action. If successfully applied, social policy learning can result in better understanding of the underlying causal theory of a public problem, leading to better policy responses. Evidence of social policy learning involves learning the causes of problems and the effectiveness of policy interventions based on those problems. May argues that prima facie indicators of social learning involve “policy redefinition entailing changes in policy goals or scope—e.g., policy direction, target groups, rights bestowed by the policy.”29 There are many examples of such learning. One example concerns the way communities address prostitution. Traditionally, the police tried to control prostitution by arresting prostitutes, and doing so often enough to dissuade women from working in a particular area or community. When this policy was found to be ineffective—and, in many ways, unfair to the prostitutes themselves— communities focused instead on the men who seek out prostitutes, arresting the men and, in some cases, publicizing their arrests and convictions to shame them. In this case, the target of the policy shifted from the prostitute to the “John” because of a new understanding of the problem as being caused at least as much by demand as by supply. A similar logic is sometimes employed against illegal drugs, when attention shifts toward eradication and interdiction of drugs from abroad, rather than making smaller, seemingly less effective arrests of users at home. One can roughly equate instrumental learning with single-loop learning, and social learning with double-loop learning. Political learning is considerably different from instrumental and social learning. Peter May defines political learning as focusing on “strategy for advocating a given policy idea or problem,” leading potentially to “more sophisticated advocacy of a policy idea or problem” and effective political advocacy. Political learning

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

occurs when advocates for or against policy change alter their strategy and tactics to conform to new information that has entered the political system. For example, the breakdown of the nuclear power industry in the United States was due, in part, to the efforts of groups that mobilized against nuclear power; their efforts began before the 1979 Three Mile Island (TMI) nuclear power plant accident, but the event accelerated them. Group leaders learned that events such as TMI and the specter of the “China syndrome” were highly effective in promoting public and elite concerns about the safety and cost-effectiveness of nuclear power. Indeed, the exploitation of the more frightening or upsetting aspects of any event, from an industrial accident to the nomination of a potential Supreme Court justice, include the sophisticated use of imagery and storytelling to advance a position; these techniques have been learned and honed over time as competing groups seek to improve their competitive positions. Conclusion For policy makers and public managers, policy implementation is one of the most difficult aspects of the policy process, and policy failure is one of the most frustrating parts of their jobs, because most managers and decision makers want their ideas to work. For students of public policy, implementation is fascinating because implementation brings together many actors and forces that cooperate and clash with each other in order to achieve—or to thwart—policy goals. In that sense, it is truly a microcosm of the entire policy cycle. It is frustrating to research because the process has proven particularly hard to model; contributing to this frustration is the tension between building and testing good policy theory and implementation theory while providing useful information to policy makers and implementers on how to structure programs for greater success. Given the complexity of our political system, it seems that policy failure—or, at best, very limited success—would be the inevitable outcome of any public program. This may not be true, however, because failure is, like so much else in public policy, a subjective condition that is more often grounded in the perceptions of a particular interest than in empirical “fact.” Indeed, in areas such as crime control, terrorism, or environmental protection, one can argue that a policy has failed if it hasn’t achieved 100 percent of its goal—but what would have happened if the policy had not been adopted at all? Is 75 percent worse than perfection, or better than nothing? Clearly, this depends on the nature of the policy domain—in some systems, such as aviation safety policy or policies regulating drugs, we expect near perfection. However, we can stipulate that some policies are much less successful than others and that policy makers and others concerned with the management of public programs will learn from the purported failure of the policy. In this way, policy development is an ongoing process with no discernible beginning and no obvious end, but with plenty of opportunities for refinement and fine tuning.

277 political learning. Learning about making more effective political arguments in policy debate.

278 Chapter 9

Case Study: Policy Failure and Learning in Aviation Security, 2000–2010 On Christmas Day 2009, the world was once again reminded of the vulnerability of civil aviation to terrorist attacks. Sensitivity to this issue was clearly stoked by the September 11 terrorist attacks, which starkly highlighted the challenge of keeping commercial aviation safe from terrorist and criminal attacks. But just as the 2009 attack was not entirely novel, neither were the September 11 attacks. Hijackings often occurred in the United States and overseas in the 1960s and 1970s, and terrorist bombings of airplanes were rare, but not unheard of, in the 1980s. In the last twenty-five years, the two most disturbing breaches of aviation security in the United States, or involving a U.S. airline, were the bombing of Pan Am flight 103 over Lockerbie, Scotland, in 1988, and the September 11 hijackings and attacks. As in most disasters, these incidents served as focusing events that drew a great deal of attention to the shortcomings existing in aviation security policy design and implementation. The two big questions that arose from these attacks were whether these events were evidence of policy failure and whether there was anything learned from these potential failures that could reduce the probability of their recurrence. Congress and the media immediately labeled both the Pan Am and September 11 attacks as evidence of major policy failures. In the Pan Am case, attention was focused on how it was possible to smuggle enough explosives (a few pounds) into checked baggage to yield a bomb large enough to cause a plane to break up in mid-flight; after all, of all the bombs set off on airplanes between 1975 and 1999, 57 percent of those planes (thirty-five bombings) survived. Still, this means that 43 percent of planes did not survive, and bombing is a substantial problem with huge costs for airlines and for societies in general.30 After the Pan Am 103 attack, and after the in-flight explosion of TWA flight 800 off Long Island, New York, in 1996 (an explosion that many people thought was a terrorist attack, but which was due to a rare technical fault), presidential commissions were formed that made a number of recommendations about the organization of aviation security and about the technologies available to prevent bombs from bringing down planes. Indeed, the Pan Am bombing, as well as other terrorist bombings of planes, led most aviation authorities to believe that bombing would replace hijacking as the number one threat to civil aviation. As a result, significant progress was made in bomb detection technology and in hardening cargo containers and cargo holds on airplanes so that, even if a bomb were to detonate, the damage could be contained and the plane could safely land. In this case, we can say that some instrumental policy learning occurred. After the 1996 TWA crash, a commission headed by Vice President Al Gore made a sweeping set of recommendations on both aviation security and safety. Many, but not all, of these recommendations were studied and implemented, but the key recommendations on aviation security—that the Federal Aviation Administration (FAA) exercise greater oversight and control over passenger and baggage screening—were not implemented before the September 11 attacks. The FAA was in the process of implementing these recommendations, but opposition from the airlines delayed the process. The airlines were worried about the cost of new security requirements and about any inconvenience to passengers—inconveniences and costs that pale in comparison to the costs of the September 11 attacks. After the September 11 attacks, it became clear to nearly all commentators, experts and (continued)

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

279

Case Study (continued) lay people alike, that the aviation security system did not work, and that its failure greatly undermined public confidence in the safety of U.S. commercial aviation. As a result, in November of 2001, the Aviation and Transportation Security Act (ATSA) was enacted as both a means to improve security and as a way to attempt to restore public confidence in the nation’s civil aviation system. As Cobb and Primo note: There was [after September 11] a marked effect on the aviation industry. Security procedures in the airports and on planes came into question. All aspects of the security process were reexamined, severely affecting airline travel. . . . Many policy changes in aviation safety were unprecedented in their scope and in the speed at which they were enacted, but none of the issues was new to the political agenda.31 [My italics.]

The media and expert condemnation of lax aviation security after September 11 was particularly intense, focusing on the fact that the passenger screeners—the people who staff the metal detectors and X-ray machines—were poorly trained, underpaid, possibly overworked, and experienced remarkably high turnover. But these screeners, employed by contractors that were hired by the airlines to do the screening, were cheap, and security costs were kept low. It is also important to note that the attackers used small box cutters as weapons, which were not banned from airliners at the time. And yet, as Cobb and Primo note, and as I note in a later article,32 almost none of the ideas about better policy and policy failure that rose on the agenda after these attacks were new ideas. Instead, they were revived on the agenda by a focusing event. If the Pan Am 103 bombing, reinforced by greater concern about aviation safety overall after the TWA crash, led to a reasonably broad range of ideas and legislative change to address aviation security lapses, how could September 11 have happened? There are two potential places to look for failure. Most notably, the FAA failed to fully implement recommendations from the post–Pan Am and TWA presidential commissions or to fully implement congressional intent as contained in the laws enacted after these events. The recommendations were relatively routine, but important; they included more careful screening of passengers’ carry-on luggage, explosives detecting, better training for screeners to recognize suspicious passengers, and so forth. This is evidence of attempts at single-loop or instrumental policy learning in this domain, learning that was apparently unsuccessful. The second place to look is at the failure to imagine the possibility of hijacking airplanes and using them as, in essence, guided missiles. Many officials said that such a thing was “unimaginable,” but there was accumulating evidence of just such a type of an attack from intelligence sources and thwarted plots,33 such that the commission set up to investigate the September 11 attacks—known popularly as the 9/11 Commission—noted that the attacks happened because of a “failure of imagination” on the part of intelligence, antiterrorism and security experts.34 In other words, the commission was advocating that serious consideration be given to fundamentally rethinking how terrorists go about their business, which would involve something like social policy learning or double-loop learning. We do know that, after September 11, substantial changes were made to aviation security. (continued)

280 Chapter 9

Case Study (continued) Regulations and laws were enacted that required locked cockpit doors on commercial airliners. The Transportation Security Administration (TSA) was created to replace the private contractors that were hired by airlines as passenger screeners; these companies had poor records well before September 11. The TSA screeners are, by and large, better educated, better trained, and more professional than the screeners they replaced. But the system was soon jolted by the so-called “shoe-bomber” attempt to destroy American Airlines flight 63, flying from Paris to Miami in December 2001. Richard Reid, the alleged shoe bomber, hid explosives in his shoes that he attempted to detonate in mid-flight. His attempt failed, and, in a reflection of the changes in public behavior after September 11, passengers aboard the flight helped the flight crew subdue Reid. It is worthwhile to note that one of the explosives used in the shoe bombs was PETN, the same kind of explosive carried by Umar Farouk Abdulmutallab in his attempt to bring down Northwest flight 253 in 2009 with a bomb hidden in his underwear. Students of the policy process have found that policy implementation is often where attention to detail flags as the belief sets in that a problem has largely been addressed.35 The passage of legislation removes an issue from the immediate congressional agenda, and journalists pay less attention to the issue as it moves from lurid front-page headlines to the more mundane aspects of daily administration. There are many examples of legislators and executives with unattainable expectations (both in terms of management techniques and the application of technology), such as funding and other resources failing to match the perceived needs addressed by the legislation. The expectations for perfection in the aviation security system are one such example. And given that oversight of the FAA by Congress is generally “fire alarm” oversight—that is, oversight triggered by events rather than through an ongoing process—it is unsurprising that, to the extent that there was social policy learning in the years after PAA 103 and TWA 800, these lessons became less important as Congress shifted its attention away from aviation security to other aspects of aviation, and to other matters of domestic or international importance. Meanwhile, one can argue that instrumental learning continued at TSA, to the point where its rules generated complaints. The most prominent change in aviation security since the shoe bomber incident (which has led to Americans putting their shoes in the X-ray machines at airports) is the new “3-1-1” requirement that containers of liquids and gels carried aboard the plane cannot exceed 3 ounces, that all containers must fit into a one-quart zip-top bag, and that each passenger can only have one such bag in carry-on. These restrictions were put in place in response to a thwarted plot hatched in 2006 to simultaneously bomb several flights from London to North America, a plot that, if fully successful, could have exceeded the death toll from September 11. In this case, British intelligence in particular was able to stop the plot before it escalated into something much more dangerous.36 While one might question the 3-1-1 rule—and many do—it is likely that the failure of this plot, and its having been thwarted by sound intelligence work, both hindered a plot and led to the discovery of a dangerous new mode of terrorism. But the system is hardly perfect, as the December 2009 “underwear bomber” attempt demonstrated. Why did the system appear to fail in this case? First, implementation of improved policy becomes more difficult as the “low hanging fruit” is picked. There is already evidence (continued)

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

281

Case Study (continued) of this effect in the post–September 11 aviation security environment, as the more easily implemented features were addressed. The ATSA required, among other things, much more stringent passenger screening, inspection of luggage, more restrictions on the sorts of things that could be carried aboard aircraft, and, in particular, the “federalization” of the passenger screening workforce to ensure that weapons would be detected. While many of the screening processes and training for screeners had been improved shortly after the enactment of ATSA, Kenneth Mead, the inspector general of the U.S. Department of Transportation, noted in January 2002 that “while progress has been made, clearly the heavy lifting [installing explosives detection systems to screen all checked baggage and hiring a workforce] lies ahead.”37 And explosives detection machinery, in particular, was not installed rapidly after passage of ATSA, owing to technological and practical considerations—the machines were quite large, and airports were not designed to accommodate them. A similar set of events has accompanied the underwear bomber crisis, which involves making difficult and unpopular choices to deal with hard-to-detect threats to airliners. A great deal of interest was generated in using full-body scanners known as “millimeter-wave” or “backscatter” scanners. The advantage of this technology is that it creates an image that looks very much like a nude human body, which makes it difficult to conceal weapons or explosives on one’s person. On the other hand, many people are uncomfortable with the very idea of being seen virtually nude on a computer screen, even if the screener is some distance from the security checkpoint, as current protocols require. The debate about this technology is unsettled, but it appears that this attempt tipped the balance in favor of using these machines, in yet another example of a terrorist action and a security reaction. One reason why the 2001 screening changes were accomplished quickly, including the deployment of TSA employed screeners, is that they were symbolically important measures designed to add some measure of security (although, not of course, total security), while reassuring the traveling public that something was being done. The question is whether what was done legislatively is a good match with what really needed to be done. Again, one wonders whether the full-body scanners are a viable antiterrorism tool, or if they serve a symbolic value, suggesting, once again, that TSA and other nations’ security systems are “doing something.” (It’s worth noting that the underwear bomber passed through Dutch security on his Amsterdam-to-Detroit flight, rending criticism of the TSA rather odd.) The TSA’s reactive stance, coupled by what many people believe to be silly or ineffective ideas for security—such as the short-lived idea to ban passengers from leaving their seats or having anything in their laps during the final hour of flight—have led many critics to deride TSA efforts as “security theater” that is almost entirely symbolic. A good case can be made that the ATSA and the TSA have addressed important issues, considering that they had been debated but hardly implemented since at least the late 1980s. The challenge was to make sure that the TSA implemented the program contemplated in the law. This is perhaps a stiffer challenge than many of us can imagine, because terrorists have shown that they have changed their tactics since the September 11 attacks, and have found other targets or methods to accomplish their goals. (continued)

282 Chapter 9

Case Study (continued) Finally, the underwear bomber crisis raised, once again, a key theme of the post-September 11 investigations—the extent to which information and intelligence are or are not shared among the various domestic and international agencies. We know that the would-be bomber had been reported as a security concern by his own father to the U.S. Embassy in Lagos, Nigeria. We know that the CIA separately opened a file on him. The U.S. government had other information that would suggest that he might pose a threat. He purchased his ticket with cash and checked no baggage, two of the classic signs of terrorist or criminal activity. Also, the British had put Abdulmutallab on their terrorist watch list in May 2009.38 As President Obama said in January 2010, the relevant agencies failed to “connect the dots” in a way that would have prevented Abdulmutallab from boarding the plane in the first place.39 This exact terminology was used to describe the intelligence failures that followed the 2001 attacks, and suggest that, in the broader sense, the nation’s antiterrorism efforts are still falling short of the mark, even if aviation safety is better than it was ten years ago.

Key Terms Advocacy Coalition Framework Bottom-up approach Double-loop learning Implementation

Instrumental policy learning Social policy learning Policy learning Top-down approach Political learning Single-loop learning

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. What is the most important problem with top-down models of policy implementation? Cite several problems with this model. Do bottom-up approaches address these problems? Do bottom-up models have their own shortcomings? What are they? On balance, which model do you think would best aid someone who is attempting to design a policy? 2. What is a street-level bureaucrat? Give several examples. With what sort of street-level bureaucrats have you had interactions? Would you argue that these individuals have a great deal of implementation discretion; that is, latitude to make decisions about how to apply policies? What are some examples of this discretion? Is it a good idea to allow street-level bureaucrats to have discretion in policy implementation? Think of your answer from both a program management and a democratic politics perspective.

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

3. Do you believe that people in the policy process can actually learn from experience? Can you think of examples of policies that have benefited from learning from experience? Are there policies in which learning has not occurred, or in which the “wrong” lessons were learned? Is there a difference between policies where there is successful learning and policies where learning is more difficult to achieve? 4. Why do Goggin and his colleagues believe that implementation is as much a matter of negotiation and communication as it is a matter of command? When considering this question, remember the organization of American government and how power is shared within that organization. 5. As you know, Ingram and Mann argue that policy failure is highly subjective, and that what appears to be policy failure can be a result of, among other things, excessive policy demand, or the fact that failure in one policy area is a function of spillovers from other policy areas that prevent a policy from being fully implemented. Many stories in newspapers and on television, particularly those that claim to be “investigative reporting,” contain coverage of supposed policy failures. Such stories are usually serious and are not the same as stories about personal corruption and scandal. For this activity, find a story or series of stories about what you believe is a policy failure (it is probably easier to use print media than TV and radio). What kinds of arguments in favor of failure are being made? Are any arguments presented in these news stories that contradict claims of policy failure? Are the claims of policy failure reasonable, given what you know about the subjectivity of such claims? Can you think of alternative explanations of “failure” that aren’t explored in the story? Why do you think that the stories of failure that are in the media are so prominent, while others are less so? Additional Reading While it is indeed true that implementation concerns go back many years before the 1970s, the book that really started policy scientists thinking carefully about implementation is Jeffery Pressman and Aaron Wildavsky, Implementation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973). Still required reading in many courses on public policy and policy implementation, this book describes the problems that accompanied the implementation of economic development projects at the Port of Oakland and the Oakland International Airport. The authors find that implementation is made difficult by the “complexity of joint action.” Research from the “second generation” of implementation studies, which sought to create more advanced theories of implementation, include Richard Elmore, “Backward Mapping: Implementation Research and Policy Decisions,” Political Science Quarterly 94, no. 4 (Winter 1979): 601–16; Daniel Mazmanian and Paul Sabatier, Implementation and Public Policy (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989); and Carl

283

284 Chapter 9 Van Horn, Policy Implementation in the Federal System: National Goals and Local Implementers (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1979).One of my favorite texts in the so-called third generation of implementation research is Malcolm L. Goggin, Ann O’M. Bowman, James P. Lester, and Laurence J. O’Toole, Jr., Implementation Theory and Practice: Toward a Third Generation (Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman/ Little Brown, 1990). This volume is a synthesis of top-down and bottom-up approaches to implementation in what the authors call a “communications” model of implementation. In their model, the top policy designers send implementation messages that are received and interpreted by targets and intermediaries. In the late 1990s, a lively debate took place in Policy Currents, the then-newsletter of the public policy section of the American Political Science Association. That debate started with James P. Lester and Malcom L. Goggin, “Back to the Future: The Rediscovery of Implementation Studies,” Policy Currents 8, no. 3 (1998): 1–9, http://apsapolicysection.org/v018_3/83.pdf (accessed January 4, 2010). The series of articles continues in volume 8, no. 4. On the question of policy failure, Helen Ingram and Dean Mann’s “Policy Failure: An Issue Deserving Attention,” in Why Policies Succeed or Fail, edited by Helen Ingram and Dean Mann (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1980), explores some reasons that policies fail—or are claimed to have failed. The authors argue that the question of policy failure deserves further study to determine whether policies are really failing, why they fail, and to what extent their failure is influenced by other, overlapping policies and goals. In “Policy Learning and Failure,” Journal of Public Policy 12, no. 4 (1992): 331–54, Peter May links policy failure or the perception of failure to learning, and outlines the three different styles of learning described in this chapter. This argument was very influential in my recent book Lessons of Disaster (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006), which also relies heavily on Peter May’s book. In that book I also relied on Colin J. Bennett and Michael Howlett, “The Lessons of Learning: Reconciling Theories of Policy Learning and Policy Change,” Policy Sciences 25, no. 4 (1992): 275–94; Peter A. Hall, “Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State: The Case of Economic Policy Making in Britain,” Comparative Politics 25 (1993): 275–96; and Paul Sabatier and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith, Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1993). Notes 1. Neal Ryan, “Unraveling Conceptual Developments in Implementation Analysis,” Australian Journal of Public Administration 54, no. 1 (1995): 65–81. 2. Kevin B. Smith and Christopher W. Larimer, The Public Policy Primer (Boulder, CO: Westview, 2009), 155–156. 3. Smith and Larimer, chapter 7. 4. Jeffery Pressman and Aaron Wildavsky, Implementation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973); Martha Derthick, New Towns in Town (Washington, DC: Urban Institute, 1972). 5. Carl E. Van Horn and Donald S. Van Meter, “The Implementation of Intergovernmental Policy,” in Public

Policy Implementation, Failure,

and

Learning

285

Policy Making in a Federal System, ed. Charles O. Jones and Robert D. Thomas (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1976); Carl Van Horn, Policy Implementation in the Federal System: National Goals and Local Implementers (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1979); Daniel Mazmanian and Paul Sabatier, Implementation and Public Policy (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989). 6. Ryan, “Unraveling Conceptual Developments.” 7. Caroline Dyer, “Researching the Implementation of Educational Policy: A Backward Mapping Approach,” Comparative Education 35, no. 1 (1999): 45–62. 8. “About Us: Mission,” United States Forest Service, http://www.fs.fed.us/aboutus/mission.shtml (accessed January 19, 2010). 9. James E. Anderson, Public Policymaking, 5th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2002): 205–10. 10. Paul A. Sabatier, “Top-Down and Bottom-Up Approaches in Implementation Research: A Critical Analysis and Suggested Synthesis,” Journal of Public Policy 6, no. 1 (1986): 21–48. 11. Malcolm L. Goggin, Ann O’M. Bowman, James P. Lester, and Laurence J. O’Toole Jr., Implementation Theory and Practice: Toward a Third Generation (Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman/Little Brown, 1990). 12. Sabatier, “Top-Down and Bottom-Up,” 25. 13. Michael Lipsky, “Street Level Bureaucracy and the Analysis of Urban Reform,” Urban Affairs Quarterly 6 (1971): 391–409. 14. Richard Elmore, “Backward Mapping: Implementation Research and Policy Decisions,” Political Science Quarterly 94, no. 4 (Winter 1979): 601–16. 15. Rene Torenvlied, “Political Control of Implementation Agencies,” Policy Sciences 8, no. 1 (1996): 25–57. 16. Peter J. May, “Reconsidering Policy Design: Policies and Publics,” Journal of Public Policy 11, no. 2 (1990): 187–206. 17. Anne Schneider and Helen Ingram, “The Social Construction of Target Populations: Implications for Politics and Policy,” American Political Science Review 87, no. 2 (1993): 334–48. 18. Richard Elmore, “Forward and Backward Mapping,” in Policy Implementation in Federal and Unitary Systems, ed. K. Hanf and T. Toonen (Dordrecht, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985): 33–70. 19. Sabatier, “Top-Down and Bottom-Up,” 37–38. Laurence O’Toole, “Policy Recommendations for Multi-Actor Implementation: An Assessment of the Field,” Journal of Public Policy 6, no. 2 (1986): 181–210. 20. Sabatier, “Top-Down and Bottom-Up,” 39. 21. Goggin, Bowman, Lester, and O’Toole, Implementation Theory and Practice. 22. Paul C. Light, Government’s Greatest Achievements: From Civil Rights to Homeland Security (Washington DC: Brookings Institution, 2002). 23. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann, “Policy Failure: An Issue Deserving Attention,” in Why Policies Succeed or Fail, ed. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1980), 12. 24. Colin J. Bennett and Michael Howlett, “The Lessons of Learning: Reconciling Theories of Policy Learning and Policy Change,” Policy Sciences 25, no. 3 (1992): 275–94. 25. Bennett and Howlett, “The Lessons of Learning,” p. 276, quoting Peter A. Hall, “Policy Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State,” presented at the International Political Science Association, Washington D.C. 26. Peter M. Senge, The Fifth Discipline: The Art and Practice of the Learning Organization, rev. ed. (New York: Doubleday/Currency, 2006); Chris Argyris, On Organizational Learning. 2d ed. (Malden, MA: Blackwell Business, 1999). 27. Chris Argyris and Donald A. Schön, Organizational Learning: A Theory of Action Perspective (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co., 1978). 28. Paul A. Sabatier, “An Advocacy Coalition Framework of Policy Change and the Role of Policy-Oriented Learning Therein,” Policy Sciences 21 (1988): 129–68; Peter J. May, “Policy Learning and Failure,” Journal of Public Policy 12, no. 4 (1992): 331–54; George J. Busenberg, “Learning in Organizations and Public Policy,” Journal of Public Policy 21, no. 2 (2001): 173–89. 29. May, “Policy Learning and Failure,” 336. 30. National Research Council (U.S.), Panel on Assessment of Technologies Deployed to Improve Aviation Security, Assessment of Technologies Deployed to Improve Aviation Security (Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 1999), chapter 5.

286 Chapter 9 31. Roger W. Cobb and David M. Primo, The Plane Truth: Airline Crashes, the Media, and Transportation Policy (Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 2003), 120. 32. Thomas A. Birkland, “Learning and Policy Improvement after Disaster: The Case of Aviation Security,” American Behavioral Scientist 48, no. 3 (2004): 341–64. 33. Gregg Easterbrook, “The All-Too-Friendly Skies: Security as an Afterthought,” in How Did This Happen? Terrorism and the New War, ed. J.F. Hodge Jr. and G. Rose (New York: Public Affairs, 2001): 162–81. 34. National Commission on Terrorist Attacks upon the United States, The 9/11 Commission Report: Final Report of the National Commission on Terrorist Attacks Upon the United States, official government ed. (Washington, DC: National Commission on Terrorist Attacks upon the United States, U.S. Government Printing Office, 2004). 35. David C. Nice and Ashley Grosse, “The Evolution of Emergency Management in America: From a Painful Past to Promising but Uncertain Future,” in Handbook of Crisis and Emergency Management, ed. A. Farazmand (New York: Marcel Dekker, 2001): 55–67. 36. Duncan Gardham, “Airline Terror Trial: The Bomb Plot to Kill 10,000 People,” The Telegraph, September 7, 2009, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/terrorism-in-the-uk/6153243/Airline-terror-trial-The-bomb-plotto-kill-10000-people.html (accessed January 19, 2009). 37. Kenneth Mead, Committee on Transportation and Infrastructure, Subcommittee on Aviation, U.S. House of Representatives, “Challenges Facing TSA in Implementing the Aviation and Transportation Security Act,” January 23, 2002, http://www.oig.dot.gov/library-item/4126 (accessed January 10, 2010). 38. Mark Thompson, “Why Was the Accused Bomber Banned in Britain, Not the U.S.? Time, December 28, 2009, http://www.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1950280,00.html (accessed January 19, 2010). 39. Todd Spangler, “Obama: Officials ‘Failed to Connect the Dots’ in Botched Attack,” Detroit Free Press, January 5, 2010, http://www.freep.com/article/20100105/NEWS07/100105022/1322/Obama-Officials-failed-toconnect-the-dots-in-botched-attack (accessed January 19, 2010).

Science and Theory in the Study of Public Policy Chapter at a Glance The Study of Policy as a Scientific Endeavor Science in the Policy Process Policy Studies as Science The Idea of Policy Theory A Science of the Policy Process Heeding the Call for Improved Policy Theory Major Models of the Policy Process Kingdon’s Streams Metaphor The Advocacy Coalition Framework Punctuated Equilibrium Institutional Analysis and Development Conclusion Key Terms Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research Additional Reading

The Study of Policy as a Scientific Endeavor The preceding chapters laid a foundation to help you understand the current theories of the policy process that I describe in this chapter. These theories have dominated public policy theory for the past twenty-five years, and remain influential because scholars have found them to be useful for explaining important aspects of the public policy process. However, like most social science theories, they do not explain all the phenomena that comprise the policy process. This is not, of course, an indictment of these theories. Rather, it suggests that the search for a unified theory of the policy process or, logically, a unified theory of politics, may be an impossible goal. The challenges to theory building are described in this chapter. The scientific study of the policy process—and of building models and theories of how public policy is made—is one of the most challenging endeavors in social science, and while no “final” theory of the process has ever been developed, we can say that remarkable progress in theory building has been made since the early 1980s.

287

10 CHAPTER

288 Chapter 10 This chapter defines the concept of policy science and explains why the advanced study of public policy is a scientific endeavor. I describe the dominant theories of the policy process, but bear in mind that these descriptions are, of course, no substitute for careful study of these theories; my goal is to provide you with a basic sense of what the theories are and how they relate to each other. Many readers of this book will not ultimately engage in the advanced academic study of policy making, but these theories are worth consideration in helping to understand the broader sweep of the policy process, and how all the parts of the process fit together. Science in the Policy Process Harold Lasswell’s call for a science of public policy was driven by a desire to generate sound social science, but also by the desire to solve problems, much the same way that science was used to unlock the atom or cure diseases. Lasswell, like many social scientists and reformers of the 1940s through the 1960s, felt that the increasingly sophisticated research techniques available to social scientists would allow them to study public problems and to propose solutions to them. While one use of science is to inform social decision making on a range of issues, from nuclear war to medicine to mass transit, a great deal of scientific endeavor is not solely or simply driven by the desire to learn about individual problems and their solutions. Often science is a function of a desire to gain knowledge of the social world. Many of the scholars whose work is described in this book are interested in public policy because they can apply the tools of their disciplines to social problems, thereby gaining greater understanding of society and politics as a whole while contributing to change for the better. Harold Lasswell argued that quantitative analysis and the scientific method were important elements of any policy science. However, you should not confuse “the scientific method” with “statistics,” as many students do, particularly if their first exposure to research methods, theory building, and hypothesis testing comes in a statistical methods course. Often, these courses are more about running computer software than on what it means to develop a theory, establish hypotheses, and devise the appropriate tests. If anything, these courses focus on the latter, while assuming (often wrongly) that students have had some exposure to theory building and research design. Policy Studies as Science normative. arguments are arguments based on values and beliefs; positive arguments are those based on empirical evidence.

While Lasswell was motivated by a desire to harness science to explain the policy process and to help solve social problems, the science of public policy and policy analysis have generally fallen short of his vision of a broadly useful policy science. But creating policy theories has, at least in political science, shifted to the development and testing of how the system works, with less emphasis on how it should work; that is, we have shifted from a normative to a positive direction.

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

The proliferation of theory building without testing or systematic refinement led George Greenberg and his colleagues to assert that the explosion of modeling needed to yield to actual empirical testing of theories. These tests would allow policy scholars to gain a better sense of which theories work better than others.1 Paul Sabatier, echoing this sentiment, promotes a research agenda to improve the making and testing of policy theories.2 Why is theory important when there are real-world problems to solve? It would be simple enough to dismiss this question by saying that theory is what academic researchers do, across all disciplines. Unlike folk wisdom or craft knowledge, scientific researchers create theories to try to understand why it is that a particular collection of observations—for example, case studies—yield broadly similar outcomes. For example, the implementation literature has, for the most part, noted that most public policies fail to achieve all the goals their most ardent proponents claimed that they would meet. Of course, there are key differences between implementation of, say, social security programs, environmental policies, and urban development policies, all of which have been studied by academics and pursued by practitioners. These cases differ, but the phenomena that they share allow us to develop general concepts that apply to more than one case or problem. In creating these general concepts or “rules,” we can structure our thinking about the policy process and its application to real-world situations. The Idea of Policy Theory Before we consider these theories of the process in greater detail, we should take a moment to consider just what we mean by theory. Theory is important because, without it, it is hard to really understand how we can generalize the process to more than some disconnected case studies. What is a theory, after all? The Oxford English Dictionary provides the following definition: A scheme or system of ideas or statements held as an explanation or account of a group of facts or phenomena; a hypothesis that has been confirmed or established by observation or experiment, and is propounded or accepted as accounting for the known facts; a statement of what are held to be the general laws, principles, or causes of something known or observed.

A theory is therefore not just a set of ideas; it is a system of ideas that helps to explain things that happen in the world. The definition goes on to note that theory is a hypothesis that is tested and “a statement of . . . the general laws, principles and causes” of something. Merriam-Webster Online defines the term somewhat differently: “a plausible or scientifically acceptable general principle or body of principles offered to explain phenomena.” This definition is well suited to our discussion. The point of this definition is that a theory is “general”; that is, it can be general-

289

290 Chapter 10 ized to a broad range of phenomena within a field of study. Thus, we have a theory of the policy process, not individual theories about energy policy, environmental policy, social welfare policy, morality policy, and the like; even though these are different policy areas and differ in many ways, a sound theory can explain general phenomena that occur across policy domains. The different policy typologies described in chapter 7 are examples of this type of theory. The difference, then, between talking about public policy and studying it is simple: we study it in a scientific way, developing and testing theories of the process. Theories can be developed either deductively or inductively. In a deductive process we develop a theory of how we believe the world works, develop a hypotheses, gather data—either by direct observation or via another source—and then test the hypotheses using various statistical and logical techniques. In an inductive study we build models based on observation, discern apparent patterns in the world and form tentative hypotheses that we test and refine until a theory is developed. One should not make too much of the difference between these two methods of theory construction; indeed, a very clear explanation of this process notes that “it doesn’t take a rocket scientist to see that we could assemble the two graphs above into a single circular one that continually cycles from theories down to observations and back up again to theories.”3 A sound theory is also one that is “scientifically” acceptable. But what does this mean? Philosophers of science and scientists themselves argue that a good theory should generate a set of hypotheses about the world and subject them to tests. If such hypotheses are not falsifiable, then they are not, by definition, hypotheses. In science, we generally state a hypothesis in the form of a “null hypothesis.” For example, if our theory is that “the greater the number of interest groups that form around an issue, the greater the attention paid to the issue by Congress,” the null hypothesis would be: “The extent of interest group participation in an issue has no influence on the Congressional agenda.” We do this because as Karl Popper has argued, it is easier to prove something false than it is to prove something true. A Science of the Policy Process So far, we have discussed various models of the policy process without seriously considering what a model of the policy process is or how to assess whether, in Thomas Dye’s words, a model “is helping or not.” Dye considers this question in some detail. He says that “a model is merely an abstraction or representation of political life.”4 We can clarify this idea by thinking about the difference between, say, a model airplane and a real airplane. A model airplane is merely an approximation of the real thing. While the model airplane has wings, a propeller, a tail, landing gear, and the like, it is a simplified version of the “real thing”; it may not have a working engine or may not even actually fly. But the model tells us enough to help us learn about an airplane. Models vary in their complexity and faithfulness to the

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

actual thing they represent based on the use to which we want to put the model. And, of course, if the model becomes as complex as the thing it is modeling, it may not help much at all.5 Similarly, our models of the policy process do not reproduce every aspect of the policy process, for such a model would be nearly impossible to create. After all, what are “all” the elements of the process? The policy process is complex, so we do not design models to account for every aspect of public policy making. Instead, social scientists strive to create so-called middle-range theory that is readily testable using existing data and knowledge, a more realistic endeavor than attempting to create a “theory of everything.” We create theory in this way to explain general principles without becoming so bogged down in detail that the essence of what we seek to explain is lost. This is because good models, according to Dye, seek to order and simplify reality, identify what is significant about a system, are congruent with reality, communicate meaningful information about the policy process, direct inquiry and research, and suggest explanations of public policy. In the end, Dye argues that models “should suggest hypotheses about the causes and consequences of public policy.”6 There’s no negative connotation to the notion of middle-range theory. Indeed, much of science consists of middle-range theory, and we can say with confidence that policy theorists’ work is scientific because it is not merely descriptive. Those of us who study social systems—how economic transactions take place, how communities coalesce, how families get along, how policy decisions are made, why there are wars, how people developed language—do not practice our science the way natural scientists do. We do not generally work in labs; instead, we observe societies and people, which are inherently dynamic and changing. While some disciplines have explored experimental designs, such as behavioral economics and game theory, many of us in the social scientists can only rely on “quasi-experimental” research in which we try to hold certain variables constant, with varying degrees of success.7 But we share with scientists the desire to broaden human knowledge, which is ultimately what the word “science” means. Merriam-Webster’s Collegiate Dictionary gives the derivation of the word science as the Latin word scientia, meaning “having knowledge.” Webster’s defines science as “the state of knowing: knowledge as distinguished from ignorance or misunderstanding.” The following example illustrates this very well. When I was in junior high school, one of our science teachers explained the differences between ancient Greek and modern methods of pursuing scientific knowledge. He said that there was once a debate in Greece over whether men had more teeth than women. A number of reasons were given for men having the most teeth: larger jaw and overall body size, bigger appetites, the supposed physical superiority of men over women. The Greeks, our teacher told us, failed to do an obvious thing: look in the mouths of men and women and count up how many teeth they have. This seems obvi-

291

292 Chapter 10 One Big Happy IT WAS ORIGINALLY IT WAS ORIGINALLY

OF TRIVIA

IT WAS ORIGINALLY IT WAS ORIGINALLY IT WAS ORIGINALLY IT WAS ORIGINALLY IT WAS ORIGINALLY

WHY WHY WHY

OF TRIVIA OF TRIVIA

WHY

OF TRIVIA

Source: One Big Happy reprinted by permission of Rick Detorie and Creators Syndicate, Inc. scientific method. The system most commonly used in Western science for gaining knowledge. It involves identifying a problem, gathering data, and testing hypotheses.

ous to us because we are steeped in the logic of the Enlightenment. One of the outgrowths of the Enlightenment was the development of empirical science; that is, science based on the observation of a phenomenon or the collection of data about a phenomenon. Since we are so steeped in this tradition, it seems absurd to argue about the number of teeth in men’s and women’s mouths. Of course, this story may be an anecdote told simply to make a point about the difference between the scientific method and other, less successful ways of learning things. But the story makes a useful point: that observation is an important tool in the empirical scientist’s tool kit. From a scientific perspective, evidence that is gathered and described using the scientific method is superior, we believe, to evidence offered through anecdotes and stories. It is superior by virtue of its method. We seek to apply the best methods to our work—to ensure that our data and conclusions are reliable, valid, and, ultimately, useful in advancing knowledge. To achieve this goal, we try to create the strongest research designs, and report our results in the form of aggregate data, rather than as separate, disconnected stories without a method to assess whether the stories reveal a trend. Scientific research sometimes runs counter to the “common wisdom” dispensed in anecdotes. As steeped as we are in Enlightenment notions of method, evidence, and proof, we often see political debate reduced to the level of anecdotes or stories, rather than careful analysis. We should neither be surprised nor confused by this—day-to-day politics is not the province of theory development, testing, careful logic, and the accumulation of evidence. Rather, it is about telling stories—about health insurance horror stories that turn out not to be true;8 about people who buy expensive steaks with food stamps;9 about how kids who commit acts of violence at school do so because of the malign influence of popular music, video games, or television;10 or about how New Orleans was intentionally left to wither after Hurricane Katrina because of ideological bias or institutional racism.11

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

I use these examples to illustrate the difference between the scientific analysis of public policies and the political analysis of policies that do not rely primarily or solely on what we usually think of as science. The stories people (and, quite often, their elected officials and journalists) tell are known as anecdotes, the collection of which constitutes what we call anecdotal evidence. Anecdotes are quite powerful in the debate over policies. President Ronald Reagan was particularly fond of using anecdotes to illustrate policy problems, and presidents and other elected officials before and since Reagan have told stories to great rhetorical effect. The problem with anecdotes is that they are little tidbits of information that are unsystematically gathered and that reflect the biases of the person relating the story. A political conservative is likely to tell stories extolling the virtues of individual initiative and limited government, while her liberal counterpart will often spin tales of the proper role and function of government in ensuring our quality of life. And, even if the anecdotes are based on correct information with respect to one individual story, the accumulation of similar anecdotes may—or may not—serve as data to confirm or deny a trend or phenomenon. The differences between evidence and anecdote are outlined in Table 10.1. A recent example is the contrast between the discussion of a mining method sometimes called “mountaintop removal” mining in Appalachia on The Diane Rehm Show,12 a highly regarded public affairs talk show on National Public Radio, and an article published on the subject in the journal Science. On the radio show, a representative of the coal mining industry claimed that his firm did not engage in environmentally damaging practices that result in water pollution, coal dust, the destruction of streams, profound human health consequences, and other outcomes of this technique. On the other hand, the Science article—which underwent extensive peer review—revealed a large body of existing research and new water quality data to show that mountaintop removal mining had profound consequences for the environment. This is a good case of science attempting to influence policy by the careful application of the scientific method, rather than stories and anecdotes. This is not to say that good natural or policy science can or will carry the day. The authors of the study strongly urged proper regulatory action: Regulators should no longer ignore rigorous science. The United States should take leadership on these issues, particularly since surface mining in many developing countries is expected to grow extensively.13

Despite the weight of scientific evidence, and contradicting its own campaign promises, the Obama administration issued permits to allow a mountaintop mining operation to proceed, much to the dismay of the environmentalists and scientists who are concerned with the environmental and human impacts of this practice.14 This one small example illustrates that, while we can apply scientific methods to studying policy, it is unreasonable to expect participants in policy making to act

293

anecdotal evidence. Evidence offered in policy debates that is based on stories and personal experience rather than empirical evidence.

peer review. A process in which articles published in academic journals have been submitted to other experts in the same field to determine the suitability of the article for publication, based on the existing norms and body of knowledge of the profession.

294 Chapter 10 Table 10.1 Anecdotes and Evidence Description

How it is used

Strengths/rationale

Anecdotes

Stories told to illustrate a problem or the failure of a policy, such as “I saw someone buy a steak with a food stamp” or “welfare queen” stories.

To justify starting or stopping programs by providing an easily understood story with obvious conclusions and underlying normative or moral principles.

Anecdotes are good for staking out a position on an issue, or for motivating people to believe a certain way. They are less useful as part of serious analysis, because they do not delve deeply into how programs work.

Evidence from scientific study

Conclusions reached through scientific study of a problem or of the outcomes of a policy.

To justify starting or stopping programs by providing the most scientifically sound information that policy makers can use to make decisions.

Scientific evidence is much stronger than anecdotes in understanding how and why things work the way they do. However, the results of scientific study are often controversial and unpopular, and sometimes run counter to popular expectations.

like a set of rational theory builders and hypothesis testers. Decision makers often do not have the luxury of relying solely on scientific methods or findings, because the practice of politics is as much art as it is science. Indeed, so many issues in public policy, such as policies relating to pornography, abortion, teenage pregnancy, and other controversial matters of public and private morality, are so difficult to address through scientific or rational policy analysis that they are known as “transscientific” problems; they transcend the ability of “science,” however defined, to address them.15 In this mining case, the president and the regulatory agencies must weigh many competing interests: miners, mining companies, the power companies that make electricity by burning coal, local residents (some of whom work at the mines, and some of whom suffer the mines’ environmental damage), natural scientists, and environmentalists. How a policy maker decides what decision to make is often guided by a sense of what is possible or sensible politically, not what is the “best” policy from a scientific perspective. To a considerable extent, then, this decision is trans-scientific. This is not to say that science has no role in the policy process. We do know that natural, physical, and social science play a big role in policy. After all, health professionals and epidemiologists led the efforts to contain the so-called “swine flu” (H1N1) virus in 2009–2010. Scientists and engineers led efforts to build the atomic bomb, build the great power dams, develop the Internet and other communications technologies, improve food safety, control polio, and so on. The list of such achievements is long, and is a symbol of the scientific and creative energy that characterized twentieth-century science. But there are often times where science’s role can be controversial or even peripheral in policy debate. And, in particularly contentious policy domains, science can be actively disdained by participants in

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

the process. The debate over global climate change is a case in point: the scientific community has been subject to withering attacks on the science, including the methods used and the substantive meaning of their research findings. Scientists’ work has not been aided by those who make claims about how disasters like Hurricane Katrina are a direct consequences of global climate change. On the other hand, it is clear that the science is either used or pilloried to make political points; as an old saying goes, “politicians use science the way drunks use lampposts—for support, not for illumination.” In the end, we can say that the application of scientific and policy analytic tools to decision making in public policy is more complicated than ever before, in large part because the optimism that proponents of scientific policy analysis brought to the enterprise in the 1960s was, by the 1970s, unredeemed. At the same time, scientific policy analysis—but not its analytical substance—had been taken up by so many participants in policy making that the language and logic of “policy analysis” based on scientific and social scientific methods had become a part of the ebb and flow of politics in general. There was no special claim to expertise or methodological excellence that would set policy science apart from decisions made in the seemingly irrational world of everyday politics.16 Heeding the Call for Improved Policy Theory Policy studies, like many social sciences, are sometimes said to lag behind the natural sciences because we still have not developed what McCool calls a “dominant theoretical tradition,” or what Thomas Kuhn would call, in the natural sciences, a “paradigm.”17 For example, McCool notes that Thomas Dye’s Understanding Public Policy18 lists and discusses eight theoretical traditions in policy study. All eight are treated as equally useful, even though some of them may actually conflict, such as the theories that support pluralism versus those that suggest a more elitist model of government. And understanding and developing policy theory can be difficult because of the wide variation in terminology in the various texts and policy studies. Daniel McCool lists three different definitions of policy science taken from the policy literature, two definitions of policy studies, three definitions of policy evaluation, and four definitions of policy analysis. “The conceptual distinction between these terms,” he argues, “is indistinct.” McCool also lists five definitions of the term “theory” and four each of “model” and “concept,” the definitions of which overlap considerably. With all these overlapping and sometimes confusing definitions, it is understandable that theory seems so complex and unhelpful to theorists and practitioners alike. But theories of public policy making—and the act of developing and testing theory—are important because they are the very tools that help us to understand the broader questions of public policy. The proliferation of theory building without testing and refinement of something that looks like a paradigm or at least a set of

295

296 Chapter 10 principles for the study of public policy led George Greenberg and his colleagues to assert that the explosion of modeling needed to yield to actual empirical testing of theories. These tests would allow policy scholars to gain a better sense of which theories work better than others.19 Paul Sabatier, echoing this sentiment, promotes a research agenda to improve the making and testing of policy theories.20 Major Models of the Policy Process To a considerable extent, calls for developing and testing theories have been heeded. Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith, in their 1993 text Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach, further refine Paul Sabatier’s Advocacy Coalition Framework and invite other policy scholars to help test it. It is important to note that all the major theories described here have been applied and tested by a wide range of policy scholars.21 Frank Baumgartner and Bryan Jones, in Agendas and Instability in American Politics, extensively study how issues gain or lose prominence in American politics by analyzing congressional hearings and news coverage of key policy areas. They gathered an immense database of legislative, regulatory, and media information that is available to all researchers at the Policy Agendas Project Web site.22 Their research yields two important insights: First, using the evidence derived from congressional hearings and media coverage of issues, Baumgartner and Jones find that American politics is characterized by long periods of policy stability followed by sudden change in the agenda and in policy. Second, Baumgartner and Jones show how congressional hearing data can be used to track how much attention is being paid to particular issues. This methodological contribution—and their publicly available dataset—may be as important as the main conclusions of the study, because it shows how one can use congressional data to study the public policy process and how one can build a fairly sophisticated model or at least a story of why policy making seems so slow or even static at one moment and highly dynamic the next.23 Because there are so many models, and because they are analytically quite rich, space permits only a summary of three prominent models here: John Kingdon’s “streams” metaphor of public policy, Paul Sabatier’s Advocacy Coalition Framework, and Frank Baumgartner and Bryan Jones’s “punctuated equilibrium” model of agenda and policy processes. I also touch on Elinor Ostrom’s Institutional Analysis and Development approach. The creation of these theories was driven by many motivations, but one thing they have in common is an implicit or explicit rejection of the stages model as a theory of the policy process outlined in chapter 1. This is not to deny the substantial analytic and instructional value of the stages heuristic, stages model, or whatever one chooses to call it.24 Indeed, the organization of this textbook owes a great deal to this formulation. Rather, I summarize these theories because they seek to overcome the stages model’s obvious shortcomings—in particular, its failure to provide a predictive theory of policy making.

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

297

Kingdon’s Streams Metaphor In Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies,25 John Kingdon argues that issues gain agenda status, and alternative solutions are selected, when elements of three “streams” come together. The notion of streams is borrowed from March, Cohen, and Olsen’s idea of how ideas combine in “garbage cans” in nearly anarchic decision-making environments, like universities, in which decision-making powers are broadly distributed. March and his colleagues argued that ideas flow in to and out of “garbage cans” of ideas, and get mixed and matched with other ideas, whereupon the ideas are taken up by other actors and promoted to decision makers. Kingdon’s innovation was to organize and label these streams of ideas and facts into the problem, policies, and politics streams in the policy process. Each of these three streams contains various individuals, groups, agencies, and institutions that are involved in the policy-making process. The problem stream encompasses the attributes of a problem and whether it is getting better or worse, whether it has suddenly sprung into public and elite consciousness through a focusing event, and whether it is solvable with the alternatives available in the policy stream. The policy stream contains the potential ideas that could be advocated as solutions to a problem. The politics stream encompasses the state of politics and public opinion—the sort of public opinion variables reviewed in chapter 2. All three streams suggest different types of variables that can be examined for their influence on the agenda and on decision making. Within any particular problem area, these streams run parallel and somewhat independently of each other in a policy area or domain until something happens to cause two or more of the streams to meet in a “window of opportunity.” This window is the possibility of policy change, but the opening of the window does not guarantee that policy change will occur. That trigger can be a change in our understanding of the problem, a change in the political stream that is favorable to policy change, a change in our understanding of the tractability of the problem given current solutions, or a focusing event that draws attention to a problem and helps open a window of opportunity. The streams metaphor is graphically represented in Figure 10.1. Paul Sabatier argues that the streams metaphor may be an incomplete description of policy making because it does not describe the policy process beyond the opening of the window of opportunity.26 However, while Kingdon is best known for the streams metaphor, he devotes considerable attention to alternative selection, noting that, while the Congress has considerable power in winnowing down the range of acceptable policies, the president is usually most influential in making the ultimate decision as to which policy to adopt. Furthermore, Nikolaos Zahariadis argues that the streams approach can be applied to decision opportunities, not simply agendasetting opportunities; a decision to make new or change existing policy may be more likely when the streams come together.27

streams metaphor. The metaphor used to describe Kingdon’s approach to the policy process, in which we can think of the politics, problem, and policy streams coming together in a “window of opportunity” for policy change.

298 Chapter 10 Figure 10.1â•… Kingdon’s Streams Metaphor

Problem Stream Window of opportunity

Policy Stream

Politics Stream

Time

For example, the decisions by agencies to adopt more stringent aviation safety and security standards were often driven by windows of opportunity that opened after crashes or terrorist attacks—often, these decisions involved the stricter application of rules or the assumption of greater regulatory power than the agency had used before. Thus, Kingdon provides a rich and multilayered metaphor of policy making from the early acceptance of new ideas about public problems to the active considerations of solutions as new public policy. The Advocacy Coalition Framework

Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF). A model or framework for understanding the interactions of groups and coalitions of groups called advocacy coalitions. In the frame�work, typically two to four coalitions form based on shared beliefs on policy issues. Paul Sabatier is the primary developer of the ACF, which has been applied to studies of im� ple�men�tation, policy change, and learning.

Sabatier’s Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF) is an important model of the policy process, based on the idea that interest groups are organized in policy communities within a policy domain. The most recent version of this framework is depicted in Figure 10.2. Like the streams metaphor, Sabatier’s ACF encompasses a variety of individual and institutional actors, and it views policy making as an iterative process that runs over years or decades. The ACF also considers the mechanisms for policy change (not simply the possibility for change, as in the streams metaphor) and more consciously encompasses the influence of implementation and feedback on the system. In the ACF, policy making is influenced both by “relatively stable” system parameters and by “dynamic (system) events,” with the interaction between the two promoting or inhibiting policy making. The stable parameters include the basic attributes of the problem area, the basic distribution of natural resources in the society, the fundamental cultural values and social structure, and the basic legal structure, which in the United States is the constitutional framework and judicial norms. The dynamic features of the system include changes in socioeconomic conditions and technology, changes in public opinion, changes in systemic governing coalitions (partisan balance in the legislature or the executive branch, for example), and policy decisions and impacts from other subsystems. Change in the governing coalition cor-

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

299

Figure 10.2â•… The Advocacy Coalition Framework

RELATIVELY STABlE PARAMETERS

1. Basic allribulesof

the problem 81811 (good) 2. Basicdistribution of nallfal rescuces 3. Fundamental sociocIMuraI values and social slructlJe 4 Basic constitutional structure (rules)

Degree of consensus needed for major policy chs1ge

1. Changesin socioeoonomic concitions 2. Changes in p!JlIic opinion 3. Changes in sysiemicgoveming

CaaitionA a. Poiey Beliefs b.Reswoes

CoosII'IIirU

and

EXTERNAl (SYSlEM) EVENTS

POLICY SUBSYSTEM Policy Brokers

S1rategyA1 !!guidanca instnmm

CoaIitionB a. Policy Beliefs b. Resources

StralegyB1

reguidance

instruments

Deasionsby Govemmental Authorities

Rescuces of

Institutional Rules, Resouroe Allocations, and Appointments

Subsyslem Policy 0utpUs

AdOJS

coalition

4. Policydecisions and impacts from other

Policy Impacts

subsystems

Source: From Theories of the Policy Process, by Paul A. Sabatier. Copyright © 2007 by Paul A. Sabatier. Reprinted by permission of Westview Press, a member of Perseus Books, L.L.C.

responds to one example of change in the politics stream in Kingdon’s model, while changes in socioeconomic and technological conditions influence the problem and policy streams. The activities of other subsystems can influence the policy, politics, and problem streams as their activities spill over into other policy domains. In the ACF, two to four advocacy coalitions typically form in a particular policy domain when groups coalesce around a shared set of core values and beliefs. These groups engage in policy debate, competing and compromising on solutions based on their core values and beliefs. Competition between coalitions is mediated by policy brokers who have a stake in resolving the problem, either on substantive grounds or because of their interest in maintaining political harmony in the system. These brokers are more likely to succeed when they can develop compromises that do not threaten either advocacy coalition’s core beliefs and values. Policy change is much less likely if polarization of advocacy coalitions that the groups’ peripheral beliefs provide little or no opportunity for shared interests.

300 Chapter 10 Here’s an example of how two very different types of interests can find common ground on an issue of common concern, and form alliances and a potential advocacy coalition. Political conservatives, many of whom identify as religious conservatives or evangelicals, are strongly opposed to the production and distribution of pornography on moral grounds.28 At the same time, many people who identify as “feminists”—that is, people who believe that women should be entitled to the same legal and social rights as men—strongly oppose the production of pornography as a matter of equality for women. They argue that women are degraded when pornography is made, distributed, and consumed. In this example, you can see how religious conservatives and feminists—who generally are considered liberal in our political spectrum—are troubled by pornography. These groups allied because of their shared opposition to pornography, a matter that’s important, but part of the peripheral belief system of these groups. But this coalition, like many such coalitions, cannot last because these two groups are fundamentally opposed to each other in their core beliefs, including gender equity. While the efforts of political conservatives and feminists to restrict the distribution of what they consider to be pornography haven’t been entirely successful, this example is illustrative of how groups can coalesce.29 Other examples include recent instances of evangelical Christians allying with environmental groups to promote better stewardship of the earth’s resources,30 and liberals and conservatives coming together to oppose claimed intrusions on privacy that followed the September 11 terrorist attacks.31 Punctuated Equilibrium punctuated equilibrium. An idea borrowed from evolutionary biology by Â�Baumgartner and Jones (1993), in which policy change is characterized by long-run stability punctuated with short-term shocks that make policy change more likely.

Baumgartner and Jones borrow the concept of “punctuated equilibrium” from evolutionary biology to describe the process by which policy is made in the United States.32 They argue that the balance of political power between interest groups remains relatively stable over long periods of time, punctuated by relatively sudden shifts in public understanding of problems and in the balance of power between the groups seeking to fight entrenched interests. Key to their theory of equilibrium is the idea of the policy monopoly, which corresponds with the idea of policy subsystems. A policy monopoly is a concentrated, closed system of the most important actors in policy making. Such a monopoly has an interest in keeping policy making closed, because a closed system benefits the interests of those in the monopoly and keeps policy making under some measure of control. Under the iron triangle notion of policy making, this system will remain closed and stable for a long time. But Baumgartner and Jones argue that there are instances when the “equilibrium” maintained by policy monopolies will break down, greater and more critical attention to issues will follow, and rapid policy change will be the immediate result. The policy monopolies themselves can break down or at least become more open issue networks. How do policy monopolies and their dominant construction of problems break

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

down? First, greater media attention to an issue can begin to break open policy monopolies. Media attention to issues can grow when a small but compelling or influential group of people voice complaints about a policy problem to which members of the policy community do not effectively respond. Baumgartner and Jones and Jeffrey Berry use the breakdown of the nuclear power monopoly to illustrate the effect of greater attention on a problem.33 The nuclear policy monopoly consisted of the Atomic Energy Commission (AEC), the nuclear utilities, the builders of nuclear power plants, the civil and military nuclear establishment, and the Joint Committee on Atomic Energy (JCAE), a very powerful joint committee of the U.S. House and Senate. This monopoly began to break down as interest groups and, in time, the public voiced greater concern about the safety and cost of nuclear power, and by the mid-1970s the JCAE had been disbanded, the AEC broken up, and the Nuclear Regulatory Commission created, all due to reformist tendencies in government in the early 1970s and the greater media and public attention paid to nuclear power. This example also illustrates an important finding: that increased attention to a problem usually means greater negative attention to it. In this way, the “policy image” of various issues and policies can change. In the nuclear power case, the increased scrutiny of the industry began to break down the image of nuclear power as “the peaceful atom” creating power “too cheap to meter” to an image of danger and expense. This negative image was reinforced by the accident at the Three Mile Island nuclear plant in Pennsylvania in 1979 and the multi-billion-dollar default on bonds sold to build nuclear power plants in Washington State in 1982. Policy monopolies also break down when groups go venue shopping to find the best setting in which to press their claims. The media are one venue, and groups can seek access to the courts or other units of government to engage in policy debate. The reform of the congressional committee system and, most important, the increasing autonomy of subcommittees starting in the early 1970s have led to a greater number of venues in Congress for groups to find a sympathetic ear to influence policy making. An important aspect of this way of thinking about policy is the pattern of long periods of stability followed by rapid change, followed again by long periods of stability. In this way, Baumgartner and Jones argue, policy change is not incremental or in a state of constant flux. Institutional Analysis and Development Elinor Ostroms’s Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD) framework has become widely used among researchers interested in the management of what are called common pool resources; that is, resources that are shared and used in common, like a publicly owned forest, or a fishing area. The IAD framework encompasses a wide range of ideas about actors, institutions, and rules in the policy process, and how they work together to result in particular kinds of public policies.

301

institutional analysis and development (IAD). A way of understanding the policy process pioneered by Elinor Ostrom. It is rooted in ideas of rationality, of group cooperation to achieve shared goals, and in a broad definition of the meaning of “institution” within politics and society. common pool resources. Resources that are used in common by a community, such as water supplies, fisheries, grazing land, that require some sort of regulatory system to prevent unsustainable use of the resource by one or a few people at the expense of the whole community.

302 Chapter 10

satisficing. Making the best possible decision under constraints related to time, information, and other resources

The IAD framework is also called an “institutional rational choice” approach, because it is built on ideas derived from rational choice theory. Rational choice theory is based on the idea that individuals—acting alone, or within organizations—are utility-maximizing, rational individuals who are goal oriented and use near-perfect information to weigh a range of options before adopting the optimal choice based on their calculation of costs and benefits. People are boundedly rational in their decision making because they do the best they can in making decisions given limited time and information. Herbert Simon calls this satisficing—doing the best they can under resource and other constraints rather than solving problems assuming no constraints, which would be inaccurate. Assuming that people are boundedly rational, they come together to make public policies within “institutions” through the use of “rules.” I place these terms in quotation marks because thus far in this book we have assumed a shared understanding of these terms, particularly in political science. An “institution” to a political scientist is often an agency or branch of government, such as the Justice Department, or the Congress. Sociologists also describe social institutions like family and marriage. The behavior of members of institutions is shaped by the nature of the institution, which encompasses a set of norms and expectations of the various actors, such as the norms for behavior in Congress. “Rules” are the decisions that institutions make to enforce their decisions. Rules can be really broad, at the constitutional level, such as rules prohibiting government interference in religion, or government promotion of it, in the First Amendment to the Constitution. Or rules can be very specific and focused, such as the laws and regulations regarding running pet stores or having fishing licenses. Ostrom argues that the study of institutions and rules is not so straightforward. She identifies several significant challenges to the study of institutions 34: 1. “The term institution refers to many different types of entities, including both organizations and the rules used to structure patterns of interaction within and across organizations. 2. “Although the buildings in which organized entities are located are quite visible, institutions themselves are invisible.” Let’s consider these two challenges together. Ostrom argues that an institution is not just its organization and its building, but is also the rules that institutions make and that constrain the behaviors of people within those organizations. Indeed, Ostrom makes clear that institutions are best understood by how they actually use rules than by the rules that they claim are the most important; she claims that this is a distinction between “rules-in-use” rather than “rules-in-form.” She then raises some important challenges for the study of institutions: 3. “To develop a coherent approach to studying diverse types of institutional arrangements, including markets, hierarchies, firms, families, voluntary

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

organizations, national governments, and international regimes, one needs multiple inputs from diverse disciplines. 4. “Given the multiple languages used across disciplines, a coherent institutional framework is needed to allow for expression and comparison of diverse theories and models of theories applied to particular puzzles and problem settings.” Here, Ostrom notes that those who study public policy really need to draw on insights from many disciplines, as you have seen throughout this book. But in the fourth point, Ostrom points to the need for some sort of shared framework for understanding how all the aspects of policy work together, across disciplinary contributions. 5. “Decisions made about rules at any one level are usually made within a structure of rules existing at a different level. Thus, institutional studies need to encompass multiple units of analysis. 6. “At any one level of analysis, combinations of rules, attributes of the world, and communities of individuals involved are combined in a configural rather than an additive manner.” In simplest terms, Ostrom is saying that rules made at a “higher” level in a government or organization will influence other levels, so if we are to understand the policy process we need to understand multiple levels of government; it is not clear, however, whether a “level” is necessarily below, above, or parallel to any particular level. Thus, in the sixth point, Ostrom argues that rules do not simply accumulate, one on top of another. Instead, rules combine with other features of institutions to create new configurations of actors and rules. With these challenges in mind, Ostrom has developed a framework for understanding the policy process that is shown in Figure 10.3. In this model, the existing physical world, the attributes of a community (that is, the various things that bind and define a community) and the rules-in-use that structure individual and group behavior influence the “action arena.” The action arena includes the action situation—that is, the problem at hand—and the actors, the people and groups who will do something about it. The action situation contains the people who participate in making decisions, their positions on what they would like to see happen, the outcomes they believe should occur, or worry will occur, the connection between what is done and what will happen as a result, the nature and extent to which the participants can shape or control outcomes, the adequacy of the information available to some or all actors, and the rational weighting of costs and benefits resulting from outcomes. According to Ostrom, actors can be individuals or groups, and include “assumptions about four clusters of variables”:

303

304 Chapter 10 Figure 10.3â•… A Framework for Institutional Analysis

Physicall Material Conditions Action Arena

Attributes

Action Situation

of

Community

Pattemsof

Interaction Actors

Evaluative Criteria

Rules in Use

Interaction

Source: Elinor Ostrom, “Institutional Rational Choice: An Assessment of the Institutional Analysis and Development Framework,” in Theories of the Policy Process, ed. Paul A. Sabatier, 2d ed. Paul A. Sabatier. Reprinted by permission of Westview Press, a member of the Perseus Group. Copyright © 2007.

1. “The resources that an actor brings to a situation; 2. “The valuation actors assign to states of the world and to actions; 3. “The way actors acquire, process, retain, and use knowledge contingencies and information; and 4. “The processes actors use for the selection of particular courses of action.” Both the actors and the action situation are required in an action arena for there to be any outcome. These outcomes are shaped by “patterns of interactions”; that is, the processes by which participants work in the policy process. And the activities of the participants—as well as the outcomes—are influenced by at least six factors encompassing efficiency, equity, accountability, “conformance to general morality” (that is, following the rules), and adaptability. This is an extremely broad-brush review of IAD, which is presented here for two main reasons. First, while it is extremely complex, if you delve into the IAD you will find that Ostrom—unique among most policy theorists—very carefully specifies the variables that should be considered throughout the policy process, in terms of the actors, the outcomes, and the process itself. Second, it is important to know a little about the IAD framework because, as Ostrom and others have ap-

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

plied it, the IAD framework has become a particularly valuable contribution to the study of rules surrounding common pool resources. In a well-known book, The Tragedy of the Commons, Garrett Hardin argues that a common area—such as a pasture or fishing grounds—can be overused and the resource will be depleted unless it is somehow managed for the benefit of its users. Ostrom argues, using the IAD as a starting point, that many cases of shared resources exemplify successful local management because institutions and the rules and enforcement of rules that go with these structures—in the sense described here—are formed and developed at the local or near-local level to manage the resource so that many people benefit without its overexploitation. The research of Ostrom and others has found that people can, under proper conditions, form these institutions, thereby avoiding the heavy hand of central government regulation, which often is suboptimal because it fails to equitably distribute a resource or because it creates no incentives for following the rules. These local institutions can avoid the much-feared tragedy of the commons. Why is the IAD so well suited to this? Because the configuration of actors, action situations, and the definition of rules and institutions is more closely attuned to human behavior in communities than are most depictions of the policy process. Conclusion While this discussion of some of the dominant theories of the policy process forms the conclusion to this book, this is just a taste of the ideas contained in these rich and complex theories of the policy process, and no summary of this sort could do justice to these models. Second, the development of theory continues apace. While these are the major theoretical traditions under which policy process scholars have worked over the past twenty to twenty-five years, many scholars have isolated particular aspects of these theories and have refined and modified them. It is indeed possible that these refinements and modifications could yield yet another round of highly sophisticated theory building in the field. Finally, this is not the last word because it is my hope that you can find, in these theories, ways of thinking about what is most important to you in your studies and work in the policy process. What this means will be unique to your individual approach to policy studies and to your motivations for studying policy. For those with a theoretical bent, I hope this book and the materials I cite will spark your interest in the field and induce you to read and think broadly about the policy process. For those who plan to become participants in the policy process—and this may include anyone with an interest in public affairs, whether one is an academic, a professional analyst, or a civic-minded citizen—I hope you can adapt all the models we have described here to help you think about what is most important in the policy process, particularly if they help you make sound political arguments based on sound logic, good evidence, and strong rhetoric. If these models in this book help you, your allies, and even your opponents think about how policy is made—and how you can get involved to make better policy—then this enterprise has most assuredly been worth the effort.

305

306 Chapter 10

Key Terms Advocacy Coalition Framework Anecdotal evidence Common Pool Resources Peer review Punctuated equilibrium

Institutional Analysis and Development Normative and positive Satisificing Scientific method Streams metaphor

Questions for Discussion, Reflection, and Research 1. Consider the classic “stages” model of policy making. Paul Sabatier, among many other scholars, has argued that the stages metaphor has some substantial shortcomings. List these shortcomings, but then ask: What are the remaining strengths of the stages model for the student of the policy process? Does this conception still have some value to the student and researcher? 2. How would you go about measuring the national mood? Is the national mood something you can measure or is it just something you feel intuitively? Could two people disagree about the national mood? Why would they disagree? 3. As you may know, Elinor Ostrom was the co-winner of the 2009 Nobel Prize in Economics (technically known as the Swedish Central Bank [Sveriges Riksbank] Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel) for her work on common pool resource management, even though her disciplinary background is as a political scientist. Spend some time reviewing the news stories and journalistic descriptions of her work. Why do you think that Ostrom was awarded a prize in economics if she is a political scientist? What does this say about the nature of her work and of the IAD framework, or about the nature of policy science or the boundaries that separate social science disciplines? 4. Many scholars (myself included) mix and match elements of the theories presented in this chapter to explain how specific policies are made, or to develop theory about a particular kind of policy making. Is it sensible to borrow from more than one theory of the policy process when testing theory? What does it say about theory that it is possible to borrow from different models? 5. How might you use the theories outlined in this book to explain the policy outcomes in fields that interest you? This might be a particularly good question to ask yourself if you are writing a term paper for a policy class project, in which it is useful to demonstrate some knowledge of theory.

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

6. Consider the difference between empirical scientific evidence and anecdotal evidence. Which is considered more useful to the study of public policy and why? Think of some anecdotes you use to explain why you hold particular political beliefs. Are these anecdotes backed by social science? If not, why are anecdotes still important? 7. Why is methodology important to science, whether it’s natural science, physical science, or social science? What would happen if we did science without a method? 8. Why is creating theory about public policy important, rather than just describing specific problem areas, such as health policy or defense policy? 9. Find an article on an issue of public policy in a newspaper. Consider carefully whether the people making arguments for or against a particular policy are making normative or positive arguments. Are they using anecdotes or evidence? How can you tell the difference? Whose arguments do you consider most persuasive? Why? Additional Reading The study of the public policy process is dominated today by three books, and by books inspired by these original studies. The first is John Kingdon’s Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies, 2d ed. (New York: Harper Collins, 1995), which was originally published in 1994. The advocacy coalition framework was published by Paul Sabatier in several forms, and was then published in a book, Paul Sabatier and Hank C. JenkinsSmith’s Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993). Paul Sabatier has since supplemented this book with a broader consideration of the policy process, Theories of the Policy Process (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999), and an updated and refined second edition (2006). Elinor Ostrom updates her 1999 essay in the first edition of Theories of the Policy Process with an essay in the 2006 edition. Indeed, both volumes, which overlap to some extent, contain a wealth of theoretical information, including coverage of important questions in the field, and serious students should obtain and read both editions. The punctuated equilibrium metaphor of agenda and policy change was broadly introduced in Frank R. Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones, Agendas and Instability in American Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993). Their project inspired a massive data collection effort called the Policy Agendas Project (http:// www.policyagendas.org), which contains the datasets for the 1993 volume as well as far more data about Congress, the executive branch, and media coverage of key issues. Much of this data was gathered and used by scholars who published in an edited volume, Frank R. Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones, Policy Dynamics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002). There are many public policy textbooks on the market that seek to synthesize the vast amount of information on the policy process. One of my favorite basic texts is

307

308 Chapter 10 James E. Anderson, Public Policymaking, 7th ed. (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2010). For advanced students of the policy process, I recommend Michael Howlett and M. Ramesh, Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems (Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1995). An excellent collection of classic readings in the policy process literature is Daniel C. McCool, Public Policy Theories, Models, and Concepts: An Anthology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995). Finally, a pointed and readable overview of public policy is a new book, Kevin B. Smith and Christopher W. Larimer, The Public Policy Theory Primer (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2009). Notes 1. George D. Greenberg et al., “Developing Public Policy Theory: Perspectives from Empirical Research,” American Political Science Review 71, no. 4 (1977): 1532–43. 2. Paul A. Sabatier, “Political Science and Public Policy,” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991): 144–7; Paul A. Sabatier, “Toward Better Theories of the Policy Process,” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991): 147–56. 3. William M.K. Trochim, “Deduction and Induction,” http://www.socialresearchmethods.net/kb/dedind.php (accessed November 1, 2009). 4. Thomas R. Dye, Understanding Public Policy, 7th ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1992), p. 44. 5. McCool’s explanation of a model involves using a car. See Daniel C. McCool, Public Policy Theories, Models, and Concepts: An Anthology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995), p. 1. 6. Dye, Understanding Public Policy, 45. 7. Donald Thomas Campbell, Julian C. Stanley, and N.L. Gage, Experimental and Quasi-Experimental Designs For Research (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966). 8. Calvin Woodward, “Fact Check: Some Obama Health Care Stories Flawed,” Associated Press Online, September 29, 2009 (accessed via LexisNexis). 9. Jason Deparle and Robert Gebeloff, “Food Stamp Use Soars Across U.S., and Stigma Fades,” The New York Times, November 29, 2009, A1; Christine Rehl, “Find a Way to Stop Abuse of Food Stamps,” Letters to the Editor, Columbus Dispatch, December 8, 2009, 14A; David A. Super, “The Quiet ‘Welfare’ Revolution: Resurrecting the Food Stamp Program in the Wake of the 1996 Welfare Law,” New York University Law Review 79, no. 4 (2004): 1271–1392. 10. Thomas A. Birkland and Regina G. Lawrence, “Media Framing and Policy Change after Columbine,” American Behavioral Scientist 52, no. 10 (2009):1405–25; Regina G. Lawrence and Thomas A. Birkland, “Guns, Hollywood, and Criminal Justice: Defining the School Shootings Problem across Public Arenas,” Social Science Quarterly 85, no. 5 (2004): 1193–1207. 11. An example of this argument is Lee Sustar, “Katrina Exposes Racism,” Zmag.com, http://www.zmag.org/ znet/viewArticle/5514 (accessed January 7, 2010); a much more nuanced treatment of “racism” as understood by different groups and as it relates to New Orleans is Nils Gilman, “What Katrina Teaches about the Meaning of Racism,” Understanding Katrina; Perspectives from the Social Sciences, Social Science Research Council, http:// understandingkatrina.ssrc.org/Gilman/ (accessed January 10, 2009). 12. The podcast for this show is at http://wamu.org/programs/dr/10/01/07.php#31354 (accessed January 9, 2009). 13. M.A. Palmer et al. “Mountaintop Mining Consequences,” Science 327 (January 8, 2010): 148–49. 14. Suzanne Goldenberg, “US Scientists Demand Government Ban on Mountaintop Mining,” The Guardian, January 7, 2010, http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/jan/07/us-scientists-mountaintop-mining (accessed January 7, 2010). 15. Giandomenico Majone, Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), p. 5.

Science

and

Theory

in the

Study

of

Public Policy

309

16. Beryl Radin, Beyond Machiavelli: Policy Analysis Comes of Age (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000). 17. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970); McCool, Public Policy Theories, 7. 18. Thomas R. Dye, Understanding Public Policy. 19. George D. Greenberg, Jeffrey A. Miller, Lawrence B. Mohr, and Bruce C. Vladeck, “Developing Public Policy Theory: Perspectives from Empirical Research.” American Political Science Review 71 no. 4 (1977): 15–43. 20. Paul A. Sabatier, “Toward Better Theories of the Policy Process,” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991):144–56. 21. Paul A. Sabatier and Hank C Jenkins-Smith, Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1993). 22. http://www.policyagendas.org/. 23. Frank R. Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones, Agendas and Instability in American Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993). 24. Peter deLeon, “The Stages Approach to the Policy Process: What Has It Done? Where Is It Going?” in Theories of the Policy Process, ed. Paul A. Sabatier (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1999); Robert T. Nakamura, “The Textbook Policy Process and Implementation Research,” Policy Studies Journal 7, no. 1 (1987): 142–54. 25. Originally published in 1984, the most current edition is Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies, 2d ed., Longman Classics in Political Science (New York: Longman, 2003). 26. Paul A. Sabatier, “Political Science and Public Policy,” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991): 138–143. 27. Nikolaos Zahariadis, “To Sell or Not to Sell? Telecommunications Policy in Britain and France,” Journal of Public Policy 12, no. 4 (1993): 355–76. 28. I will leave aside the problem of defining pornography for this discussion; the courts have found this definition extremely challenging, but, whatever it means, the example here is still apt. Perhaps we should satisfy ourselves with Justice Potter Stewart’s claim that it is difficult to define, but “I know it when I see it.” See his concurrence in Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U.S. 184 (1964). 29. Of course, this alliance is itself extremely controversial among members of these groups. See, for example, Mary Jo Weaver, “Pornography and the Religious Imagination,” in For Adult Users Only: The Dilemma of Violent Pornography, ed. Susan Gubar and Joan Hoff (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1989), chapter 3; and Lynne Segal and Mary McIntosh, Sex Exposed: Sexuality and the Pornography Debate (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1993), especially pp. 19 and p. 28. Some writers note the fundamental differences in the rationale on which feminists and religious conservatives base their antipathy toward pornography. An example is Ted G. Jelen, “Fundamentalism, Feminism, and Attitudes toward Pornography,” Review of Religious Research 28, no. 2 (1986): 97–103. Again, the ACF explains how these alliances are impermanent, but do form around short-term policy goals rather than around shared fundamental beliefs. 30. Eli Kintisch, “Evangelicals, Scientists Reach Common Ground on Climate Change,” Science 311, no. 5764 (2006): 1082–83. 31. “Conservatives, Liberals Align against Patriot Act,” The Washington Times, June 14, 2005, http://www. washingtontimes.com/news/2005/jun/14/20050614–121304–2787r/ (accessed January 10, 2010); Jesse Walker, “Bob Barr, Civil Libertarian,” Reason (December 2003) (accessed January 10, 2010); Spencer S. Hsu, “Probe of Homeland Security Privacy Office Sought; Group Says Chief Is Enabling, Not Curbing, Surveillance,” The Washington Post, October 27, 2009, p. A3 (accessed via LexisNexis). 32. Frank R. Baumgartner, and Bryan D. Jones, Agendas and Instability in American Politics. 33. Jeffrey M. Berry, “Subgovernments, Issue Networks, and Political Conflict,” in Remaking American Politics, ed. Richard and Sidney Milkis Harris (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1989). 34. Elinor Ostrom, “Institutional Rational Choice: An Assessment of the Institutional Analysis and Development Framework,” in Theories of the Policy Process, 2d ed., ed. Paul A. Sabatier (Boulder, CO: Westview, 2007).

This page intentionlly left blank

References

Aberbach, Joel D. Keeping a Watchful Eye: The Politics of Congressional Oversight. Washington DC: Brookings Institution, 1990. Affholter, Dennis P. “Outcome Monitoring.” In Handbook of Practical Program Evaluation, edited by Joseph S. Wholey, Harry P. Hatry, and Kathryn E. Newcomer. San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 1994. Agranoff, Robert, and Michael McGuire. Collaborative Public Management, ed. Barry Rabe. American Governance and Public Policy Series. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003. Alger, Dean E. The Media and Politics. 2d ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1996. Allison, Graham, and Philip Zelikow. Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. 2d ed. New York: Addison Wesley Longman, 1999. â•… This classic text explores various ways of explaining American and Soviet decision-making processes during the Cuban Missile Crisis. The book’s value is in its development of three models of decision making and their application to the missile crisis case. This second edition is completely rewritten and takes into account new historical information about the behavior of the key actors in the crisis. Anderson, James E. Public Policymaking. 5th ed. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2002. â•… A reliable standard text on the policy process; its strength is its theoretical richness combined with practical examples, without providing a series of disconnected chapters on substantive policy topics. Anderson, Virginia, and Lauren Johnson. Systems Thinking Basics: From Concepts to Causal Loops. Cambridge, MA: Pegasus Communications, 1997. Argyris, Chris. On Organizational Learning. 2d ed. Malden, MA: Blackwell Business, 1999. Argyris, Chris, and Donald A. Schön. Organizational Learning: A Theory of Action Perspective. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co., 1978. Arnold, R. Douglas. The Logic of Congressional Action. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990. Bachrach, Peter, and Morton Baratz. “The Two Faces of Power.” American Political Science Review 56 (1962): 947–52. â•… A now-classic article on how political power is used by groups to advance their ideas while preventing other groups’ ideas from gaining attention. Baker, Ross K. House and Senate. 4th ed. New York: W.W. Norton, 2008. Bardach, Eugene. A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Effective Problem Solving. 3d ed. Washington DC: CQ Press, 2009. Baumgartner, Frank, and Bryan D. Jones. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009. â•… This book uses the idea of “punctuated equilibrium” to explain how policies often remain

311

312 References at a standstill for a long time, and then suddenly gain attention and undergo rapid change. This book is remarkable for both its method and the sweep of its analysis. ———. Policy Dynamics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002. Beard, Charles A. An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States. New York: Macmillan, 1956. â•… This book presents the controversial argument that the founders of the Constitution structured the document, and thus the American system of government, largely to protect their own economic interests and the interests of their economic class. Bendor, Jonathan, and Thomas H. Hammond. “Rethinking Allison’s Models.” American Political Science Review 86, no. 2 (1992): 301–22. â•… A review and critique of Graham Allison’s decision-making models in Essence of Decision. The article is useful both for its careful summary of Allison’s argument and its reasoned critique of it. Bennett, Colin J., and Michael Howlett. “The Lessons of Learning: Reconciling Theories of Policy Learning and Policy Change.” Policy Sciences 25, no. 3 (1992): 275–94. â•… A review of the literature on policy learning and its relationship to change. Bennett, W. Lance. News, the Politics of Illusion. 6th ed. New York: Longman, 2004. â•… A very readable text on how the news media cover and present the news. Bennett argues that the information provided by news media is insufficient for people to use to make decisions in a democracy. Bernstein, Carl, and Bob Woodward. All the President’s Men. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974. Berry, Jeffrey M. “Subgovernments, Issue Networks, and Political Conflict.” In Remaking American Politics, ed. Richard and Sidney Milkis Harris. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1989. Birkland, Thomas A. After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy and Focusing Events. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1997. â•… A book on how the politics of focusing events differ depending on the nature of the event and the type of policy community that mobilizes, or fails to do so, to change policy in response to the event. ———. “Learning and Policy Improvement after Disaster: The Case of Aviation Security,” American Behavioral Scientist 48, no. 3 (2004): 341–64. ———. Lessons of Disaster. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006. Birkland, Thomas and Regina G. Lawrence. “Media Framing and Policy Change after Columbine.” American Behavioral Scientist 52, no. 10 (2009):1405–25. Boehlert, Eric. Bloggers on the Bus: How the Internet Changed Politics and the Press in 2008. New York: Free Press, 2009. Busenberg, George J. “Learning in Organizations and Public Policy.” Journal of Public Policy 21, no. 2 (2001): 173–89. Campbell, Donald Thomas, Julian C. Stanley, and N.L. Gage. Experimental and QuasiExperimental Designs for Research. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966. Cannon, Lou. President Reagan: The Role of a Lifetime. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1991. Caro, Robert A. Master of the Senate. New York: Knopf, 2002. ———. Means of Ascent. New York: Knopf, 1990. ———. The Path to Power. New York: Knopf, 1982. Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. Greenwich, CT: Fawcett, 1962. â•… This book is about the environmental damage done by pesticides. The publication of Carson’s book is widely acknowledged as one of the most important events in the history of the environmental movement, and in many ways elevated, the environmental issue to the institutional agenda. Casper, Jonathan D. “The Supreme Court and National Policymaking.” American Political Science Review 70 (1976): 50–63.

References Chesney, James, and Otto Feinstein. “Making Political Activity a Requirement in Introductory Political Science Courses.” PS: Political Science and Politics 26, no. 3 (1993): 535–38. Choldin, Harvey M. “How Sampling Will Help Defeat the Undercount.” Society 34, no. 3 (1997): 27–30. Cigler, Allan J. “Interest Groups: A Subfield in Search of an Identity.” In Political Science, Looking to the Future: Volume IV: American Institutions, ed. William Crotty. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1991. Cobb, Roger W., and Charles D. Elder. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building. 2d ed. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1983. â•… Cobb and Elder view agenda setting, or, as they put it, “agenda building,” as “a particularly critical phase in the policy process.” This book is a rich description of how problems are defined and how groups interact and compete to build their own agendas and deny others access to the agenda. Cobb, Roger W. and David M. Primo. The Plane Truth: Airline Crashes, the Media, and Transportation Policy. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 2003. Cobb, Roger W. and Marc Howard Ross. Cultural Strategies of Agenda Denial: Avoidance, Attack, and Redefinition. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1997. Cochran, Charles L., and Eloise F. Malone. Public Policy: Perspectives and Choices. New York: McGraw Hill, 1995. Cochran, Clarke E., Lawrence Mayer, T.R. Carr, and N. Joseph Cayer. American Public Policy: An Introduction. 6th ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999. Cogan, John F. The Budget Puzzle: Understanding Federal Spending. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994. Cohen, Michael D., James G. March, and Johan P. Olsen. “A Garbage Can Model of Organizational Choice.” Administrative Science Quarterly 17 (1972): 1–25. â•… The “garbage can model” was developed to describe decision making and agenda setting in “anarchic” settings, such as universities. John Kingdon adopted and modified the streams and garbage cans concept in his book Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies. Cook, Timothy E. Governing with the News: The News Media as a Political Institution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998. Cranford, John. Budgeting for America. Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly, 1989. Crouse, Tim. The Boys on the Bus. New York: Random House, 1973. â•… An amusing and readable journalistic account of the 1972 presidential primaries, in which pack journalism became evident as a major problem in the news media. Dahl, Robert A. “Decision Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National PolicyMaker.” Journal of Public Law 6 (Fall 1957): 279–95. â•… An investigation into the extent to which the Supreme Court makes policy that differs meaningfully from the preferences of the public, as measured by the composition of the “governing coalition” in Congress. Dahl found that the Supreme Court’s decisions did not stray too far from the policy choices made by Congress, although later research has questioned his conclusions. Davidson, Roger H., and Walter J. Oleszek. Congress and Its Members. 12th ed. Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly Books, 2008. deLeon, Peter. “The Stages Approach to the Policy Process: What Has it Done? Where Is it Going?” In Theories of the Policy Process, ed. Paul A. Sabatier. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1999. Dempsey, Paul Stephen. Flying Blind: The Failure of Airline Deregulation. Washington, DC: Economic Policy Institute, 1990. Dempsey, Paul Stephen, and Andrew R. Goetz. Airline Deregulation and Laissez-Faire Mythology. Westport, CT: Quorum Books, 1992. Derthick, Martha. New Towns in Town. Washington, DC: Urban Institute, 1972. An early study of policy implementation; in this case, of the “New Towns in Town” program initiated during the Johnson administration. Dionne, E.J. Why Americans Hate Politics. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1991.

313

314 References Drinker Bowen, Catherine. Miracle at Philadelphia: The Story of the Constitutional Convention, May to September, 1787. Boston: Little, Brown, 1986. Dye, Thomas R. Understanding Public Policy. 7th ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1992. Dyer, Caroline. “Researching the Implementation of Educational Policy: A Backward Mapping Approach.” Comparative Education 35, no. 1 (1999): 45–62. â•… A very useful article showing how the key concepts of implementation research can be applied to a particular case and to nations outside the United States and Europe; in this case, India. Easterbrook, Gregg. “The All-Too-Friendly Skies: Security as an Afterthought.” In How Did This Happen? Terrorism and the New War, ed. James F. Hodge Jr. and Gideon Rose. New York: Public Affairs, 2001. Easton, David. A Systems Analysis of Political Life. New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1965. â•… The book that introduced systems thinking and modeling to political science and policy studies; while the models it inspired are no longer in vogue among political scientists, the concepts and terminology that were developed are still employed today. ———. A Framework for Political Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968. Edelman, Murray J. The Symbolic Uses of Politics. 2d ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1985. ———. Political Language: Words that Succeed and Policies that Fail. New York: Academic Press, 1977. ———. Constructing the Political Spectacle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988. â•… Edelman’s work is the foundation for almost all the work on the importance of symbols and symbolic rhetoric in politics and policy making. His work has influenced students of the news media, agenda setting, and social construction. Eldersveld, Samuel J. Political Parties in American Society. 2d ed. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000. Elmore, Richard. “Backward Mapping: Implementation Research and Policy Decisions.” Political Science Quarterly 94, no. 4 (Winter 1979): 601–16. ———. “Forward and Backward Mapping.” In Policy Implementation in Federal and Unitary Systems, ed. K. Hanf and T. Toonen. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985. â•… In his 1979 article, Richard Elmore describes the backward mapping technique for analyzing policy implementation, arguing that it is important to take into account the motivations and actions of lower level implementers when designing and implementing policies. The 1985 article is an effort to combine top-down (forward mapping) and bottom-up approaches to the study of implementation. Erber, Ralph, and Richard R. Lau. “Political Cynicism Revisited: An Information-Processing Reconciliation of Policy-Based and Incumbency-Based Interpretations of Changes in Trust in Government.” American Journal of Political Science 34, no. 1 (February1990): 236–53. Erikson, Robert S., Gerald C. Wright, and John P. McIver. Statehouse Democracy: Public Opinion and Policy in the American States. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Fenno, Richard. Homestyle: House Members in their Districts. Boston: Little, Brown, 1978. â•… A major study of how members of the House of Representatives work in their home districts to gain the support of constituents and voters. Fenton, Natalie. New Media, Old News: Journalism and Democracy in the Digital Age. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2009. Fiorina, Morris P. Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment. 2d ed. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004. â•… A lively and assertive book in which Fiorina argues that there exists a “Washington establishment” of interest groups, bureaucrats, the media, lobbyists and others, but that the focal point or “keystone” of all this activity is in Congress.

References Fiorina, Morris P. “Some Problems in Studying the Effects of Resource Allocation in Congressional Elections.” American Journal of Political Science 25, no. 3 (1981): 543–67. Fiorina, Morris P., and Samuel J. Abrams. “Political Polarization in the American Public.” Annual Review of Political Science 11, no. 1 (2008): 563–88. Fiorino, Daniel J. Making Environmental Policy. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995. â•… An excellent introductory text on environmental policy, written by an insider in the federal environmental community. Freedman, David A., and Kenneth W. Wachter. “Census Adjustment: Statistical Promise or Illusion.” Society and Natural Resources 39, no. 1 (2001): 26–33. Gaventa, John. Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1980. â•… Chapter 1 of this book is a remarkably concise and insightful discussion of three levels of political power. The remainder of the book describes how these levels of power work to keep coal miners from mobilizing to improve their position in their jobs and communities. Gay, Peter. The Enlightenment: An Interpretation. W.W. Norton & Company, 1966. Goggin, Malcom L., Ann O’M. Bowman, James P. Lester, and Laurence J. O’Toole, Jr. Implementation Theory and Practice: Toward a Third Generation. Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman/ Little, Brown, 1990. â•… This volume, which has unfortunately gone out of print, is a synthesis of top-down and bottom-up approaches to implementation in what the authors call a “communications” model of implementation. In their model, the top policy designers send implementation messages that are received and interpreted by targets and intermediaries. Goodwin, Doris Kearns. Team of Rivals: The Political Genius of Abraham Lincoln. New York: Simon & Schuster, 2005. Graber, Doris A. Mass Media and American Politics. 8th ed. Washington: CQ Press, 2010. â•… This is a balanced, readable, and comprehensive text on political communications written by one of the primary experts in the field. Green, John Clifford, and Daniel J. Coffey. The State of the Parties: The Changing Role of Contemporary American Politics. 5th ed. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2007. Green, John C., and Daniel M. Shea, eds. The State of the Parties: The Changing Role of Contemporary American Parties. 4th ed. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003. Greenberg, George D., Jeffrey A. Miller, Lawrence B. Mohr, and Bruce C. Vladeck. “Developing Public Policy Theory: Perspectives from Empirical Research.” American Political Science Review 71, no. 4 (1977): 1532–43. â•… This article argues that more efforts at theory building should give way to, or at least by accompanied by, greater efforts at empirical testing of theory. Greenstein, Fred I. “The Presidential Leadership Style of Bill Clinton: An Early Appraisal.” Political Science Quarterly 108, no. 4 (Winter 1993): 589–601. Gusfield, Joseph. The Culture of Public Problems: Drinking, Driving and the Symbolic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981. Hall, Peter A. “Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State: The Case of Economic Policy Making in Britain,” Comparative Politics 25 (1993): 275–96. Heclo, Hugh. “Issue Networks and the Executive Establishment.” In The New American Political System, ed. Anthony King. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1978. â•… In this article, Hugh Heclo argues that the iron triangle concept of policy “was not so much wrong as it is disastrously incomplete.” He argues that the issue network is a better way of describing the more competitive and contentious relationships between interests, regulators, and lawmakers. Heilbroner, Robert L. The Worldly Philosophers: The Lives, Times, and Ideas of the Great Economic Thinkers. 7th rev. ed. New York: Simon and Schuster Trade Paperbacks, 1999. â•… This very readable book is a good starting point for those interested in the history of economic ideas, ranging from Adam Smith to John Maynard Keynes.

315

316 References Hilgartner, James, and Charles Bosk. “The Rise and Fall of Social Problems: A Public Arenas Model.” American Journal of Sociology 94, no. 1 (1988): 53–78. â•… Hilgartner and Bosk argue “that public attention is a scarce resource, allocated through competition in a system of public arenas.” Because public attention is scarce, the competition to gain a place on the agenda is often fierce. Hill, Kevin A., and John E. Hughes. Cyberpolitics: Citizen Participation in the Age of the Internet. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998. Hofstadter, Richard. The Paranoid Style in American Politics, and Other Essays. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979. Horowitz, Donald. The Courts and Social Policy. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1977. Howard, Christopher. “Testing the Tools Approach: Tax Expenditures versus Direct Expenditures.” Public Administration Review 55, no. 5 (1995): 439. Howlett, Michael, and M. Ramesh. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. Toronto: Oxford University Press, 1995. â•… Howlett and Ramesh have written one of the most sophisticated texts on the public policy process in recent years. As Canadians, the authors bring a comparative perspective to the study of public policy that is not often seen in texts by American writers. Hrebenar, Ronald. Political Parties, Interest Groups, and Political Campaigns. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1999. Ingram, Helen, and Dean Mann. “Policy Failure: An Issue Deserving Attention.” In Why Policies Succeed or Fail. Helen Ingram and Dean Mann, eds. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1980. â•… This introductory essay explores some reasons why policies fail—or are claimed to have failed. The authors argue that the question of policy failure deserves further study to determine whether policies are really failing, why they fail, and to what extent their failure is influenced by other, overlapping policies and goals. Johannes, John R., and John C. McAdams. “The Congressional Incumbency Effect: Is It Casework, Policy Compatibility, or Something Else? An Examination of the 1978 Election.” American Journal of Political Science 25, no. 3 (1981): 512–42. Johnson, Haynes. Sleepwalking through History: America in the Reagan Years. New York: W.W. Norton, 2003. Kenneth J. Meier. Regulation, Politics, Bureaucracy and Economics. New York: St Martin’s Press, 1985. Also, excerpted in Stella Theodoulou and Cahn, eds. Public Policy: The Essential Readings. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995. Keynes, John Maynard. The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money London: Macmillan, 1936. â•… This is Keynes’s most famous book, and launched the Keynesian movement in economics. Adherents of Keynesian economics argue, among other things, that government should spend money during recessions to stimulate the economy, and collect tax surpluses during periods of growth to prepare for the inevitable economic downturns that characterize the business cycle. Kingdon, John W. Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies. 2d ed. New York: Harper Collins, 1995. â•… This text, first published in 1984, outlines a “streams” metaphor of public policy making, in which policy change is more likely to occur when changes in the politics, policy, and problem streams lead to the opening of a “window of opportunity” for change. This book has become very influential in policy studies and is used to explain policy making in many different fields. Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. â•… This book, first published in 1962, is a major work in the history of science. Kuhn argues that science does not progress through the steady accretion of knowledge, but, rather, though

References the adoption and destructions of “paradigms” in which researchers perform “normal science” until the contradictions between their findings and the paradigm lead to a revolution and the creation of a new paradigm. Lasswell, Harold D. Politics: Who Gets What, When, How. New York: Meridian Books, 1958. ———. A Pre-View of Policy Sciences. New York: American Elsevier Pub. Co., 1971. Laumann, Edward O., and David Knoke. The Organizational State: Social Choice in National Policy Domains. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987. Lawrence, Regina G., and Thomas A. Birkland. “Guns, Hollywood, and Criminal Justice: Defining the School Shootings Problem across Public Arenas.” Social Science Quarterly 85, no. 5 (2004): 1193–207. Leonard, David K., and Jiming Jiang. “Gender Bias and the College Predictions of the SATs: A Cry of Despair.” Research in Higher Education 40, no. 4 (1999): 375–407. Lerner, Daniel, and Harold D. Lasswell. The Policy Sciences: Recent Developments in Scope and Method. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1951. Lester, James P., and Malcom L. Goggin. “Back to the Future: The Rediscovery of Implementation Studies.” Policy Currents 8, no. 3 (1998): 1–9. http://apsapolicysection.org/v018_3/83. pdf. Accessed January 4, 2010. Levi, Edward. An Introduction to Legal Reasoning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949. Levine, Charles H., B. Guy Peters, and Frank J. Thompson. Public Administration: Challenges, Choices, Consequences. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman/Little, Brown, 1990. â•… This is a basic undergraduate text on public administration, a field that shares a considerable amount of research and thinking with public policy. This book is particularly strong in understanding and explaining the relationships between politics, policy, and public management. Light, Paul C. The President’s Agenda: Domestic Policy Choice from Kennedy to Carter (with Notes on Ronald Reagan). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982. â•… A groundbreaking book in the tradition of Neustadt’s Presidential Power. Light argues that the power of the presidency is in the power to set the agenda—that is, to cause Congress, the media, interest groups, and the public to focus on the issues he finds most important. Nevertheless, the president’s power is limited; he must gather resources to advance his chosen issues on the agenda early in his term, before those resources are expended. ———. Government’s Greatest Achievements: From Civil Rights to Homeland Security. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 2002. Lindblom, Charles E. “The Science of ‘Muddling Through.’” Public Administration Review 19 (1959): 79–88. ———. “Still Muddling, Not Yet Through.” Public Administration Review 39 (1979): 517–26. â•… These two articles discuss the idea of incrementalism as a way of understanding why policy decisions seem so small and timid. Lipford, Jody. “Twenty Years after Humphrey-Hawkins.” Independent Review 4 (Summer 1999): 41–63. Lipsky, Michael. “Street Level Bureaucracy and the Analysis of Urban Reform.” Urban Affairs Quarterly 6 (1971): 391–409. â•… This article introduces the idea of the “street-level bureaucrat” as an important element of policy implementation. Street-level bureaucrats are the teachers, police officers, and social workers charged with the direct delivery of services; their exercise of professional discretion in the delivery of services can significantly influence the extent to which policy goals are met. Lowi, Theodore J. “American Business, Public Policy, Case Studies, and Political Theory.” World Politics 16 (July 1964): 667–715. â•… Lowi introduces the distributive–redistributive–regulatory policy typology in this article.

317

318 References ———. The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States. 2d ed. New York: W.W. Norton, 1979. Majone, Giandomenico. Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989. March, James G., and Herbert A. Simon. Organizations. New York: Wiley, 1958. Martin, Margaret E., Martin R. Frankel, Noreen Goldman et al. “Report of the ASA Technical Panel on the Census Undercount.” American Statistician 38, no. 4 (1984): 252–56. May, Peter J. “Reconsidering Policy Design: Policies and Publics.” Journal of Public Policy 11, no. 2 (1990): 187–206. â•… Peter May discusses the policy design implications of “policies without publics”—that is, policy for which there is little or no public demand or mobilization to cause policy to be made, such as policies intended to mitigate natural hazards. ———. “Policy Learning and Failure.” Journal of Public Policy 12, no. 4 (1992): 331–54. Mazmanian, Daniel, and Paul Sabatier. Implementation and Public Policy. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989. McAdams, John C., and John R. Johannes. “Does Casework Matter? A Reply to Professor Fiorina.” American Journal of Political Science 25, no. 3 (1981): 581–604. McCann, Michael W. “Reform Litigation on Trial.” Law and Social Inquiry 17, no. 4 (1992): 715–43. McCloskey, Robert G. The American Supreme Court. 2d ed., ed. Sanford Levinson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994. â•… This is one of the best books on the Supreme Court, because it links the historical development of the United States to the legal doctrines that were being developed by the Court. The book proceeds chronologically, from the founding until 1960, This second edition, edited by Sanford Levinson, updates McCloskey’s original work with chapters on the Court and civil rights and other topics. McCool, Daniel C. Public Policy Theories, Models, and Concepts: An Anthology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995. â•… An anthology of classic readings in public policy that stands apart by including excellent introductory essays that place the readings in context and bring the theories up to date. McCullough, David G. Truman. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1992. McDougall, Walter A. The Heavens and the Earth: A Political History of the Space Age. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997. McFarland, Andrew. “Interest Groups and Theories of Power in America.” British Journal of Political Science 16 (1978): 129–47. McPherson, James H. Abraham Lincoln and the Second American Revolution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990. Meadows, Donella H., and Diana Wright. Thinking in Systems: A Primer. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green Pub., 2008. Meyer, Philip. The Vanishing Newspaper: Saving Journalism in the Information Age. 2d ed. Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 2009. Moore, Barrington. Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy; Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modern World. Boston: Beacon Press, 1966. Morris, Edmund. Theodore Rex. 1st ed. New York: Random House, 2001. Nakamura, Robert T. “The Textbook Policy Process and Implementation Research.” Policy Studies Journal 7, no. 1 (1987): 142–154. â•… Nakamura argues that the stages model or what he calls “the textbook policy process” as being unrealistic, because the process is not a step-by-step, orderly process. Neustadt, Richard E. Presidential Power and the Modern Presidents: The Politics of Leadership from Roosevelt to Reagan. New York: Free Press, 1990.

References Nice, David C., and Ashley Grosse. “The Evolution of Emergency Management in America: From a Painful Past to Promising but Uncertain Future.” In Handbook of Crisis and Emergency Management, ed. Ali Farazmand. New York: Marcel Dekker, 2001. Nickey, Neil. “Cable Wars.” Columbia Journalism Review 41, no. 5 (2003): 12–17. Nixon, Richard M. RN: The Memoirs of Richard Nixon, with a New Introduction. The Richard Nixon Library Edition. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1990. Olson, Mancur. The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971. â•… This is the classic book on why collective action—that is, joining and taking action in groups—is so difficult to achieve unless there are powerful incentives for group formation and action. This book serves as a reaction to the pluralist claim that people will often join groups to advance their claims and serve as counterweights to other interest groups. Osborne, David. Laboratories of Democracy: A New Breed of Governor Creates Models for National Growth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 1988. Ostrom, Elinor. “Institutional Rational Choice: An Assessment of the Institutional Analysis and Development Framework.” In Theories of the Policy Process, ed. Paul A. Sabatier. 2d ed. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2007. O’Toole, Laurence. “The Public Administrator’s Role in Setting the Policy Agenda.” In Handbook of Public Administration, edited by James L. Perry. San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 1989. ———. “Policy Recommendations for Multi-Actor Implementation: An Assessment of the Field.” Journal of Public Policy 6, no. 2 (1986): 181–210. Pellikaan, Huib, and Robert J. van der Veen, Environmental Dilemmas and Policy Design. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Peters, B. Guy. American Public Policy: Promise and Performance. Chappaqua, NY: Chatham House/Seven Rivers, 1999. â•… A public policy textbook, this book combines theory and the first half focuses on policy theory, with a series of case studies. Perhaps the best balance between theory and case studies in any undergraduate textbook. Phillips, Kevin P. The Politics of Rich and Poor: Wealth and the American Electorate in the Reagan Aftermath. New York: Random House, 1990. â•… Kevin Phillips, a political commentator long associated with Republican causes, surprised many people with this well documented discussion of the growing concentration of wealth at the top of society, and the growing wealth gap between the rich and poor. He argues that this gap will have significant political consequences. Plotnick, Robert D., and Richard F. Winters. “A Politico-Economic Theory of Income Redistribution.” The American Political Science Review 79, no. 2 (1985): 458–73. Pralle, Sarah B. “Venue Shopping, Political Strategy, and Policy Change: The Internationalization of Canadian Forest Advocacy.”Journal of Public Policy 23, no. 3 (2003): 233–60. ———. Branching Out, Digging In: Environmental Advocacy and Agenda Setting. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006. Pogue, Lloyd Welch, and John Marshall Pogue. Airline Deregulation, Before and After: What Next? National Air and Space Museum Occasional Paper Series, No. 2. Washington, DC: National Air and Space Museum, Smithsonian Institution, 1991. Pressman, Jeffery, and Aaron Wildavsky. Implementation. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973. â•… Still required reading in many courses on public policy and policy implementation, this book describes the problems that accompanied the implementation of economic development projects at the Port of Oakland and the Oakland International Airport. The authors find that implementation is made difficult by the “complexity of joint action.” Radin, Beryl. Beyond Machiavelli: Policy Analysis Comes of Age. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999.

319

320 References Reagan, Ronald, and Douglas Brinkley. The Reagan Diaries. New York: HarperCollins, 2007. Reid, Herbert G. “Review of John Gaventa, Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an Appalachian Valley.” Journal of Politics 43, no. 4 (1981): 1270–73. Reissman, Frank. “Full Employment Now?” Social Policy 29, no. 4 (1999): 4. Richards, Leonard L. Shays’s Rebellion: The American Revolution’s Final Battle. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2002. Ripley, Randall, and Grace Franklin. Congress, Bureaucracy, and Public Policy. 5th ed. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks-Cole, 1991. â•… This book adopts and extends on Lowi’s distributive–redistributive–regulatory policy typology to illustrate the relationships between Congress, the bureaucracy, and interest groups in the policy process. Robertson, David B., and Dennis R. Judd. The Development of American Public Policy: The Structure of Policy Restraint. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman and Company, 1989. â•… This book adopts a historical and structural analysis of the constitutional system to show how American government and politics were explicitly designed to restrain policy making, particularly when that policy making is supported by mass publics rather than by elites. Rodgers Jr., Harrell R. “Civil Rights and the Myth of Popular Sovereignty.” Journal of Black Studies 12, no. 1 (1981): 53–70. Romero, David W. “The Case of the Missing Reciprocal Influence: Incumbent Reputation and the Vote.” Journal of Politics 58, no. 4 (1996): 1198–1207. Rosenbaum, Walter A. Environmental Politics and Policy, 7th ed. Washington: CQ Press, 2008. Rosenberg, Randall. The Hollow Hope. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991. â•… A well researched, clearly argued, and very controversial book in which the author argues that the Supreme Court and the lower courts are not the powerful protector of civil rights and venue for policy change that many social movement leaders and lay people believe. Ryan, Neal. “Unraveling Conceptual Developments in Implementation Analysis.” Australian Journal of Public Administration 54, no. 1 (1995): 65–81. Sabatier, Paul A. “Top-Down and Bottom-Up Approaches in Implementation Research: A Critical Analysis and Suggested Synthesis.” Journal of Public Policy 6, no. 1 (1986): 21–48. ———. “An Advocacy Coalition Framework of Policy Change and the Role of Policy-Oriented Learning Therein.” Policy Sciences 21 (1988): 129–68. ———. “Political Science and Public Policy.” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991): 138–143. ———. “Toward Better Theories of the Policy Process.” PS: Political Science and Politics 24, no. 2 (1991): 144–56. Sabatier, Paul A., ed. Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1999. Sabatier, Paul A., and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith. Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1993. â•… All these works by Paul Sabatier contain efforts to advance the sophistication and usefulness of policy theory. Sabatier’s most important contribution to policy studies is his Advocacy Coalition Framework, which has been advanced, tested, and refined for over ten years. At the same time, Sabatier, in his PS articles, seeks to locate the Advocacy Coalition Framework in context with other models of the process. Salamon, L.S., ed. Beyond Privatization: The Tools of Government Action. Washington, DC: Urban Institute, 1989. Salamon, L.S., and Michael S. Lund. “The Tools Approach: Basic Analytics,” In Beyond Privatization: The Tools of Government Action, ed. Lester M. Salamon. Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1989. Salamon, L.S., “The New Governance and the Tools of Public Action: An Introduction.” In The Tools of Government: A Guide to the New Governance, ed. Lester M. Salamon. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002.

References Salamon, L.S. and Odus V. Elliott. The Tools of Government: A Guide to the New Governance. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. Sappington, David Edward Michael. Principles of Regulatory Policy Design. World Bank, Office of the Vice President, 1994. Schachter, Hindy Lauer. Reinventing Government or Reinventing Ourselves: The Role of Citizen Owners in Making a Better Government. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1997. Schattschneider, E.E. The Semisovereign People. Hinsdale, IL: The Dryden Press, 1975. Schiavo, Mary. Flying Blind, Flying Safe. New York: Avon Books, 1997. Schlesinger, Arthur M. The Imperial Presidency. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1973. â•… This book is very much a reflection of the times in which it was written. Schlesinger, writing during the Vietnam and Watergate years, argued that the presidency had gained so much power that it was becoming “imperial” and therefore answerable only to itself. Experience with later administrations has tempered the belief that the presidency is unfettered by other institutions. Schneider, Anne, and Helen Ingram. “The Social Construction of Target Populations: Implications for Politics and Policy.” American Political Science Review 87, no. 2 (1992): 334–48. ———. “Behavioral Assumptions of Policy Tools.” Journal of Politics 52 (May 1990): 510– 529. ———. Policy Design for Democracy. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997. Schulman, Paul R. “Nonincremental Policy Making: Notes toward an Alternative Paradigm.” American Political Science Review 69, no. 4 (December 1975): 1354–70. â•… Schulman argues that there are many instances where incremental policy making does not explain policy outcomes or cannot work to reach policy goals. He uses NASA’s mission to the moon, which started in 1961, as an example of nonincremental policy making. Senge, Peter M. The Fifth Discipline: The Art and Practice of the Learning Organization. Rev. and updated ed. New York: Doubleday/Currency, 2006. Shulman, Stuart W. “The Case against Mass E-mails: Perverse Incentives and Low Quality Public Participation in U.S. Federal Rulemaking.” Policy and Internet 1, no. 1. Available at http:// www.psocommons.org/policyandinternet/v011/iss1/art2. Smith, Kevin B., and Christopher W. Larimer. The Public Policy Primer. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2009. Steinberger, Peter J. “Typologies of Public Policy: Meaning Construction and the Policy Process.” Social Science Quarterly 61 (September 1980): 185–197. â•… This discusses a way of thinking about policy types that focuses on how participants in policy making attribute meanings to policies, rather than attempting to find objective attributes of policies. Stillman, Richard J. The American Bureaucracy. Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1996. â•… This is a clearly written and very thorough textbook on the structure and function of the bureaucracy. Unlike many treatments of bureaucracy, this book explains this important part of policy without bogging down in highly technical jargon. Stokey, Edith, and Richard Zeckhauser. A Primer for Policy Analysis. New York: W. W. Norton, 1978. â•… While showing its age, this book remains one of the most useful introductory texts in policy analysis. This book is a good complement to Wiemer and Vining’s book; Stokey and Zeckhauser rely somewhat less on economic explanations than do Weimer and Vining. Stone, Deborah A. “Causal Stories and the Formation of Policy Agendas.” Political Science Quarterly 104, no. 2 (1989): 281–300. ———. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making. Rev. ed. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 2002. â•… Deborah Stone directly takes on the rationalist approach to policy analysis—she calls this the “rationality project”—in this book. She compares the rationalist notions of society as a market

321

322 References with a more politically and sociologically useful idea of society as the “polis” to illustrate why there are so many paradoxes in politics and policy making that cannot be “rationally” explained. Strahan, Randall, and Daniel J. Palazzolo. “The Gingrich Effect.” Political Science Quarterly 119, no. 1 (2004): 89–90. Strauss, Leo, and Joseph Cropsey. History of Political Philosophy. 3d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1987. Szatmary, David P. Shays’ Rebellion: The Making of an Agrarian Insurrection. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1980. Tallon Jr., James R., and Lawrence D. Brown. “Who Gets What? Devolution of Eligibility and Benefits in Medicaid.” In Medicaid and Devolution: A View from the States, ed. Frank J. Thompson and John J. DiIulio Jr. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, 1998. Thomas, Janet. The Battle in Seattle: The Story Behind and Beyond the WTO Demonstrations. Golden, CO: Fulcrum, 2000. Torenvlied, Rene. “Political Control of Implementation Agencies.” Policy Sciences 8, no. 1 (1996): 25–57. Tufte, Edward R. The Visual Display of Quantitative Information. Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1983. ———. Envisioning Information. Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1990. ———. Visual Explanations. Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1997. ———. The Cognitive Style of Powerpoint. Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 2003. â•… All of Tufte’s books are beautifully designed and printed books on information graphics. They are useful to anyone who wants to honestly present quantitative information, and are useful tools for defense against those who fail, by design or accident, to honestly convey statistical information. Van Horn, Carl. Policy Implementation in the Federal System: National Goals and Local Implementers. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1979. Van Horn, Carl E., and Donald S. Van Meter. “The Implementation of Intergovernmental Policy.” In Public Policy Making in a Federal System, ed. Charles O. Jones and Robert D. Thomas. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1976. Vig, Norman, and Michael Kraft. Environmental Policy: New Directions for the Twenty-First Century. 7th ed. Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2010. Walker, Jack L. “Setting the Agenda in the U.S. Senate: A Theory of Problem Selection.” British Journal of Political Science 7 (1977): 423–45. â•… Walker argues that the United States Senate’s agenda is heavily influenced by the scarcity of time to deal with every issue. In particular, so many routine or crisis-driven items reach the Senate’s agenda that it is very difficult for the Senate to tackle its “chosen problems.” Weber, Max. “Bureaucracy.” In From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press, 1973. Weimer, David Leo, and Aidan R. Vining. Policy Analysis: Concepts and Practice. 4th ed. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall. â•… This book is a standard text on policy analysis, with excellent examples and explanations. Like most policy analysis texts, this book is firmly grounded in economics. Wholey, Joseph S., Harry P. Hatry, and Kathryn E. Newcomer. Handbook of Practical Program Evaluation. San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 1994. Wildavsky, Aaron, and Naomi Caiden. The New Politics of the Budgetary Process. 4th ed. New York: Addison Wesley Publishing Co., 2000. Wilson, James Q. Bureaucracy. New York: Basic Books, 1989. ———. Political Organizations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995. In both Bureaucracy and Political Organizations, Wilson outlines a way of categorizing policies based on the distribution of costs and benefits associated with a policy. Wilson, Woodrow. “The Study of Administration.” Political Science Quarterly 2, no. 2 (1887): 197–222.

References Wood, B. Dan. “Federalism and Policy Responsiveness: The Clean Air Case.” Journal of Politics 53, no. 3 (1991): 851–859. Woodward, Bob. The Agenda: Inside the Clinton White House. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1994. ———. Bush at War. New York: Simon & Schuster, 2002. ———. The Choice. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1996. ———. The Commanders. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1991. Woodward, Bob, and Scott Armstrong. The Brethren: Inside the Supreme Court. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1979. Woon, Jonathan. “Change We Can Believe In? Using Political Science to Predict Policy Change in the Obama Presidency.” PS: Political Science & Politics 42, no. 2 (2009): 329–33. Yiannakis, Diana Evans. “The Grateful Electorate: Casework and Congressional Elections.” American Journal of Political Science 25, no. 3 (1981): 568–580. Zahariadis, Nikolaos. “To Sell or Not to Sell? Telecommunications Policy in Britain and France.” Journal of Public Policy 12, no. 4 (1993): 355–76. Zukin, Cliff, Scott Keeter, Molly Andolina, Krista Jenkins, and Michael X. Delli Carpinin. A New Engagement?: Political Participation, Civic Life, and the Changing American Citizen. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006.

323

This page intentionlly left blank

Index

Bold numbers indicate pages with Key Term definitions Abortion policy, 141 Accountability problem, 117–21 Adams, Samuel, 5 Administrative Procedures Act (1946), 28, 206–7, 219 Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF), 157, 184–85, 270–72 defined, 271, 298 graphic illustration, 299f policy process models, 298–300 African Americans bus boycott (Alabama, 1955), 85, 141 Jim Crow laws, 67, 84 March on Washington (1963), 85–86, 141 population growth, 29, 31f school desegregation, 9, 53, 82, 85, 86, 122, 141, 186, 203 segregation policy, 67, 84, 122 Selma-Montgomery march (1965), 85, 86 slavery, 61–62, 66, 83–84 voting rights, 84–85, 86 See also Civil rights movement Agenda, 168, 169–73 Agenda setting, 168 condition, 170 elite theory, 168–69, 177 enactment, 170 hidden agenda, 169–70, 191 levels of agenda universe, 170–72 decision agenda, 172 institutional agenda, 172

Agenda setting levels of (continued) overview, 171f systemic agenda, 170, 171–72 media, 149–50, 181–83, 187, 191–92 pluralism, 168–69, 177 political power dimensions of, 174–76 focusing event, 180–83, 185 group coalescence, 184–87 group mobilization, 176–81 indicator, 179–80, 185 litigation, 186 policy monopoly, 177 power deficits, 178–79 symbols, 177 social constructionism, 187–95 aggregate data, 192–95 causal story, 192, 193t conditions, 189–90 public goods, 188 symbols, 190–92 study guide additional reading, 198–99 case study, 181–83 discussion questions, 196–98 key terms, 196 window of opportunity, 178 Agenda universe, 170–72 Aggregate data agenda setting, 192–95 outlier, 195 Aging population age-group population, 30f

325

326 Index Aging population (continued) demographic trends, 28–29, 30f policy implications, 33–34 population (1960–2007), 29f population growth (1960–2007), 30f Airline industry deregulation, 72–73 public interest, 119–20, 121 regulation policy, 216 regulatory process, 206–7 security policy, 208, 209, 240, 241, 278–82 Air Transport Association (ATA), 135, 206–7 Albright, Madeleine, 33 Alexander v. Holmes County Board of Education (1969), 86 American Association of Retired Persons (AARP), 135, 136 American Automobile Association (AAA), 136 American Bankers Association, 213 American Bar Association, 138 American Enterprise Institute, 143 American Medical Association (AMA), 138 American Petroleum Institute, 135 Amtrak, 223 Anecdotal evidence in policy process, 17t policy studies, 293, 294t Antitrust policy, 66, 67–68, 217 Argument, 14–17 Articles of Confederation, 62, 80 Articles of Impeachment, 108 Asian Americans cultural assimilation, 34–35 population growth, 31f, 35–36 Astroturf group, 142 Atomic Energy Commission (AEC), 301 Aviation and Transportation Security Act (2001), 279–82 Backward mapping, 268–70 Banking industry, 62, 67, 74 Barron v. Baltimore (1832), 68 Behaviorism, 92–93 Bernstein, Carl, 144

Bill of Rights, 68–69, 235 Bills, 94–95, 98, 99f, 100 private bills, 95t public bills, 95t Black box, 27 systems model illustration, 27t Block grant, 79, 229 Blogs, 150–51 Bonneville Power Authority (BPA), 70 Bottom-up approach, 268–72 Bounded rationality, 255–57 Brazil, 190 Brookings Institution, 143 Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, Kansas (1954/1955), 9, 53, 82, 85, 122, 141, 186, 203 Budget and Impoundment Act (1974), 72 Budget deficit, 43–44, 45f Budget surplus, 43, 45f Bureaucracy, 110–21 accountability problem, 117–21 budget growth (1981–2010), 112, 115f federal civilian employees (1981–2010), 112, 115f free riders, 116 government agency role, 116–17 government employee growth (1981–2010), 112, 115f government employees (1992–2006), 112, 114f government outlays (1940–2014), 112, 113f, 114f public goods, 116–17 Bureaucratic discretion, 118 Bureaucratic politics model, 258 Bush, George H. W., 40–41, 258 Bush, George W., 33, 105 approval ratings, 40–41, 107 government decentralization, 73–74 gun control, 110 Canada, 60 Car Allowance Rebate System (CARS), 105 Carter, Jimmy, 72–73 Case law, 53 Casework, 96 Cato Institute, 143

Index Causal story, 192, 193t Causal theory, 231t, 236, 240, 241–43 Central Intelligence Agency (CIA), 72, 237–38 Cheney, Dick, 105 Chevron, 66 China, 60 Civil Aeronautics Administration, 70 Civil Aeronautics Board (CAB), 70, 216 Civilian Conservation Corps, 69 Civil liberties, 208, 237–39 Civil Rights Act 1866, 66, 84 1870, 84 1871, 84 1875, 66, 84 1957, 85 1960, 85 1964, 86, 204 Civil Rights Cases, 84, 122 Civil rights movement fragmentation, 82 group coalescence, 186, 187 lobbying, 140–41 redistributive policy, 214 social movements, 136–37 stability, 83–87 state activism, 66–67 Civil War, 75 Civil War Amendments, 66, 84 Classical liberalism, 10 Clayton Act (1914), 67–68 Clean Water Act, 241 Clientelism, 216–18 Clinton, Bill, 73, 78, 104, 110, 160, 214 Clinton, Hillary, 33 Code of Federal Regulations (CFR), 53, 204–5, 207 defined, 205 Coercive policy tool, 246, 252 Columbine High School, Colorado, 110, 173 Commerce clause, 65 Committees, 98, 99f, 100, 100t Common Cause, 137 Common pool resource, 301 Comparative Public Policy, 14t

327 Competitive regulatory policy, 211t, 212–13 Concurrent resolutions, 95t Condition, 170, 189–90 Congress approval ratings, 41, 42f bills, 94–95, 98, 99f, 100 private bills, 95t public bills, 95t casework, 96 committees, 98, 99f, 100, 100t committee chair, 100 concurrent resolutions, 95t constitutional powers, 63, 64t, 65 decentralization of, 102–3 field hearings, 97 filibuster, 81 House speaker, 98 joint resolutions, 95t legislative activities, 54, 94–98, 99t, 100 legislative branch, 93–106 critiques of, 100–102 oversight function, 54, 96–97 party control (1994–2008), 103–5 policy evaluation, 54 policy making implications, 106 political parties, 98, 103–5, 142–43 pork-barrel spending, 210, 212 public hearings, 96–97 reelection, 101–2 regulatory process, 99f separation of powers, 28, 61, 78–79, 81–82 structural organization, 97–98, 100 study guide additional reading, 125–27 case study, 103–5 discussion questions, 123–25 key terms, 123 symbolic law, 94 Congressional Budget Office, 54, 107 Congressional Research Service, 54, 97 Congress of Racial Equality (CORE), 85 Conservatism policy typologies, 223–24 political power, 178–79 social movements, 137 think tanks, 143

328 Index Conspiracy theory, 191–92 Consumers Union, 135 Contract with America, 103–5, 142 Cost-benefit analysis clientelism, 216–18 decision-making models, 255 policy typology, 215–18 Council of Economic Advisors, 108 C-SPAN, 97, 148 DARE (Drug Abuse Resistance Education), 18–20, 54, 220, 252 Decentralization of Congress, 102–3 government era, 72–75 policy networks, 159 Decision agenda, 172 Decision-making models, 253–59 bounded rationality, 255–57 bureaucratic politics model, 258 cost-benefit analysis, 255 garbage can model, 257–58 government politics model, 259 incrementalism, 255–57 normative model, 253–254 positive model, 253–254 rational actor model, 258 rational comprehensive decision making, 254–55 standard operating procedure (SOP), 258 study guide additional reading, 260–61 case study, 237–39 discussion questions, 259–60 key terms, 259 Declaration of Independence, 80 Demographers, 29 Demographic trends, 28–36 Depression, 38 Devolution, 79 Dewey, John, 5 Dinh, Viet, 238 Discipline, 13, 15t Distributive policy, 210, 211t, 217–18 interest group liberalism, 212 Divided power era, 62–63, 65 Double-loop learning, 275

Drug abuse prevention policy, 18–20, 54, 158–58, 220, 252 Economic environment budget deficit, 43–44, 45f budget surplus, 43, 45f gross domestic product (GDP), 43, 44, 45f, 46 income distribution, 46, 48f Keynesian economics, 43 laissez-faire economics, 67 national debt, 43–44 systems model, 42–49 tax policy, 44, 46 transfer payments, 44, 46 Economic interest group, 137–39 Economic policy tool, 245, 246 Economics, 15t Education policy, 71, 74, 204, 269 achievement tests, 193–94 school desegregation, 9, 53, 82, 85, 86, 122, 141, 186, 203 school violence, 110, 173 Efficiency, 133, 233–34 Eisenhower, Dwight D., 70 Elastic clause, 65 Elections Congressional, 101–2 input-output model, 50 participation rate 1932–2004, 132f 1932–2008, 40f voter turnout, 131–33 Elementary and Secondary Education Act (ESEA), 71 Elite theory agenda setting, 168–69, 177 defined, 169 Enactment, 170 Energy policy, 266, 277, 301 Enlightenment, 5, 291–92 Environmental policy, 9, 71, 219–20, 241, 242–43, 255, 293–94 Environmental Protection Agency (EPA), 71 European Union (EU), 46–47, 48f, 49 Evaluation, 54 Evans, Lane, 221

Index Executive Office approval ratings, 40–41, 42f impeachment, 108 media role, 107 organizational structure, 106–7 pocket veto, 106 policy making activities, 106–10 separation of powers, 28, 61, 78–79, 81–82 study guide additional reading, 125–27 discussion questions, 123–25 key terms, 123 veto, 106 ExxonMobil, 66 Exxon Valdez, 181, 241 Facebook, 150, 151 Fair Employment Practices, 85 Fair Housing Act, 86 Family planning services, 236, 240 Farmer, James, 85–86 Federal Aviation Administration (FAA), 119–20, 121, 206–7, 240, 241, 278–82 Federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI), 72, 237, 239 Federal Communications Commission (FCC), 70, 120, 216 Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation (FDIC), 70 Federal Home Administration (FHA), 70 Federalism, 28, 61, 78–79 Federal Register, 53, 204–5, 207 Federal Reserve Act (1913), 62 Federal Reserve Bank, 65, 67 Federal Reserve System, 67 Field hearing, 97 Fifteenth Amendment, 66, 84, 86 Fifth Amendment, 68–69, 235 Filibuster, 81 First Amendment, 9, 60–61, 139, 171, 222 Flag desecration, 221–22 Focusing event agenda setting, 180–83, 185 policy design, 231 terrorism, 181–83 Food packaging industry, 68

329 Forward mapping, 270–72 Foucault, Michel, 6 Fourteenth Amendment, 66, 69, 84 Fourth Amendment, 208, 235–36 Fragmentation, 81–82 France, 75 Freedmen’s Bureau, 66 Freedom of Information Act, 29, 156–57, 219 Free rider, 116 Free riding, 116 Full Employment and Balanced Growth Act (1978), 241 Garbage can model, 257–58 Gay, bisexual, lesbian and transgendered (GBLT) agenda-setting, 170 same-sex marriage, 141, 214 social movements, 136–37 General Electric, 219–20 Germany, 75–76, 256–57 Gibbons v. Ogden (1824), 65 GI Bill, 70 Gingrich, Newt, 98, 103–5 Google, 184 Gore, Al, 278 Government Accountability Office (GAO), 54, 97, 107 Government in the Sunshine Act (1976), 219 Government politics model, 259 Grassroots organization, 134–35, 159 Great Britain, 75, 256–57 Great Depression, 69 Great Society, 71, 178 Gross domestic product (GDP) aggregate data, 194 budget deficits/debt (1940–2014), 45f economic environment, 43, 44, 45f, 46 economic indicator, 179–80 government outlays (1940–2014), 112, 113f 1930–2007, 43f Gun control policy, 110 Hamilton, Alexander, 5, 65, 121 Hastert, Dennis, 98, 105

330 Index Hayes, Rutherford B., 66–67, 84 Haymarket Riot (Chicago, 1886), 66 Head Start, 71 Health care policy, 62, 73, 78, 104, 105, 108, 171, 186–87 Helplessness-and-control story, 191 Heritage Foundation, 143 Hidden agenda, 169–70, 191 Hispanics, 29, 31f Hobbes, Thomas, 5 Holidays, 221 Homeland security, 74 Homeland Security Act, 269 House Un-American Activities Committee (HUAC), 70 Hurricane Katrina (2005), 97, 230 Ideas, 10 Ideological stability, 76–77 Immigration policy, 34, 240 Impeachment, 108 Implementation. See Policy implementation Inc. Fund, 141 Income distribution aggregate data, 194–95 economic environment, 46 global comparison, 48f median family income (1949–2007), 33f redistributive policy, 214–15 Incorporation doctrine, 69 Incrementalism decision-making models, 255–57 defined, 256 Indicator agenda setting, 179–80, 185, 192–95 aggregate data, 192–95 policy design, 230–31 Individual citizens, 131–34 Industrial Revolution, 65 Initiative, 50 Input-output model, 26–27, 49–53 inputs, 49–53 election results, 50 interest group, 52 media, 52–53 public communications, 51

Input-output model inputs (continued) public opinion, 50–51 outputs evaluation, 54 laws, 53 oversight, 54 Institutional agenda, 172 Institutional analysis and development (IAD) common pool resources, 301 graphic illustration, 304f policy process models, 301–5 satisficing, 302 Institutional interest group, 137 Institutionalism, 92 neoinstitutionalism, 93 Institution defined, 92–93 Instrumental policy learning, 276 Interest group, 134 Astroturf group, 142 economic interest group, 137–39 grassroots organization, 134–35, 159 input-output model, 52 institutional interest group, 137 lobbying, 139–41 membership group, 137 mobilization, 136–37, 141–42 peak association, 135–36 protest marches, 141–42 public interest group, 135, 137–42 social movement, 136–37 special interest group, 135, 191–92 types of, 137–42 venue shopping, 141 Interest group liberalism, 212 Intermarriage, 34–35 Internet, 150–54, 159–60 adoption trends (2000–2009), 152f news sites (2008), 153f Interstate Commerce Commission, 66 Interstate Highway System, 70–71 Iran, 60 Iran-Contra scandal, 73 Iron triangle, 155–58 defined, 156 Issue network, 103, 157 Italy, 75, 256–57

Index Japan, 75, 256–57 Jay, John, 5 Jefferson, Thomas, 5, 65 Jeffords, Jim, 105 Jim Crow laws, 67, 84 Johnson, Lyndon, 38, 71, 85, 86, 178 Joint Committee on Atomic Energy (JCAE), 301 Joint resolutions, 95t Judicial review, 121 Judiciary, 121–23 separation of powers, 28, 61, 78–79, 81–82 study guide additional reading, 125–27 discussion questions, 123–25 key terms, 123 See also U.S. Supreme Court Kemp, Jack, 258 Kennedy, John F., 256 Kennedy, Robert F., 38 Keynesian economics, 43 King, Martin Luther, Jr., 38, 85–86, 141, 221 Labor force demographic trends, 31–34 federal civilian employees (1981–2010), 112, 115f government employee growth (1981–2010), 112, 115f government employees (1992–2006), 112, 114f median family income (1949–2007), 33f participation rate (1975–2008), 32f policy implications, 33–34 regulation policy, 67, 68, 69, 85, 217 unemployment rate, 46, 47f, 241 women’s participation, 31–33 workplace safety, 191–92 Laissez-faire economics, 67 Laws case law, 53 enactment, 170 input-output model, 53 regulations, 53 regulatory process, 99f, 204–5, 206–7

331 Laws (continued) statute law, 53, 94 symbolic law, 94 Legislative branch. See Congress Legislative intent, 54 Lewinsky, Monica, 104 Lewis, John, 85–86 Liberalism interest group liberalism, 212 policy typologies, 223–24 political power, 178 Lieberman, Joseph, 74, 160 Lincoln, Abraham, 5 Litigation, 186 See also U.S. Supreme Court Lobbying, 139–41 Lochner v. New York (1905), 68, 69 Locke, John, 5, 10 Logrolling, 156 Machiavelli, Niccolò, 5 Madison, James, 5, 78–79, 134 Mapp v. Ohio (1961), 208 Marbury v. Madison (1803), 121 Marriage intermarriage, 34–35 same-sex marriage, 141, 214 Marshall, Thurgood, 85, 141 Marx, Karl, 5 Material policy, 220, 221–22 McCain, John, 215 McCarthy, Joseph, 70 Media agenda setting, 149–50, 181–83, 187, 191–92 Executive Office role, 107 focusing event, 181–83 input-output model, 52–53 Internet, 150–54, 159–60 muckrakers, 144 newspapers, 144–45, 146f, 147, 181–83 pack journalism, 153–54 public interest, 120 radio, 148 regulation policy, 216 social media, 144 study guide additional reading, 164–65

332 Index Media study guide (continued) discussion questions, 162–64 key terms, 164–65 television, 147–48, 220 Membership group, 137 Michel, Robert, 104 Military policy, 72, 73, 247, 256–57 Mobil, 66 Mobilization agenda setting, 176–81 interest group, 136–37, 141–42 public interest, 133–34, 160–62 social movements, 136–37 Monopolies antitrust policy, 66, 67–68, 217 policy monopoly, 177 state activism era, 66 Montesquieu, 5 Mothers Against Drunk Driving (MADD), 158–59 MoveOn.org, 160 Muckraker, 68, 144 Narrative story, 191 National activism era, 69–71 National Aeronautics and Space Administration (NASA), 253, 256 National Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP), 85, 137 Legal Defense Fund, 85, 141 National Association of Manufacturers, 135, 213 National Association of Realtors, 136 National Center for Policy Analysis (NCPA), 143 National debt, 43–44 National Economic Council, 110 National Education Association, 135 National Environmental Policy Act (NEPA), 9, 71 National Industrial Recovery Act (NIRA), 69 National mood, 38–42 National Opinion Research Center, 50 National Rifle Association (NRA), 137 National security, 70 See also Terrorism

National Security Council, 108 National standards era, 71–72 National Transportation Safety Board (NTSB), 119–20, 121, 206–7, 241 Neoinstitutionalism, 93 New Deal, 69–70, 78, 178 New Federalism, 71–72 Newspapers, 144–45, 147 circulation (1940–2008), 146f terrorism coverage, 181–83 U.S. newspapers (1940–2008), 146f New Zealand, 190 NIMBY (Not in My Backyard), 186 Nixon, Richard New Federalism, 71–72 resignation, 108, 144 Watergate, 38, 102, 144–45 Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC (2000), 139 No Child Left Behind Act (2001), 74, 204, 269 Noncoercive policy tool, 246 Normative decision-making models, 253–254 policy studies direction, 288–89 North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), 70 “Notice of Proposed Rulemaking,” 205 Nuclear power, 277, 301 Obama, Barack approval rating, 105, 107 economic stimulus policy, 35–36 government decentralization, 74 health care policy, 78, 108, 186–87 policy overexposure, 109 racial attitudes toward, 35, 86 tax policy, 215 Occupational Safety and Health Act, 217 Occupational Safety and Health Administration (OSHA), 191–92, 217 Office of Technology Assessment (OTA), 107 Official actors bureaucracy, 110–21 Executive Office, 106–10 judiciary, 121–23

Index Official actors (continued) legislatures, 93–106 study guide additional reading, 125–27 case study, 103–5 discussion questions, 123–25 key terms, 123 See also Unofficial actors Oil Pollution Act (1990), 241 Oil spills, 181, 190, 241 O’Neill, Thomas, 98 Open public meeting laws, 28 Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD), 46–47, 48f, 49 Outcomes, 229–30, 232 Outlier, 195 Oversight, 54, 96–97 Pack journalism, 153–54 Paraguay, 190 Parks, Rosa, 85, 141 Peak association, 135–36 Peer review, 293 Pelosi, Nancy, 98, 103 Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act (1996), 104, 214 Pharmaceutical industry, 68 Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America, 138 Plessy v. Ferguson (1896), 67, 84, 122 Pluralism agenda setting, 168–69, 177 defined, 169 Pocket veto, 106 Policy, 9, 203 Policy community, 155–58 Policy design, 228, 238–43 causal theory, 231t, 236, 240, 241–43 elements of, 231t general concepts, 229–30 goals, 231t, 232–41 ambiguity in, 236, 240–41 conflict in, 234–41 efficiency of, 233–34 polis, 233–34

333 Policy design goals (continued) security versus liberty, 234–36, 237–39 outcomes, 229–30, 232 problems, 230–31 focusing event, 231 indicators of, 230–31 study guide additional reading, 260–61 case study, 237–39 discussion questions, 259–60 key terms, 259 Policy domain, 155 Policy environment, 27 economic environment, 42–49 political environment, 36–42 social environment, 28–36 structural environment, 28 systems model, 26–49 Policy failure, 272–75 case study, 278–82 explanations for, 274t Policy goal, 231t, 232–41 defined, 236 Policy implementation, 263–72 approaches to, 264–72 backward mapping, 268–70 bottom-up approach, 268–72 forward mapping, 270–72 strategic delay, 267, 271 street-level bureaucrat, 268–70 synthesis of, 270–72 top-down approach, 265–68, 270–72 resources for, 247, 252 study guide additional reading, 283–84 discussion questions, 282–83 key terms, 282 Policy learning, 275 double-loop learning, 275 instrumental policy learning, 276 organizational learning, 273–75 political learning, 276–77 single-loop learning, 274–75 social policy learning, 276 study guide additional reading, 283–84

334 Index Policy learning study guide (continued) discussion questions, 282–83 key terms, 282 Policy making history American constitutional order, 58–75 federalism, 61, 78–79 historical development, 61–75 decentralization era, 72–75 divided power era, 62–63, 65 national activism era, 69–71 national standards era, 71–72 state activism era, 66–69 policy restraint, 61–62 separation of powers, 61, 78–79, 81–82 stability, 75–87 study guide additional reading, 89 case study, 83–87 discussion questions, 88–89 key terms, 87 Policy monopoly, 177 venue shopping, 301 Policy network, 157 decentralization impact, 159 going public, 159–60 policy making access, 158–60 Policy process anecdotes in, 17t argument in, 14–17 classical liberalism, 10–11 Enlightenment, 5 ideas, 10 overview, 3–4 policy studies, 7, 12–13, 15t politics defined, 4–7 problems, 10 public interest, 10–11 public policy defined, 7–10 scientific evidence in, 14–20 study guide additional reading, 22–23 case study, 18–20 discussion questions, 21–22 key terms, 21 Policy process models, 296–305 Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF), 298–300

Policy process models (continued) input-output model, 26–27, 49–53 institutional analysis and development (IAD), 301–5 punctuated equilibrium, 300–301 stages model, 25–26 streams metaphor, 297–98 study guide additional reading, 307–8 discussion questions, 306–7 key terms, 306 systems model, 26–54 Policy process system economic environment, 42–49 input-output model, 27f, 49–54 inputs, 49–53 election results, 50 interest group, 52 media, 52–53 public communications, 51 public opinion, 50–51 outputs evaluation, 54 laws, 53 oversight, 54 political environment, 36–42 social environment, 28–36 stages model, 25–26 structural environment, 28 study guide additional reading, 56 discussion questions, 55 key terms, 55 systems model, 26–54 Policy regime, 158 Policy restraint, 61–62 Policy science, 288, 295–96 Policy stability, 76t, 77–78 Policy studies disciplinary areas, 13, 15t disciplinary development, 7 normative direction, 288–89 policy theory, 289–90, 295–96 positive direction, 288–89 professional journals, 14t public policy morphology, 13, 14t rationale for, 12–13 as science, 288–90

Index Policy studies (continued) as scientific endeavor, 287 scientific method, 238, 292 scientific theory, 12, 287–95 anecdotal evidence, 293, 294t peer review, 293 in policy process, 288 of policy process, 290–95 theoretical improvement, 295–96 theory defined, 289–90 study guide additional reading, 307–8 discussion questions, 306–7 key terms, 306 Policy subsystem, 103 See also Issue network; Policy network Policy tools, 243 characteristics of, 251t coercive policy, 246, 252 dimensions of, 243–47 automaticity, 245 centralization, 244–45 delivery system, 244 government activity, 244 economic model, 245, 246 noncoercive policy, 246 political model, 245–46 selection considerations administrative feasibility, 252 effectiveness, 252 implementation resources, 247, 252 political feasibility, 247 study guide additional reading, 260–61 case study, 237–39 discussion questions, 259–60 key terms, 259 types of, 243–47, 248–50t Policy typologies, 210 conservative policy, 223–24 cost-benefit analysis, 215–18 distributive policy, 210, 211t, 212, 217–18 liberal policy, 223–24 material policy, 220, 221–22 overview, 211t policy codification, 203–8 policy defined, 203

335 Policy typologies (continued) private goods, 220, 222–23 procedural policy, 219–20 public goods, 220, 222–23 redistributive policy, 211t, 213–15 regulatory policy competitive, 211t, 212–13 protective, 211t, 213 street-level bureaucrat, 206, 208 study guide additional reading, 226 case study, 206–7, 221–22 discussion questions, 225–26 key terms, 224 substantive policy, 219–20 symbolic policy, 220, 221–22 topical categories, 209–10 Polis, 233–34 Political environment Congressional approval ratings, 41, 42f election participation (1932–2008), 40f most-important-problem question, 36–38 national mood, 38–42 presidential approval ratings, 40–41, 42f right-track question, 38–39 systems model, 36–42 Political learning, 276–77 defined, 277 Political parties, 98, 103–5, 142–43 Political policy tool, 245–46 Political power, 174–87 Political science, 13, 15t Political stability, 77–81 Politics defined, 6 in policy process, 4–7 Pork-barrel spending, 210, 212 Positive decision-making models, 253–254 policy studies direction, 288–89 Post-Katrina Reform Act (2006), 97 Powell, Colin, 33 Presidency. See Executive Office Privacy Act (1974), 219 Private bills, 95t Private goods, 220, 222–23

336 Index Private interest group, 137 Problems agenda setting, 187–95 policy design, 230–31 policy process, 10 Procedural policy, 219–20 Professional journals, 14t Protective regulatory policy, 211t, 213 Public administration (PA), 15t Public bills, 95t Public communications, 51 Public goods, 116, 188 government agency role, 116–17 policy typologies, 220, 222–23 Public interest, 134 mobilization, 133–34, 160–62 policy process, 10–11 Public interest group, 135, 137–42 Public Interest Research Group (PIRG), 10, 137 Public opinion, 50–51, 133–34 Public policy defined, 7–10 policy studies, 15t Public Policy Analysis, 14t Public policy participants. See Official actors; Unofficial actors Public Policy Processes, 14t Public Policy Research, 14t Pullman Strike (1893), 66 Punctuated equilibrium, 300–301 Pure Food and Drug Act, 68 Racial/ethnic population demographic trends, 29, 31f, 34–36 immigration policy, 34, 240 intermarriage, 34–35 policy implications of, 34–36 political participation, 59 population growth, 29, 31f, 35–36 See also specific group Radio, 148 RAND Corporation, 143 Randolph, Philip A., 85–86 Rational actor model, 258 Rational choice theory, 302 Rational comprehensive decision making, 254–55

Rawls, John, 5 Rayburn, Sam, 102 Reagan, Ronald, 72–73, 98, 214 Recession, 38 Reconstruction, 66–67 Redistributive policy, 211t, 213–15 Referendum, 50 Regulations, 53 Regulatory policy competitive policy, 211t, 212–13 protective policy, 211t, 213 Regulatory process, 99f, 204–5, 206–7 Reid, Harry, 98 Rice, Condoleezza Rice, 33 Roe v. Wade (1973), 141 Roosevelt, Franklin Delano, 69–70, 78, 85 Roosevelt, Theodore, 66 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 5 Russia, 60 Russo-Japanese War, 75 Same-sex marriage, 141, 214 Satisficing, 302 Scholastic Assessment Test (SAT), 193–94 School policy. See Education policy; specific policy Scientific evidence case study, 18–20 in policy process, 14–17 Scientific method, 238, 292 Scientific theory, 12, 287–95 Second Amendment, 69 Secondat, Charles-Louis de, 5 Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC), 70 Separation of powers, 28, 61, 78–79, 81–82 Seventh Amendment, 69 Shay’s Rebellion, 63 Sherman Antitrust Act (1890), 66, 67–68, 217 Sierra Club, 135, 136 Single-loop learning, 274–75 Slavery, 61–62, 66, 83–84 Social constructionism, 187–95, 188 Social contract, 5

Index Social environment aging population, 28–29, 30f, 33–34 demographic trends, 28–36 labor force participation, 31–34 policy implications of, 33–36 racial/ethnic population, 29, 31f, 34–35–6 systems model, 28–36 Socialism, 171 Social media, 144 Social movement, 136–37 Social policy learning, 276 Social science, 13 Social Security, 70 Sociology, 15t Southern Christian Leadership Conference (SCLC), 85, 137, 141 Speaker of the House, 98 Special interest group, 135, 191–92 Stability, 75–87 fragmentation, 81–82 ideological stability, 76–77 overview, 76t policy stability, 76t, 77–78 political stability, 77–81 in power, 76t rationale for, 83 rules and norms, 81 strategic delay, 82 study guide additional reading, 89 case study, 83–87 discussion questions, 88–89 key terms, 87 Stages model, 25–26 Standard Oil Trust, 66 Standard operating procedure (SOP), 258 State activism era, 66–69 State Children’s Health Insurance Program (SCHIP), 105 State legislatures, 98 Statute law, 53, 94 Stock market indexes, 49 Strategic delay, 82, 267, 271 Streams metaphor graphic illustration, 298f policy process models, 297–98 window of opportunity, 297, 298f

337 Street-level bureaucrat, 205, 208 policy implementation, 268–70 Structural environment, 28 Student Nonviolent Coordinating Committee (SNCC), 85 Subgovernments, 154–58, 157, 217–18 Substantive policy, 219–20 Supplemental Nutrition Assistance Program (SNAP), 205 Swine flu (2009), 230–31 Symbol, 177 agenda setting, 190–92 conspiracy theory, 191–92 helplessness-and-control story, 191 narrative story, 191 Symbolic law, 94 Symbolic policy case study, 221–22 policy typologies, 220, 221–22 Systemic agenda, 170, 171–72 Systems model, 26–54 Systems thinking, 26 Tax expenditures, 46 Tax policy, 44, 46, 73, 214–15 Television, 147–48 C-SPAN, 97, 148 news viewing (1980–2006), 147f rating system, 220 Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF), 205 Tennessee Valley Authority (TVA), 70 Tenth Amendment, 63 Terrorism focusing event, 181–83 legislation, 74, 203, 204, 237–39, 269 political environment, 39–40 September 11, 2001, 39–40, 74, 181–83, 208, 237–39, 278–82 Texaco, 66 Texas v. Johnson (1989), 220 Think tank, 143 Thirteenth Amendment, 66, 84 Three Mile Island, 277 Tilden, Samuel, 84 Top-down approach, 265–68, 270–72 Trans-Alaska Pipeline, 71

338 Index Transfer payments, 44, 46 Transportation policy, 70–71, 223, 266 See also Airline industry Transportation Security Administration (TSA), 280–82 Twitter, 150 Typology, 210 Unemployment rate, 46, 241 1948–2009, 47f Uniform Crime Reports (UCR), 194 United States Code, 94, 204, 207 United States v. Mississippi Valley Generating Company (1961), 139 Unofficial actors, 93 individual citizens, 131–34 interest group, 134–42 media, 144–54 political parties, 142–43 research organizations, 143 study guide additional reading, 164–65 discussion questions, 162–64 key terms, 162 subgovernments, 154–58 iron triangle, 155–58 issue network, 157 logrolling, 156 policy community, 155–58 policy domain, 155 policy network, 157, 158–60 policy regime, 158 policy typologies, 217–18 think tanks, 143 See also Official actors Urban enterprise zone (UEZ), 258 Urban Institute, 143 U.S. Census Bureau, 28, 193, 194–95 U.S. Constitution American constitutional order, 58–75 historical development, 61–75 Article 1, Section 8, 63, 64t, 65 Bill of Rights, 68–69, 235 Civil War Amendments, 66, 84 commerce clause, 65 elastic clause, 65 Fifteenth Amendment, 66, 84, 86 Fifth Amendment, 68–69, 235

U.S. Constitution (continued) First Amendment, 9, 60–61, 139, 171, 222 Fourteenth Amendment, 66, 69, 84 Fourth Amendment, 208, 235–36 incorporation doctrine, 69 policy codification, 203–4 Second Amendment, 69 security versus liberty, 235–36, 237–39 Seventh Amendment, 69 Tenth Amendment, 63 Thirteenth Amendment, 66, 84 U.S. Department of Homeland Security, 74 U.S. Forest Service, 245, 247, 252, 266 U.S. National Park Service, 245 U.S. Postal Service, 117, 222–23 U.S. Supreme Court appointment reorganization, 69–70 rulings Alexander v. Holmes County Board of Education (1969), 86 Barron v. Baltimore (1832), 68 Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, Kansas (1954/1955), 82 Gibbons v. Ogden (1824), 65 Lochner v. New York (1905), 68, 69 Mapp v. Ohio (1961), 208 Marbury v. Madison (1803), 121 Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC (2000), 139 Plessy v. Ferguson (1896), 67, 84, 122 Roe v. Wade (1973), 141 Texas v. Johnson (1989), 220 United States v. Mississippi Valley Generating Company (1961), 139 USA Patriot Act (2001), 74, 203, 204, 237–39 USA Patriot Improvement and Reauthorization Act (2005), 238 Venue shopping, 141 agenda setting, 185 policy monopoly, 301 Veto, 106 Vietnam War, 38 Virginia Polytechnic Institute, 110

Index Voting rights, 84–85, 86 See also Elections Voting Rights Act (1965), 86, 204 War Powers Resolution (1973), 72 Washington, George, 5 Watergate, 38, 102, 144–45 Weber, Max, 5 Welfare policy, 79, 104, 205, 214 Whitewater scandal, 104 Wilikins, Roy, 85–86 Wilson, Woodrow, 5, 118, 121–22

339 Window of opportunity, 178 streams metaphor, 297, 298f Women labor force participation, 31–33 political participation, 59 Woodward, Robert, 144 World Trade Organization (WTO), 141–42 World War II, 38, 59, 70, 75–76, 256–57 Wright, Jim, 104 Young, Whitney, Jr., 85–86

About the Author Thomas A. Birkland teaches public policy in the Graduate School of Public Affairs at North Carolina State University, where he is the William T. Kretzer Professor of Public Policy. Before joining the NC State faculty, he was on the faculty of the Nelson A. Rockefeller College of Public Affairs at the University at Albany, State University of New York, where he was the director of the University’s Center for Policy Research. He also served for a year as a program officer at the National Science Foundation. His research interests are in environmental policy, agenda setting, policy change and learning, and the politics of extreme natural and human events. Before entering academia, Professor Birkland worked for the State of New Jersey in various capacities. His doctorate in political science is from the University of Washington in Seattle.

View more...

Comments

Copyright ©2017 KUPDF Inc.
SUPPORT KUPDF